Penalty structures and deterrence in a two-stage model: experimental evidence.
Anderson, Lisa R. ; Deangelo, Gregory ; Emons, Winand 等
Penalty structures and deterrence in a two-stage model: experimental evidence.
I. INTRODUCTION
Increasingly harsh penalties characterize traditional crimes such
as theft and murder, but also violations of environmental and labor
regulations, and tax evasion. This principle of escalating sanctions
based on offense history is so widely accepted that it is embedded in
many penal codes and sentencing guidelines. (1) Whether or not this
weakens deterrence is a question with important policy implications. In
a standard utility-maximizing framework, agents will commit first
offenses with sufficiently low penalties. Moreover, if the first offense
is not detected, agents will continue to commit offenses until they are
convicted of a crime. We present experimental evidence that is
consistent with this prediction with respect to first offenses.
Often there are compelling reasons to have an escalating penalty
structure (e.g., first-time offenders might have committed a crime by
accident). (2) But there are many enforcement situations with no obvious
justification for low penalties for first offenders. For example, a firm
that has defrauded customers out of large sums of money might be
expected to pay a fine equal to consumer harm, regardless of whether it
is the firm's first offense. Furthermore, there is recent evidence
that escalating sanctions are not always effective at deterring crime.
For example, Sloan et al. (2013) show that increasing penalties for
domestic violence do not result in reductions in future arrests and
convictions. In addition, Mastrobuoni and Rivers (2016) find that
incarcerated criminals discount the future at a much higher rate than
noncriminals, which implies that increasing penalties may not lead to
substantial decreases in recidivism.
The literature on optimal law enforcement follows the pioneering
work of Becker (1968). (3) However, Becker (1968) does not address the
issue of repeat offending. Multiperiod models of criminal enforcement
based on this standard economic approach generally find that the optimal
penalty structure is either flat or declining. (4) In this paper, we
study a two-period version of Becker's (1968) model in a lab
experiment to assess whether the declining or flat penalty structures
implied by theory lead to greater levels of deterrence than the commonly
used increasing penalty structures. (5) We are not aware of any other
experimental study that has addressed this question. (6)
We use the basic theoretical framework of Emons (2003,2004) to
motivate our experimental design. In a model where criminal acts are
strictly undesirable, he shows that greater deterrence is reached when
fines are declining over a two-period time horizon. This theoretical
result is in stark contrast to the practices embodied in penal codes. In
the model, agents live for two stages and may commit an offense in each
stage. (7) The agents are wealth constrained; increasing the fine for
the first offense means a reduction in the sanction for the second
offense and vice versa. The government seeks to minimize enforcement
cost. Since the probability of being detected for a first offense is
higher than the probability of being detected for two offenses, a high
penalty for the first offense is a more effective use of the scarce
(money penalty) resource. This result is consistent with Becker's
(1968) maximal fine result; in order to minimize enforcement cost, the
government uses the agent's entire wealth for sanctions in the
first stage. (8)
The model of Emons (2003) assumes risk-neutral agents; however,
other theoretical models have suggested individual risk preference may
play a role in the decision to commit a crime. Becker (1968) shows that
only risk-loving agents will be criminals under an efficient criminal
justice system. Friedman (1984) shows, however, that Becker's
result is driven by a corner solution where fines approach infinity, and
this is not realistic. Neilson and Winter (1997) note that if certain
assumptions about expected utility maximization are relaxed, it is
possible for offenders to be both risk averse and more sensitive to
changes in the certainty of punishment. Recently, Mungan and Klick
(2014, 2015) present theoretical models that show criminals do not
necessarily need to be risk loving.
We extend the Emons (2003) model to derive predictions for other
levels of risk tolerance. We experimentally elicit a measure of
individual's risk preference using the method of Holt and Laury
(2002). Although the predicted optimal strategy within a penalty
structure is generally consistent across most risk preferences, we do
find that the predicted optimal strategy changes across penalty
structures for subjects who are either risk loving or extremely risk
averse. We then test whether subjects in a specific risk category (e.g.,
risk loving or highly risk averse) are more or less likely to follow the
optimal strategy as predicted by theory. We find that extremely
risk-averse subjects are more likely to be consistent with theory while
risk-loving subjects are significantly less likely to follow predicted
behavior.
Recall that Emons (2003) finds that decreasing penalty structures
lead to a greater level of deterrence. Our experimental results
generally confirm these predictions. We find that decreasing penalty
structures result in higher deterrence than increasing or flat penalty
structures. However, the decreasing penalty structures have the highest
rate of repeat offenses, since the second offense has a relatively small
fine. We also perform analyses on the individual decision of whether to
commit the offense. In addition to finding greater levels of deterrence
when subjects are faced with declining penalty structures, we observe
greater offense levels when subjects are male, less risk averse, and
have committed offenses in previous rounds.
We also find that being caught under previous penalty structures
has a deterrent effect in the current penalty structure, even though the
probability of being caught and the fine are independent of previous
rounds. This suggests that subjects' perceptions about the risk of
being caught are influenced by previous detection. Lochner (2007)
reports a similar finding using survey-based data; specifically, young
men who engage in criminal behavior and are undetected revise their
likelihood of being detected downward while those detected revise their
probability upward.
In the next section, we present the model that we test. Section III
describes the experimental design; Sections IV, V, and VI present
results; and in the final section, we offer a discussion of our results
and conclude.
II. PARAMETERIZED MODEL
Agents have initial wealth, w= 10, and maximize expected utility by
making decisions in two stages. In each stage, an agent can engage in an
illegal activity with a monetary benefit, b = 2. The government seeks to
deter individuals from engaging in the illegal activity by choosing a
two-part fine structure of the format ([f.sub.1], [f.sub.2]). (9) The
first sanction, [f.sub.1], applies to the first-detected offense, and
the second sanction, [f.sub.2], applies to the second-detected offense.
The government cannot confiscate more than the agent's wealth, thus
[f.sub.1] + [f.sub.2] [less than or equal to] w. (10) Throughout the
experiment, we set [f.sub.1] + [f.sub.2] = 10 so as to be consistent
with Emons (2003). Moreover, the government sets the level of detection
that determines the probability that an offense will be detected, p =
1/3. (11) Since we hold p and the overall level of the fines constant,
any variation in observed behavior (i.e., the decision to commit) may be
attributed to whether fines are increasing or decreasing.
To derive the optimal decision for each fine structure, we compare
expected utility levels associated with all possible strategy sets,
([a.sub.1], [a.sub.2]), where [a.sub.1] represents the action taken by
the agent in the first stage and [a.sub.2] represents the action taken
by the agent in the second stage. We let ([a.sub.1], [a.sub.2]) be
represented by 0 if the agent does not engage in the illegal activity
and 1 if the agent does engage in the illegal activity. Thus, there are
four possible strategy sets to consider that are not history dependent:
(0, 0), (1, 1), (0, 1), and (1, 0). The agent also can choose between
two history-dependent strategies. First, she commits the criminal act in
stage 1 and then commits the criminal act in stage 2 only if she is not
detected in stage 1. We call this strategy (1, [1]not detected;
0|other-wise]). Alternatively, she commits the act in stage 1, and then
commits the act in stage 2 only if she is detected in stage 1. We call
this strategy (1, [0|not detected; 1|otherwise]). (12)
Emons (2003) assumes that agents are risk neutral. However, we know
from a plethora of experimental studies that, on average, subjects tend
to be slightly risk averse. (13) For this reason, we generalize risk
preferences by assuming constant absolute risk aversion. Following Holt
and Laury (2002), let
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],
where x denotes income and r measures risk aversion: for r < 0
the agent is risk loving, for r = 0 she is risk neutral, and for r >
0, she is risk averse. The following set of equations describes the
expected utilities for all possible strategy sets ([a.sub.1], [a.sub.2])
(1) E [U (0,0)] = U (w)
(2) E[U(1,1)] = [p.sup.2]U(w + 2b - [f.sub.1] - [f.sub.2]) + 2p(1 -
p) U (w + 2b - [f.sub.1]) + [(1 - p).sup.2] U (w + 2b)
(3) E[U(0,1)1 = E[U(1, 0)] = pU(w + b - [f.sub.1]) + (1 - p)(w + b)
(4) E [U (1, (1 |not detected; 0| otherwise))] = pU (w + b -
[f.sub.1]) + (1 - p) pU (w + 2b - [f.sub.1]) + [(1 - p).sup.2] U (w +
2b)
(5) E[U(1, (0|notdetected; 1 |otherwise))] = [p.sup.2]U (w + 2b -
[f.sub.1] - [f.sub.2]) +(1 - p)U(w + b) + (1 - p)pU (w + 2b - [f.sub.1])
Note from Equation (1) that an agent who never plans to commit an
offense will not earn the benefit, and will not pay any fines. Hence,
her expected utility is her initial wealth, adjusted for her risk
preference. For example, if she is risk neutral, then r = 0 and expected
utility is equal to wealth. Also note from Equation (3) that if an agent
plans to commit an offense in one stage only, expected utility does not
vary depending on whether the offense is committed in the first or
second stage. In this case, with probability p, the offense will be
detected, and the agent will earn her initial wealth (w) plus the
benefit of committing the offense (b) minus the fine for being detected
for a first offense ([f.sub.1]). And with probability 1 -p, the offense
will not be detected, and the agent will earn her initial wealth plus
the benefit of committing the offense. The expected utilities for
strategies that involve multiple offenses or contingent strategies are
less intuitive because of compound probabilities. Following from this
set of equations, Table 1 shows the predicted optimal strategy for each
penalty structure over a range of risk aversion. We chose the
risk-tolerance categories in Table 1 to show the points where the
optimal strategy for a particular penalty structure changes with risk
tolerance.
Note from the first column of Table 1 that agents will always
commit an offense when the penalty is $1 regardless of risk preference,
since the benefit ($2) exceeds the penalty ($1). In general, Table 1
shows that the penalty structures with decreasing fines achieve higher
deterrence, as indicated by the (0, 0) optimal strategy sets, than the
constant or increasing fine schemes. This is even more pronounced for
risk-averse agents. Recall that the model assumes rational
forward-looking agents who view each stage within a penalty structure as
interrelated; whether an agent offends in the first stage depends on the
fine for the second offense. This forward-looking behavior is a key
assumption of the model for the following reason. The agent can only be
apprehended for a second crime after she has already been apprehended
for a first crime, meaning that the agent pays the first sanction with
probability 1/3 and the second sanction with probability 1/9. Since
paying the first fine is more likely than paying the second one,
shifting resources from the second to the first sanction increases
deterrence. (14) Table 1 also shows that even with relatively high
levels of risk aversion, the model predicts that some offenses will be
committed in the schemes with increasing sanctions. The constant fine
scheme leads to the highest level of predicted offenses and is also the
most sensitive to risk tolerance.
III. EXPERIMENTAL DESIGN
We conducted 35 experimental sessions at the College of William and
Mary in Virginia, USA. Participants were recruited from oncampus
advertisements to participate in paid economics experiments. A total of
367 undergraduate students participated in the experiment and no person
was permitted to participate in more than one session. The number of
subjects in each session ranged from 4 to 14, and sessions lasted
approximately 45 minutes. Subjects began each session by completing the
Holt and Laury (2002) lottery choice experiment using the Internet-based
Veconlab website. (15)
After completing the lottery choice experiment to elicit a measure
of individual risk-aversion, subjects completed another computerized
experiment that was programmed and administered using z-tree
(Fischbacher 2007). The experiment was divided into five periods, with
each period corresponding to a different enforcement regime (i.e., fine
structure). (16) Subjects were endowed with $10 at the beginning of each
period, and they faced two decision-making stages within the period. In
a context-free treatment, subjects could "take a chance" or
not. Every time a subject chose to take a chance, she earned an
additional $2 but she also faced a 1 in 3 chance of being
"checked" and financially penalized. Thus, a subject could
earn an additional $4 but could also pay two separate fines each period.
Subjects received feedback about whether or not they were checked after
every decision made, regardless of whether or not they took a chance.
(17) The complete instructions for the context-free experiment are
available in the Appendix. Instructions for the lottery choice
experiment and all version of the deterrence experiment are available
upon request.
All subjects made decisions for each of five different enforcement
regimes denoted (1,9), (3,7), (5,5), (7,3), and (9,1), where the first
number is the fine associated with the first-detected offense and the
second number is the fine for the second-detected offense within a given
period. At the beginning of each period, subjects were told the relevant
fines for the two stages in that period, but they were not told fines
for future periods. In every decision-making period, subjects were asked
what decisions they planned to make before they committed to the actual
decisions that affected their earnings; below we refer to these
responses as the subjects' stated strategies as opposed to the
observed behavior with actual earnings. In the discussion that follows,
we refer to the enforcement regimes with a higher fine for the second
offense as increasing fine regimes (i.e., (1,9) and (3,7)) and the
regimes with a higher fine for the first offense as decreasing fine
regimes (i.e., (7,3) and (9,1)).
To control for possible order effects, there were two treatments
that differed in the order in which enforcement regimes were presented
to subjects. Approximately half of the subjects saw the five regimes in
the order treatment presented above, with relatively low first-offense
fines in periods 1 and 2. The other subjects saw the five regimes in the
following order treatment: (9,1), (7,3), (5,5), (3,7), and (1,9). To
avoid wealth effects, subjects were told that one of the five periods
would be randomly chosen for payment at the end of the experiment.
Subject earnings averaged $10.54 for the deterrence experiment.
IV. CONSISTENCY OF BEHAVIOR WITH THEORY
In this section, we first focus on the correlation between
theoretical predictions and observed behavior. Regardless of whether or
not the experiment was presented to subjects with context, for ease of
exposition we use the term "offend" to describe all subject
choices that correspond to committing the crime.
A. Descriptive Statistics
We begin our empirical analysis by examining the frequency with
which behavior is consistent with the theoretically predicted strategy.
(18) Table 2 reports the proportion of subjects in all sessions who play
the predicted strategy. (19) Recall that subjects were also asked to
state the strategy that they planned to follow in the experiment prior
to making actual decisions. Table 2 also reports the proportion of these
"stated strategies" that are consistent with theory in
parentheses. These results are reported for each of five risk-tolerance
categories shown in Table 1, (20)
Looking at the overall level of consistency between theory and
behavior, we find that the extremely risk-averse subjects and subjects
facing the decreasing penalty structures are most likely to follow the
theorized strategy. Risk-loving subjects and subjects who face a
constant fine structure are least likely to follow the theorized
strategy. Recall that the model predicts the highest level of offenses
under this fine structure. We find that the most commonly used strategy
in the (5,5) penalty structure is for subjects never to commit an
offense. This nonoptimal strategy of (0, 0) was followed by 46% of the
subjects. Table 2 also shows that for each penalty structure, actual
behavior is closer to theoretical predictions than subjects' stated
strategies. (21)
Overall, we find that about two-thirds of subjects choose the
predicted optimal strategy in the decreasing fine structures, but for
some other penalty structures less than half of the subjects make
decisions that are consistent with theory. A possible explanation for
inconsistencies between theory and observed behavior is that agents are
myopic and treat each stage as a one-shot decision. Consider the
simplest example, where agents are risk neutral. In this case, given
that the benefit of the crime is $2 and the probability of apprehension
is 1/3, myopic risk-neutral agents will commit the act as long as the
fine is less than $6. We would expect myopic risk-averse subjects to
still commit when the fine is somewhat lower than $6 (the exact amount
depends on the risk parameter). But, in situations where myopic behavior
predicts offenses will be committed under risk neutrality, we observe
offense rates of 75%, 61%, and 35% with the $1 fine, the $3 fine, and
the $5 fine, respectively. In the situation where we expect no offenses
with myopic behavior under risk neutrality, we observe a 21% offense
rate with the $7 fine and a 19% offense rate with the $9 fine. These
offense rates do not support the idea that people consider each stage
decision separately. These aggregate results also suggest that risk
tolerance affects whether or not behavior follows theory.
B. Econometric Analysis of Behavioral Deviations from Theory
As noted above, the observed behavior in our experiment is not
always consistent with the predicted optimal choices. Across all risk
preferences and penalty structures, only 52% of observed actions follow
the predicted strategy. Additionally, 42% of stated strategies are
consistent with predicted optimal behavior. (22) In this section, we
explore which factors drive a subject to deviate from the predicted
behavior. We begin by defining two variables: (1) an indicator for
whether the subject's stated strategy is equal to the optimal
strategy and (2) an indicator for whether the observed strategy is equal
to the optimal strategy. Recall from the experimental design section
that we elicit each subject's stated strategy for each penalty
structure before they actually face that penalty structure with monetary
consequences.
In Table 3 we examine a variety of factors that may be driving
deviations from the predicted optimal strategy, as determined by theory.
In Model 1, we estimate and provide the marginal effects from a probit
model where the outcome is a binary variable for whether the stated
strategy is consistent with theoretically predicted behavior. Model 2
presents the marginal effects from the probit regression where the
outcome is the binary variable for whether observed behavior is
consistent with theory. Consistency with predicted optimal strategy is
dependent on the subject's individual risk profile as presented in
Table 1. We include indicators for the subject's risk category:
risk loving (r < 0), risk neutral (r = 0), risk averse (.75 [greater
than or equal to] r > 0), very risk averse (1.17 [greater than or
equal to] r >. 75), and extremely risk averse (r > 1.17) groups.
The omitted category is risk-neutral subjects. We also include
information about whether the subject was caught in the first stage of
the penalty structure, the percentage of times that the subject was
detected when they committed an offense, as well as information about
the penalty structure, presentation order of treatments, dummy variables
for the three contexts, and a dummy variable for whether the subject was
male.
Our results provide some interesting insights regarding deviations
from the predicted optimal strategy. Overall, stated strategies and
observed actions are relatively similar in terms of which
characteristics are correlated with the probability of being consistent
with the optimal strategy. Male subjects are more likely than female
subjects to both state a strategy that is consistent with the optimal
strategy and choose actual behavior consistent with theory. Risk-loving
subjects are approximately 21% more likely to deviate from the optimal
strategy than risk-neutral subjects. Extremely risk-averse subjects are
more likely to take actions that are consistent with the optimal
strategies than risk-neutral subjects; however, this is not the case in
their stated strategies. We know from Table 2 that the lowest level of
consistency is observed with penalty structure (5,5). Using (5,5) as the
reference category in our probit analysis, we confirm that after
controlling for subject heterogeneity, the increasing and decreasing
penalty structures exhibit higher levels of consistency with theory than
the flat penalty structure. Overall, our results indicate that the
predictive power of the model depends on the penalty structure and on
subject-specific characteristics. (23)
V. CONSISTENCY OF BEHAVIOR ACROSS DECISION-MAKING STAGES
In addition to examining consistency with theory, we next focus on
whether individuals make the same decision each time they face the same
fine. This analysis provides further evidence that subjects treat the
two decision-making stages within a penalty structure as interrelated.
Table 4 displays the consistency of behavior across the two stages of
the experiment when subjects face the same fine at different stages.
Since we are comparing behavior across two decisions for the same
subject, we aggregated these results over all risk preference types.
Column 1 shows the total number of subjects who choose not to
offend in stage 1 for each penalty structure. Of those subjects who do
not offend in stage 1, column 2 shows the number who also did not offend
in stage 2. Note that these subjects face the same fine in stage 2 as
they did in stage 1, since they did not offend in stage 1. Thus, we
would expect subjects who treat each stage as a one-shot decision to
make the same decisions in these two stages. Column 3 presents the
percentage of subjects who made consistent decisions across stages when
facing the same fine. A surprisingly large number of subjects make
different decisions across the two stages, despite facing the same fine.
The lack of consistency in choosing not to offend across these two
columns could be evidence of learning or evidence that the two-stage
nature of the problem affects the way subjects make each individual
decision. Note also that consistency across columns 1 and 2 is largest
for the decreasing fine structures, providing evidence that high first
fines deter offenses regardless of stage.
The right-hand side of Table 4 examines an alternative situation
where subjects face the same fine in both stages of decision-making;
here we focus on the decision to offend. Column 4 shows the number of
subjects who offend in stage 1, but are not caught. Column 5 shows how
many of those people go on to offend again in stage 2. Again, with
subjects who treat each stage as independent, we expect everyone to
offend in stage 1 under the increasing and constant fine structures and
no one to offend under the decreasing fine structures, regardless of
their risk type. Since column 4 is conditional on subjects not being
caught in stage 1, the same predictions hold for column 5.
We find very low rates of consistency in offending between the two
stages with decreasing and flat penalty structures, and only 60%
consistency in the increasing fine structures for this comparison of
offending when subjects are facing the same fine. This finding is a
puzzle and might be evidence of confusion on the part of subjects about
what fine they are actually facing, despite playing practice rounds and
having the fine structure explained in detail. Another possible
explanation for the lack of consistency is decreasing marginal utility
of the $2 gain from offending. Recall that subjects start with $10 and
those who offend in stage 1 and are not caught receive $2. Because they
start stage 2 with $12, the potential $2 gain from offending in stage 2
adds less utility than it added in stage 1. If this is driving the lack
of consistency, we might expect to find different levels of risk
tolerance for subjects who are consistent across stages compared with
subjects who are not consistent. For most penalty structures, Wilcoxon
tests show no difference in risk tolerance between subjects who are not
consistent across stages and those who are. However, for penalty
structures (5,5) and (7,3), we find that subjects who are not consistent
are more risk averse than those who are consistent across stages. (24)
Alternatively, the lack of consistency may be evidence of loss
aversion with an endowment effect. The subject has taken the risk to
earn $2 in the first stage and succeeded. The potential loss of the fine
is more painful now that the subject has $12 relative to the foregone
gain of $2 in the second stage, causing some subjects to choose not to
take the risk in the second stage. Unfortunately, we cannot test for
loss aversion given the experimental design and information collected.
Another possible explanation for inconsistency here is an irrational
belief by subjects that they are more likely to be caught in stage 2
after avoiding detection in stage 1. Inconsistent choices could also be
the result of learning or taking the two-stage decision into account.
While we speculate here about what is driving the lack of consistency
finding, in Section VI.B we attempt to isolate the factors influencing
the general decisions to offend using econometric analysis.
VI. DETERRENCE
Next we turn our attention to identifying which enforcement regimes
yield the greatest level of deterrence. We also examine the individual
characteristics correlated with the decision to offend.
A. Descriptive Statistics
Figure 1 shows the total number of offenses by decision stage and
enforcement regime. The most striking observation is that increasing
fine regimes have over twice as many offenses as decreasing fine
regimes. (25) The constant fine mechanism has fewer offenses relative to
increasing enforcement regimes, but more offenses compared to decreasing
fine regimes. In short, we find descriptive evidence consistent with the
theoretical prediction that a decreasing, rather than increasing penalty
structure, yields greater specific deterrence. (26)
Figure 1 also shows how offense rates vary across the two stages of
decision-making. Note that the number of offenses falls sharply between
the first and second stage in the increasing fine regimes. This is not
surprising since first stage offense rates are relatively high in these
two regimes, which means that relatively more people get caught and face
the high penalty associated with a second offense in the second stage of
these regimes. On the other hand, the number of offenses is fairly
constant across the two decision stages in the decreasing sanction
schemes. While committing an offense in the first stage is not predicted
to be optimal under these schemes, if a subject offends and is caught in
the first stage, utility maximization predicts the subject will recommit
in the second stage. Note, however, that Figure 1 provides no
information about which fine subjects face in the second stage, because
it does not distinguish between people who committed an offense and were
caught in the first stage and those who were not caught.
Table 5 provides the number of subjects who face the first fine or
second fine in stage 2. Subjects who face the first fine in stage 2
either did not commit an offense or they committed an offense and were
not caught in the first stage. Subjects who face the second fine in the
penalty structure represent those who committed an offense and were
caught in the first stage. Consistent with Figure 1, the number of
subjects facing the second fine in stage 2 is decreasing with the first
fine, as fewer subjects commit an offense at all in the first stage when
facing a decreasing penalty structure ((7,3) or (9,1)).
Figure 2 focuses on second stage decisions and provides information
about offenses and the specific fine faced by the subject. Panel A of
Figure 2 shows that among subjects who face the first fine, there are
significantly more second stage offenses in the increasing penalty
structures than in the decreasing penalty structures. (27) For those
subjects who face the second fine, very few second stage offenses are
committed overall, but there are more second stage offenses in the
constant and decreasing penalty structures than in the increasing
penalty structures. (28)
Panel B of Figure 2 presents the second stage offense data in
percentage terms. For each bar in Panel A, we divide the number of
offenses committed in that scenario by the total number of decisions
made. This figure reveals that recidivism rates among those who were
caught in the first stage are much higher in the decreasing penalty
structures than in the increasing penalty structures. (29) For example,
all 19 subjects who offended and were caught in the first stage under
the (9,1) penalty structure offended again in the second stage. As noted
above, given that a subject makes the irrational decision to commit a
first stage offense in the (7,3) or (9,1) penalty structure and gets
caught, the optimal second stage decision is to recidivate.
Overall, the graphs of offense levels and rates suggest that our
results are consistent with the theoretical model of Emons (2003);
decreasing penalty structures lead to higher levels of deterrence than
increasing penalty structures. (30) However, there may also be
potentially confounding effects of individual characteristics on
offending.
In addition to whether the fine structure is increasing or
decreasing, individual subject characteristics may play a role in how
likely the subjects are to choose to offend. Figure 3 provides details
on how many offenses subjects commit by gender and risk tolerance.
Notice that fewer than 20 subjects never commit an offense and only 13
commit 9 or 10 offenses. Figure 3 also shows that female subjects are
significantly more likely than male subjects to commit a lower number of
offenses. (31) We also divide our sample into those who are risk averse
and those who are not risk averse based on their decisions on the Holt
and Laury (2002) lottery choice experiment. (32) As the figure suggests,
risk-averse subjects commit significantly fewer total offenses than
those who are not risk averse. (33)
B. Econometric Analysis of Deterrence
Given that demographic characteristics appear to be correlated with
the frequency of offending, we examine the effect of the penalty scheme
on deterrence by running an ordered probit of total offenses within a
penalty structure controlling for the subject's gender, a dummy for
whether the subject is risk averse, context, presentation order
treatment, and an indicator for whether the subject was caught in the
first stage. (34) Based on these probit results, we calculate the
predicted probability that an individual never commits an offense,
commits an offense one time, or commits an offense in both stages under
a particular penalty structure. These results are presented in Table 6.
Individuals are most likely to commit no offenses in the decreasing
penalty regime (where there is a higher first stage penalty). On the
other hand, increasing penalty structures have the highest predicted
rate of subjects committing two offenses (at 43% and 33%), perhaps
because individuals who are not caught in the first stage have high
incentives to recidivate. Even after controlling for individual
characteristics, the overall implication of Table 6 is that decreasing
penalty structures are far more effective in deterring offenses and are
more likely to result in zero offenses than increasing penalty
structures given our parameterized model. (35)
While Table 6 shows that a decreasing fine structure reduces the
overall number of offenses, we have not examined the impact of fine
structures on the individual choice to commit offenses in each stage. To
do so, we run probit regressions on the individual decision of whether
or not to offend in each stage. (36) Table 7 presents the marginal
effects from the analysis. (37) We control for subject characteristics
(male, dummy for whether the subject is risk averse), the presentation
order treatment, the context, the number of times a subject has offended
in previous rounds, the number of times a subject has been caught in
previous rounds (excluding the first stage of the current round), and an
indicator for whether the subject was caught in the first stage of the
particular round. (38) To isolate the effect of the penalty structure,
in Model 1, we include controls for whether the decision is a second
stage decision and an indicator for each penalty structure. (39) Errors
are clustered at the subject level to account for potential correlation
across the ten individual decisions.
The results at the individual level confirm the aggregate results;
the coefficients on the decreasing fine structures (7,3) and (9,1) are
significantly different from the omitted category penalty structure
(5,5). (40) By disaggregating the data to the individual level
decisions, we also observe some phenomena that we did not observe in the
aggregated data. Subjects who offend more often are almost 9 percentage
points more likely to continue to offend in the particular stage.
Moreover, the average marginal effect of an additional instance of being
caught in previous penalty structures decreases the likelihood of
offending by slightly more than 2 percentage points, even though being
caught under a previous penalty structure has no impact on the current
period's potential payoffs. This is suggestive of a specific
deterrence effect; subjects respond to previous punishment experience
even when that previous punishment is not affecting the current cost of
offending. Last, we find that being caught in the first stage reduces
the probability of offending in the second stage by about 15 percentage
points (in addition to the 16 percentage point reduction in probability
of offending that exists for the average second stage decision). (41)
Model 2 addresses the issue of the penalty structure in a slightly
different way. Instead of including indicator variables for each penalty
structure, we include an indicator variable to capture whether subjects
are making decisions under an increasing fine scheme. We also include a
variable to capture the separate effect of the specific fine faced by
the subject. The qualitative results from Model 1 hold, with one
exception. The coefficient on the indicator variable for being caught in
the first stage is no longer significant. Model 2 reveals that,
independent of the specific fine faced for any given decision, facing an
increasing penalty structure increases the probability a subject will
commit an offense by slightly more than 5%. This provides additional
evidence that subjects take the two-stage nature of the decision into
account when making decisions and are less deterred by increasing
penalty structures.
Recall that one implication of Becker (1968) is that criminals tend
to be risk-seeking. We repeat the analysis of Model 2 in Table 7 with
the inclusion of an interaction between risk aversion and type of
penalty structure (increasing penalty vs. decreasing/flat penalty
structure). We then predict the probability of offending in order to
examine whether the likelihood of offending for types of subjects varies
across increasing and decreasing/flat penalty structures. The predicted
probability of offending for nonrisk-averse subjects is .468 in the
decreasing/flat penalty structures and .452 in the increasing penalty
structures, which is not significantly different. Alternatively,
risk-averse subjects respond significantly differently to the penalty
structures. For risk-averse subjects, the predicted probability of
offending in decreasing/flat penalty structures is .359 and .435 for
increasing penalty structures. (42) It appears that the differential in
offense rates across penalty structures is largely due to the subjects
who are risk averse rather those who are not. (43)
VII. CONCLUSION
There is a large literature on optimal law enforcement following
the pioneering work of Becker (1968). For example, Emons (2003, 2004)
presents multiperiod models of criminal enforcement based on the
standard Becker approach and finds that decreasing penalties result in
greater deterrence. As is standard in this literature, he models the law
enforcer's joint choice of the probability of detection and the
penalty if detected. A number of experimental papers have examined the
trade-off between the probability of detection and the penalty if
detected in a repeated one-shot decision. (44) To our knowledge,
however, we present the first experimental study to examine whether
increasing or decreasing penalty schemes are better at deterring risky
behavior.
We chose the basic model of Emons (2003) as the starting point for
our design. We find that decreasing, rather than increasing, sanction
schemes provides higher deterrence in our repeated decision-making
situation. Although numerous arguments have been put forth for the use
of increasing penalty schemes, our results suggest that decreasing
penalty schemes yield higher rates of deterrence. The relative
simplicity of the model might explain why the theoretical prediction is
different from the increasing sanctions we observe in most penal codes.
For example, the model does not include costs to criminals other than
the fine, and thus, does not take into account a potential desire of
policymakers to educate first offenders or to minimize stigma. A related
concern is that someone might be erroneously convicted of a first
offense. Additionally, the model does not include political aspects of
policymaking such as the fear that harsh sanctions might be viewed as
unjust. By incorporating special features, some multiperiod models
support the use of escalating penalties in a Becker-style model. (45) A
natural extension of our study is to incorporate more complicated
theoretical assumptions into our experimental design.
Although we find evidence that decreasing penalties provide higher
deterrence, observed behavior is only consistent with the theoretical
prediction in 52% of the decision-making periods. When we examine the
relationship between individual characteristics and consistency with
theory, we find that extreme risk preferences (risk loving and extremely
risk averse) are correlated with the likelihood of consistency, as well
as the gender of the subject. Consistency with theory also increases
with previous detection, suggesting the penalty and potential effect on
expected utility become more salient as the subject experiences being
caught.
Additionally, we explore some behavioral features of the
decision-making process that are not predicted by the rational
decision-making model. We observe greater offense levels when subjects
are male, less risk averse, and have committed offenses in previous
rounds. We also observe that being caught under previous penalty
structures has a small deterrence effect in the current penalty
structure, even though both the probability of being caught and the fine
are independent of previous rounds. Even after controlling for the
specific fine a subject faces, we find that the probability of
committing an offense is higher under an increasing penalty regime. When
we examine subject responses to current fines faced, we also find
evidence that subjects treat the choice to offend in each stage as part
of a two-stage interrelated decision (i.e., subjects consider the full
penalty structure of the period) and do not respond solely to the amount
of the fine.
APPENDIX
SCREENSHOTS OF EXPERIMENT
This experiment consists of 5 periods with 2 stages each, so you
will make a total of 10 decisions. At the end of the experiment, we will
randomly pick one of the 5 periods to determine your payoff. Ail of the
periods are equally likely to be chosen to determine your payoff, so you
should think carefully about each of the10 decisions.
Please enter the given ID in here
In each period you will have two stages in which you have to decide
if you want to TAKE A CHANCE or NOT TAKE A CHANCE. You begin each period
with $10. Each time you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will earn an extra
$2. In every stage you face the possibility of being observed, if you
choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are observed then you will lose money. If
you choose to NOT TO TAKE A CHANCE and are observed you will not lose
money, but you will also not earn extra money.
To determine whether or not you are being observed, the computer
will generate a random number equally likely to be 1,2, or 3. If the
random number is 3, you will be observed. Hence, the chance of being
observed is 1 in 3. You will lose money only if you choose to TAKE A
CHANCE and are OBSERVED.
Each of the 5 periods has a different payoff structure, so be sure
that you understand the payoff structure in each period before you make
your decisions.
Now you will play a practice period to help you understand how the
game works. This practice period will have 2 stages just like the 5
actual periods you will play in a moment. Because this is a practice
period, your decisions in this period will NOT affect your actual
earnings today.
Remember: You begin with an initial payment of $10.
Every time you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will receive an extra
$2, but you face a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED. If you choose to
TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED, then you will lose money as described on
the next screen. If you choose to NOT TAKE A CHANCE, and you are
OBSERVED, then you will not lose money, but you will also not earn extra
money.
Before we start the practice period, we would like to know what
your strategy wiH most likely look like. The table below will help you
understand the payoff that you will receive for different possible
decisions.
You begin with an initial payment of $10. If you are OBSERVED and
It is the first time you have been OSBERVED in this practice period, you
will lose $1. If you are OBSERVED and it is the second time you have
been OBSERVED in this practice period, you will lose $9.
Before we start the practice period we would like to know what your
strategy will most likely look like.
In every stage, if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will always
receive an extra $2 but you face a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED.
If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the first
time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the
practice period, you will lose $1. If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and
are OBSERVED and it is the second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE
and have been OBSERVED in the practice period, you will lose $9.
In the 1st stage I would most likely choose to
TAKE A CHANCE NOT TAKE A CHANCE
Before we start the practice period we would like to know what your
strategy will most likely look like.
In every stage, if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will always
receive an extra $2 but you face a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED.
If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the first
time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the
practice period, you will lose $1. If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and
are OBSERVED and it is the second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE
and have been OBSERVED in the practice period, you will lose $9.
If I was OBSERVED in the 1st stage, in the 2nd stage I would most
likely choose to
* TAKE A CHANCE * NOT TAKE A CHANCE
If I was NOT OSERVED in the 1st stage, in the 2nd stage I would
most likely choose to
* TAKE A CHANCE
* NOT TAKE A CHANCE
In the 1st stage you chose to TAKE A CHANCE.
Practice Period - Stage 1
Remember: You begin with an initial payment of $10.
Every time you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will receive an extra
$2. In every stage you face a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED. If you
choose to TAKE A CHANCE and you are OBSERVED, then you will lose money
as described below. If you choose to NOT TAKE A CHANCE and you are
OBSERVED, then you will not lose money, but you also win not earn extra
money. There is a possibility you will lose money if you choose to TAKE
A CHANCE and are OBSERVED. (Note: In each stage you face the possibility
of losing money only if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE. However, you wifl
only earn extra money if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE.)
If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and It is the first
time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the
practice period, you will lose $1.
If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and It is the
second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE, and have been OBSERVED in
the practice period, you will lose $9.
PLEASE CHOOSE NOW
* TAKE A CHANCE
* NOT TAKE A CHANCE
Practice Period 1--Stage 1
You have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE. Are you sure about your choice?
You have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE.
As this is just a practice period, NO ONE was OBSERVED.
Therefore your payoff would be $10 + $2 = $12.
Practice Period 1--Stage 2
Once again, you must choose whether you want to TAKE A CHANCE or
NOT TAKE A CHANCE. Every time you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will
receive an additional $2. There is a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED. If
you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and you are OBSERVED, then you win lose
money as described below. If you choose to NOT TAKE A CHANCE and you are
OBSERVED you will not lose money, but you will also not earn extra
money.
If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the first
time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the
practice period, you will lose $1.
If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the
second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in
the practice period, you will lose $9.
PLEASE CHOOSE NOW
* TAKE A CHANCE
* NOT TAKE A CHANCE
Practice Period 1--Stage 2
You have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE. Are you sure about your choice?
You have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE.
As this is just a practice period. NO ONE was OBSERVED.
Therefore your payoff for the practice period would be $14.
Questions?
If you have any questions about the game or If something Is unclear
please raise your hand and we will come to your desk to answer It.
Get Ready!
Now you will start playing the actual gamel
This Is the 1st period!
Before we start the 1st period, we would like to know what your
strategy will most likely look like. The table below will help you
understand the payoff that you will receive for different possible
decisions.
You begin with an initial payment of $10. If you are OBSERVED and
it is the first time you have been OSBERVED in this practice period, you
will lose $1. If you are OBSERVED and it is the second time you have
been OBSERVED in this practice period, you will lose $9.
Before we start the 1st period we would like to know what your
strategy will most likely look like.
In every stage, if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will always
receive an extra $2 but you face a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED.
If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the first
time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the 1st
period, you will lose $1. If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are
OBSERVED and it is the second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and
have been OBSERVED in the 1st period, you will lose $9.
In the 1st stage I would most likely choose to
* TAKE A CHANCE
* NOT TAKE A CHANCE
Before we start the 1st period we would like to know what your
strategy will most likely look like.
In every stage, if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will always
receive an extra $2 but you face a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED.
If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the first
time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the 1st
period, you will lose $1. If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are
OBSERVED and it is the second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and
have been OBSERVED in the 1st period, you will lose $9.
In the 1st stage you chose to TAKE A CHANCE.
If I was OBSERVED in the 1st stage, in the 2nd stage I would most
likely choose to
* TAKE A CHANCE * NOT TAKE A CHANCE
If I was NOT OBSERVED in the 1st stage, in the 2nd stage I would
most likely choose to
* TAKE A CHANCE
* NOT TAKE A CHANCE
Period 1 - Stage 1
Remember You begin with an initial payment of $10.
Every time you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will receive an extra
$2. In every stage you face a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED. If you
choose to TAKE A CHANCE and you are OBSERVED, then you will lose money
as described below. If you choose to NOT TAKE A CHANCE and you are
OBSERVED, then you will not lose money, but you also will not earn extra
money. There Is a possibility you will lose money if you choose to TAKE
A CHANCE and are OBSERVED. (Note: In each stage you face the possibility
of losing money only if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE. However, you will
only earn extra money If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE.)
If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and It is the first
time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the 1st
period, you will lose $1. If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are
OBSERVED and it is the second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE, and
have been OBSERVED in the 1st period, you will lose $9.
PLEASE CHOOSE NOW
* TAKE A CHANCE
* NOT TAKE A CHANCE
Period 1 - Stage 1
You have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE. Are you sure about your choice?
You have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE. Because you were NOT OBSERVED you
will not lose money.
Therefore your payoff is $10 + $2 = $12.
Period 1 - Stage 2
Once again, you must choose whether you want to TAKE A CHANCE or
NOT TAKE A CHANCE. Every time you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will
receive an additional $2. There is a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED. If
you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and you are OBSERVED, then you will lose
money as described below If you choose to NOT TAKE A CHANCE and you are
OBSERVED you will not lose money, but you will also not earn extra
money.
If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and It is the first
time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the 1st
period, you will lose $1.
If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the
second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in
the 1st period, you will lose $9.
PLEASE CHOOSE NOW
* TAKE A CHANCE
* NOT TAKE A CHANCE
Period 1 - Stage 2
You have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE. Are you sure about your choice?
You have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE. Because you were OBSERVED you
will lose money.
Therefore your payoff tor this period is $13
This Is the 2nd period!
Before we start the 2nd period, we would like to know what your
strategy will most likely look like. The table below will help you
understand the payoff that you will receive for different possible
decisions.
You begin with an initial payment of $10. If you are OBSERVED and
it is the first time you have been OSBERVED in this practice period, you
will lose $3. If you are OBSERVED and it is the second time you have
been OBSERVED in this practice period, you will lose $7.
Before we start the 2nd period we would like to know what your
strategy will most likely look like.
In every stage, if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will always
receive an extra $2 but you face a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED.
If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the first
time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the 2nd
period, you will lose $3. If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are
OBSERVED and it is the second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and
have been OBSERVED in the 2nd period, you will lose $7.
In the 1st stage I would most likely choose to
* TAKE A CHANCE
* NOT TAKE A CHANCE
doi: 10.1111/ecin.12464
REFERENCES
Anderson, L., and M. Mellor. "Predicting Health Behaviors with
an Experimental Measure of Risk Preference." Journal of Health
Economics, 27(5), 2008, 1260-74.
--. "Are Risk Preferences Stable? Comparing an Experimental
Measure with a Validated Survey-Based Measure." Journal of Risk and
Uncertainty, 39(2), 2009, 137-60.
Anderson, L., and S. Stafford. "Punishment in a Regulatory
Setting: Experimental Evidence from the VCM." Journal of Regulatory
Economics, 24(1), 2003, 91-110.
Arlen, J., and E. Taylor. Experimental Law and Economics.
Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar Publishing, 2008.
Baik, K. H., and I.-G. Kim. "Optimal Punishment When
Individuals May Learn Deviant Values." International Review of Law
and Economics, 21, 2001, 271-85.
Bar-Ilan, A., and B. Sacerdote. "Response to Fines and
Probabilities in a Natural Experiment." Journal of Law and
Economics, 47(1), 2004, 1-17.
Bebchuck, L., and L. Kaplow. "Optimal Sanctions When
Individuals Are Imperfectly Informed about the Probability of
Apprehension." Journal of Legal Studies, 21, 1993, 365-70.
Becker, G. "Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach."
Journal of Political Economy, 76, 1968, 169-217.
Ben-Shahar, O. "Playing without a Rulebook": Optimal
Enforcement When Individuals Learn the Penalty only by Committing the
Crime." International Review of Law and Economics, 17, 1997,409-21.
Brandts, J., and G. Chamess. "Truth or Consequences: An
Experiment." Management Science, 49, 2003, 116-30.
--. "The Strategy versus the Direct-Response Method: A First
Survey of Experimental Comparisons." Experimental Economics, 14,
2011, 375-98.
Brosig, J., J. Weimann, and C. L. Yang. "The Hot versus Cold
Effect in a Simple Bargaining Experiment." Experimental Economics,
6, 2003, 75-90.
Bumovski, M., and Z. Safra. "Deterrence Effects of Sequential
Punishment Policies: Should Repeat Offenders Be More Severely
Punished?" International Review of Law and Economics, 14, 1994,
341-50.
Camerer, C., and E. Talley. "Experimental Law and
Economics," in Handbook of Law and Economics, edited by M. Polinsky
and S. Shavell. Amsterdam: North-Holland, 2007, 1619-50.
Casari, M., and T. Cason. "The Strategy Method Lowers Measured
Trustworthy Behavior." Economics Letters, 103, 2009, 157-59.
Chu, C., S. Hu, and T. Huang. "Punishing Repeat Offenders More
Severely." International Review of Law and Economics, 20, 2000,
127-40.
Curry, P., and M. Doyle. "Integrating Market Alternatives into
the Economic Theory of Optimal Deterrence." Economic Inquiry,
54(4), 2016, 1873-83.
Dana, D. A. "Rethinking the Puzzle of Escalating Penalties for
Repeat Offenders." The Yale Law Journal, 110, 2001,733-83.
DeAngelo, G., and G. Charness. "Deterrence, Expected Cost,
Uncertainty and Voting: Experimental Evidence." Journal of Risk and
Uncertainty, 44(1), 2012, 73-100.
Emons, W. "A Note on the Optimal Punishment for Repeat
Offenders." International Review of Law and Economics, 23, 2003,
253-59.
--. "Subgame Perfect Punishment for Repeat Offenders."
Economic Inquiry, 42, 2004, 496-502.
--. "Escalating Penalties for Repeat Offenders."
International Review of Law and Economics, 27, 2007, 170-78.
Engel, C. Behavioral Law and Economics: Empirical Methods, Vol. 01.
Bonn, Germany: Preprints of the Max Planck Institute for Research on
Collective Goods, 2013.
Fellner, G., R. Sausgruber, and C. Traxler. "Testing
Enforcement Strategies in the Field: Threat, Moral Appeal, and Social
Information." Journal of the European Economic Association, 11(3),
2013, 634-60.
Fischbacher, U. "z-Tree: Zurich Toolbox for Ready-made
Economic Experiments." Experimental Economics, 10(2), 2007, 171-8.
Friedman, D. "Efficient Institutions for the Private
Enforcement of Law," Journal of Legal Studies, 13, 1984, 379-97.
Friesen, L. "Certainty of Punishment versus Severity of
Punishment: An Experimental Investigation." Southern Economic
Journal, 79, 2012, 399-421.
Funk, P. "On the Effective Use of Stigma as a
Crime-deterrent." European Economic Review, 48, 2004, 715-28.
Garoupa, N. "The Theory of Optimal Law Enforcement."
Journal of Economic Surveys, 11, 1997, 267-95.
Garoupa, N., and M. Jellal. "Dynamic Law Enforcement with
Learning." Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 20, 2004,
192-206.
Harel, A., and U. Segal. "Criminal Law and Behavioral Law and
Economics: Observations on the Neglected Role of Uncertainty in
Deterring Crime." American Law and Economics Review, 1, 1999,
276-312.
Holt, C., and S. Laury. "Risk Aversion and Incentive
Effects." American Economic Review, 92, 2002, 1644-55.
Lochner, L. "Individual Perceptions of the Criminal Justice
System." American Economic Review, 97, 2007, 444-60.
Mastrobuoni, G., and D. A. Rivers. "Criminal Discount Factors
and Deterrence." IZA Discussion Papers No. 9769, 2016.
McAdams, R. H., and T. S. Ulen. "Behavioral Criminal Law and
Economics." Public Law & Legal Theory Working Papers No. 244,
2008.
McCannon, B. "Differentiating between First and Repeat
Offenders." Contemporary Economic Policy, 27, 2009, 76-85.
Miceli, T. "Escalating Penalties for Repeat Offenders: Why Are
They So Hard to Explain?" Journal of Institutional and Theoretical
Economics, 169, 2013, 587-604.
Miceli, T., and C. Bucci. "A Simple Theory of Increasing
Penalties for Repeat Offenders." Review of Law & Economics, 1,
2005, 5.
Miles, S., and D. Pyne. "Deterring Repeat Offenders with
Escalating Penalty Schedules: A Bayesian Approach." Economics of
Governance, 16, 2015, 229-50.
Motchenkova, E. "Cost Minimizing Sequential Punishment
Policies for Repeat Offenders." Applied Economics Letters, 21,
2014, 360-65.
Mungan, M. "Repeat Offenders: If They Learn, We Punish Them
More Severely." International Review of Law and Economics, 30,
2010, 173-77.
--. "Optimal Warning Strategies: Punishment Ought Not to Be
Inflicted Where the Penal Provision Is Not Properly Conveyed."
Review of Law & Economics, 9, 2013,303-39.
--. "A Behavioral Justification for Escalating
Penalties." International Review of Law and Economics, 37, 2014,
189-97.
Mungan, M., and J. Klick. "Forfeiture of Illegal Gains,
Attempts, and Implied Risk Preferences." Journal of Legal Studies,
43(1), 2014, 137-53.
--. "Discounting and Criminals' Implied Risk
Preferences." Review of Law & Economics, 11, 2015, 19-23.
Neilson, W., and H. Winter. "On Criminals' Risk
Attitudes." Economics Letters, 55, 1997, 97-102.
Polinsky, M., and D. Rubinfeld. "A Model of Fines for Repeat
Offenders." Journal of Public Economics, 46, 1991, 291-306.
Polinsky, M., and S. Shavell. "On Offense History and the
Theory of Deterrence." International Review of Law and Economics,
18, 1998, 305-24.
--. "The Economic Theory of Public Enforcement of Law."
Journal of Economic Literature, 38, 2000, 45-76.
Rasmusen, E. "Stigma and Self-fulfilling Expectations of
Criminality." Journal of Law and Economics, 39, 1996, 519-43.
Rubinstein, A. "An Optimal Conviction Policy for Offenses that
May Have Been Committed by Accident," in Applied Game Theory,
edited by S. Brams, A. Schotter, and G. Schwodiauer. Wurzburg, Germany:
Physica-Verlag, 1979,406-13.
Schildberg-Horisch, H., and C. Strassmair. "An Experimental
Test of the Deterrence Hypothesis." Journal of Law, Economics, and
Organization, 28(3), 2012, 447-59.
Sloan, F., A. Platt, L. Chepke, and C. Blevins. "Deterring
Domestic Violence: Do Criminal Sanctions Reduce Repeat Offenses?"
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 46(1), 2013, 51-80.
Sonnemann, U., C. F. Camerer, C. R. Fox, and T. Langer. "How
Psychological Framing Affects Economic Market Prices in the Lab and
Field." Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 110, 2013:
11779-84.
Tietelbaum, J., and K. Zeiler, eds. Research Handbook on Behavioral
Law and Economics. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar Publishing, 2015.
LISA R. ANDERSON, GREGORY DEANGELO, WINAND EMONS, BETH FREEBORN and
HANNES LANG *
* The views expressed are those of the author and do not represent
those of the Federal Trade Commission or any individual Commissioner. We
would like to thank Emmanuel Dechenaux, Heiko Karle, Dan Rubinfeld,
Sergio de Souza, participants at the 2014 Southern Economic Association
Meetings Society for Ecological Economics. We also thank the editor and
two anonymous referees.
Anderson: Professor, Department of Economics, 127 Morton Hall,
College of William and Mary, Williamsburg, VA 23187. Phone 757-221-2359,
Fax 757-221-1175, E-mail
[email protected]
DeAngelo: Assistant Professor of Economics, College of Business and
Economics, West Virginia University, 1601 University Avenue, Morgantown,
WV 26506. Phone 304293-4039, E-mail
[email protected]
Emons: Professor, Department of Economics, University of Bern,
Hochschulstrasse 4,3012 Bern, Switzerland. Phone +41 31 631 39 22,
E-mail
[email protected]
Freeborn: Economist, Federal Trade Commission, 600 Pennsylvania
Avenue, NW Washington, DC 20580. Phone 202-326-2837, E-mail
[email protected]
Lang: Research Associate, Technical University Munich, 85354
Freising, Germany. Phone + 49 (0) 8161 71-5135, E-mail hanneslangl
@gmail.com
(1.) For example, in the United States under the Clean Water Act,
the maximum penalties are doubled for subsequent offenses and the
Immigration Reform and Control Act imposes minimum fines of $250 for a
first offense, $2,000 for a second offense, and $3,000 for subsequent
offenses. In Switzerland, the fine for traveling without a valid ticket
on a regional train is 100 SFR for the first offense, 140 SFR for the
second offense, and 170 SFR for any further offense. See Polinsky and
Shavell (1998) for more examples.
(2.) See, for example, Rubinstein (1979), Chu, Hu, and Huang
(2000), Emons (2007), Ben-Shahar (1997), and Bebchuck and Kaplow (1993)
for models that allow crimes to be committed by accident. In related
work, criminals might be uninformed (Mungan 2013), may lack self-control
(Mungan 2014), or may commit crimes by experimenting (McCannon 2009;
Miceli 2013). Curry and Doyle (2016) also show that optimal penalties
are increasing with criminal history in a model where voluntary trade is
a possible alternative to the criminal activity.
(3.) See Garoupa (1997) or Polinsky and Shavell (2000) for surveys
of the earlier law enforcement literature.
(4.) See, for example, Bumovski and Safra (1994) and Emons (2003,
2004).
(5.) In addition to deterring criminal behavior, legal systems also
seek to sanction those who violate laws with criminal penalties and
fines. For the purposes of this paper, we abstract away from the notion
of punishment and assume that legal systems solely seek to optimize
deterrence.
(6.) Behavioral and experimental economics have been used to
investigate theoretical concepts in many subdisciplines within
economics, but are less prevalent in studying issues within law and
economics. See Tietelbaum and Zeiler (2015), Camerer and Talley (2007),
McAdams and Ulen (2008), Arlen and Taylor (2008), and Engel (2013) for
reviews of the literature. Limited work has focused on the exact nature
and context of enforcement. In a large-scale field experiment examining
different enforcement strategies to collect fees from consumers,
Fellner, Sausgruber, and Traxler (2013) show that making a high
detection regime salient to potential offenders has a significant
deterrence effect.
(7.) Emons (2003) also assumes that the benefit to the offender is
smaller than the harm caused by the offense. Our experiment does not
address the harm aspect of the offense, because our focus is on agent
behavior, and agent utility is not affected by the harm caused to
society. Adding "harm to society" in our experimental
framework in a way that affects subject payoffs would lead to strategic
interactions between players and make it harder for us to isolate the
effect of the penalty structure on behavior.
(8.) If sanctions are less than total wealth, sanctions can be
increased and the probability of apprehension lowered so as to keep
deterrence constant. In related theoretical work, Motchenkova (2014)
shows that the results of Emons (2003, 2004) also hold for more than two
periods; however, she does not allow for history-dependent strategies.
(9.) Note that if the benefit to the activity, b, is sufficiently
large, the predictions of the model will not hold.
(10.) While there is research that focuses on sanctions that exceed
an individual's wealth (see Polinsky and Shavell 2000), we focus on
situations where monetary sanctions do not exceed an individual's
wealth. This focus is sensible in a lab experiment. In practice, we
cannot take funds from participants. Additionally, situations where
sanctions exceed wealth typically involve excessively criminal acts,
which we do not attempt to model in the lab.
(11.) Behavior is anticipated to vary with the probability of
apprehension (Bar-Ilan and Sacerdote 2004). We reduce this dimension of
variation by holding the probability fixed throughout the experiment.
(12.) Note that both of the history-dependent strategies involve
the agent committing the crime in the first stage, because there is no
chance of paying a fine in the first stage if the crime is not
committed.
(13.) For example, Anderson and Mellor (2009) report that 75% of
their subjects are risk averse.
(14.) Emons (2003) determines the optimal sanction scheme in the
sense of Becker (1968), that is, the scheme that minimizes the cost of
enforcement. In terms of our example, the probability of apprehension is
minimized at 0.25 by choosing the (10,0) sanction scheme. However, in
this experiment, we fix the probability of apprehension at 1/3 and focus
on the potential differences in deterrence from increasing versus
decreasing penalty structures.
(15.) See Anderson and Mellor (2008) for more details about how to
derive the measure of risk tolerance, r, from this lottery choice
experiment.
(16.) At the beginning of each session, subjects also participated
in a "practice" period with hypothetical earnings.
(17.) In addition to the context-free treatment, there were three
additional treatments that varied only in the way the decision was
presented to subjects. In the context treatments, decisions were
presented as "driving over the speed limit," "cheating on
your taxes," and "shoplifting." Each subject made
decisions using only one of the four contexts. We ran both context free
and framed experiments to examine how subjects treated specific
proscribed behavioral environments in comparison to a sterile risk
environment, since previous research has shown considerable differences
(see, e.g., Sonnemann et al. 2013). While this aspect of the experiment
is not the focus of this paper, we do include controls for context in
the econometric analysis that follows.
(18.) The full dataset is available upon request.
(19.) In determining whether or not behavior is consistent with a
history-dependent strategy, we only observe actions on one path of the
strategy. For example, we cannot distinguish between someone playing
(1,1) or (1|1 if not detected) if that person is not caught in first
stage.
(20.) Note that seven subjects made an irrational decision in the
Holt and Laury (2002) experiment by choosing a certain lower payoff in
one situation. We were not able to impute a risk-tolerance parameter for
those subjects, resulting in 360 subjects with risk preference
information.
(21.) We also perform Wilcoxon tests to test whether the proportion
of subjects who state a strategy consistent with theory is significantly
different from the proportion of subjects who follow a strategy
consistent with optimal behavior. For each test, the p value is .000
(22.) As noted above, the proportion of subjects who state a
strategy consistent with the predicted optimal is significantly lower
than the proportion of subjects whose observed behavior is consistent
with predicted theory. This observation is consistent with Brandts and
Charness (2003), Brosig, Weimann, and Yang (2003), and Casari and Cason
(2009) on the benefits of incentivized elicitation versus hypothetical
elicitation. See Brandts and Charness (2011) for a review of observed
differences and similarities in the use of direct response versus
strategy methods.
(23.) The results are qualitatively the same when we repeated the
analysis of Table 3 using both logit and linear probability models.
These results are available upon request.
(24.) The p value is .056 for penalty structure (5,5) and is .001
for penalty structure (7,3).
(25.) Recall that subjects saw one of two order treatments in the
experiment, starting with the (1,9) penalty structure regime and
proceeding to the (9,1) regime (Treatment 1) or the reverse order where
subjects saw the (9,1) penalty first (Treatment 2). In the figures that
follow, we pool the data from the two presentation orders because we
find that the qualitative comparisons between the different penalty
structures within a presentation order treatment are consistent across
treatments. For example, there are always more offenses in the (1,9)
penalty structure than in the (3,7) penalty structure, regardless of
whether (1,9) is seen first or last. However, it is worth noting that we
find significant differences in overall levels of offending across
presentation order treatments. For this reason, we include controls for
treatment in all econometric analyses below.
(26.) We also find statistical evidence that decreasing penalty
structures yield greater deterrence. Wilcoxon tests show that the
average number of offenses are significantly different across all but
one of the penalty structures, with p values all smaller than .001. The
only exception is the pair (7,3) and (9,1), which does not have
significantly different numbers of offenses (p value equal to .323).
(27.) Wilcoxon tests show that the number of second stage offenses
for subjects facing the first fine are significantly higher in penalty
structures (1,9) and (3,7) relative to the other penalty structures (p
values equal .000 comparing (1,9) to (5,5), (7,3), and (9,1) and
comparing (3,7) to the constant and decreasing penalty structures). In
addition, the constant fine structure (5,5) results in significantly
more second stage offenses than the decreasing penalty structures (p
value is .0192 comparing to (7,3) and .0037 comparing to (9,1)). The
decreasing penalty structures (7,3), and (9,1) do not have significantly
different numbers of second stage offenses when subjects face the first
fine.
(28.) The following pairs are found to have significantly different
numbers of second stage offenses conditional on being caught in the
first stage with p values equal to .000: (1,9) and (5,5); (1,9) and
(7,3); (1,9) and (9,1); (3,7) and (5,5); (3,7) and (7,3); and (3,7) and
(9,1). In addition, these pairs are also significantly different: (5,5)
and (9,1) (p value = .001), and (7,3) and (9,1) (p value = .011). In
other words, conditional on being caught in the first stage the two
increasing penalty structures are not significantly different from one
another in the second stage offenses, and (5,5) does not result in
significantly more offenses than (7,3).
(29.) As noted in the previous footnote, penalty structures (9,1)
and (7,3) have significantly higher repeat offense rates than (1,9) and
(3,7). However, it is important to remember that fewer subjects have the
chance to be a repeat offender in the decreasing penalty scenarios
because few subjects choose to offend in the first stage of a decreasing
penalty structure.
(30.) We repeat our analysis separately for each context and the
results remain consistent; decreasing penalty structures result in fewer
offenses than increasing penalty structures, regardless of the context.
These results are available upon request.
(31.) The average number of times a female subject offends is 3.78
compared with 4.41 for male subjects. A Wilcoxon test rejects the
hypothesis these are equal (p value = .002). One subject did not report
gender on the survey, thus the total number of female and male subjects
is 366.
(32.) Previously, we examined consistency with theoretical
predictions across a more fine categorization of risk groups (risk
loving, risk neutral, risk averse, very risk averse, and extremely risk
averse). For the analysis on offending, we consolidate into risk averse
and not risk averse for ease of presentation. Results using the finer
risk preference categories are not qualitatively different and are
available upon request.
(33.) Subjects who are not risk averse offend an average of 4.79
times and subjects who are risk averse offend an average of 3.87 times.
The p value for the Wilcoxon testis .002. Recall that seven subjects
made an irrational decision in the Holt and Laury (2002) experiment by
choosing a certain lower payoff in one situation, resulting in 360
subjects with risk preference information.
(34.) Marginal effects from the ordered probit regression using the
margins command in STATA14 are available upon request. We find that
being risk averse increases the likelihood of not offending and
decreases the likelihood of offending 1 or 2 times. Male subjects are
also significantly less likely to offend zero times, and significantly
more likely to offend 1 or 2 times.
(35.) The marginal effects of the penalty structures are all
negative and significant relative to the baseline penalty structure of
(1,9) with p values equal to .000. In addition, we perform pairwise Wald
tests of the coefficients on the penalty structures. Each penalty
structure is significantly different from the other with p values equal
to .000 except for the pair (7,3) and (9,1).
(36.) Note that when we look at individual decisions, each subject
makes ten decisions, thus the total number of observations is now 3,590
(359 individuals with nonmissing demographic information times ten
decisions per subject).
(37.) The results for both Model 1 and Model 2 of Table 7 are
qualitatively the same when we repeat using either logit or linear
probability regression analysis. These results are available upon
request.
(38.) We separate whether a subject was caught in the first stage
of the current round from the total number of times caught because being
caught in the current penalty structure directly affects the fine the
subject is facing when making her decision. In terms of coding the
variable, we set "caught in the first stage" to be 0 for
observations in the first stage and 1 for observations in the second
stage. We also include a control for second stage decision.
(39.) Model 1 also includes an interaction term for presentation
order treatment and penalty structure.
(40.) Consistent with our previous results, Wald tests show the
coefficients on penalty structures are all significantly different from
one another (p values equal to .000) with the exception of the pair
(7,3) and (9,1).
(41.) Table 7 includes both first and second stage decisions, which
allows us to disentangle the effect of the total number of times that a
subject has been caught in the experiment from whether they were caught
in the first stage of the current period. For robustness, we repeated
the analysis of Model 1 in Table 7 for only stage 2 decisions,
controlling for whether the subject offended in the first stage. The
results are qualitatively similar to what we present in Table 7 in terms
of how risk aversion, penalty structure, number of times caught in
previous periods, and caught in first stage are correlated with
likelihood of offending in the second stage. The coefficient estimate on
gender, however, is no longer significant.
(42.) The p value for the test of whether the predicted
probabilities are different across penalty structures for nonrisk-averse
subjects is .675. For risk-averse subjects, the predicted probabilities
are significantly different with a p value of .001.
(43.) While it is worth noting that less than a quarter of our
subjects are not risk averse, we would expect that 79 nonrisk-averse
subjects would provide enough power to identify significant differences
at the 10% or 15% level.
(44.) See, for example, Anderson and Stafford (2003), Harel and
Segal (1999), DeAngelo and Chamess (2012), Friesen (2012), and
Schildberg-Horisch and Strassmair (2012).
(45.) For example, Polinsky and Rubinfeld (1991) assume that
offenders differ in their propensities to commit socially undesirable
acts. Some other models incorporate a learning-by-doing effect of crime
(Baik and Kim 2001; Garoupa and Jellal 2004; Miles and Pyne 2015; Mungan
2010). Another strand of literature justifying escalating penalties
focuses on the stigma effect of a criminal conviction, which acts as a
supplement to formal criminal penalties in deterring some offenders
(Dana 2001; Funk 2004; Miceli and Bucci 2005; Rasmusen 1996). In other
related work, Polinsky and Shavell (1998) find that, in some cases, it
is optimal to punish old first-time offenders less severely than old
repeat offenders and young first-time offenders. Recently, Curry and
Doyle (2016) developed a model of crime that includes the possibility of
legal voluntary trade; the results of this model are that optimal
penalties minimize the costs of the crime and penalties are increasing
in criminal history.
TABLE 1
Predicted Optimal Strategy by Risk Type and Penalty Structure
Penalty Structure
Range of Risk [f.sub.1] = $l [f.sub.1] = $3 [f.sub.1] = $5
Aversion [f.sub.1] = $9 [f.sub.1] = $7 [f.sub.1] = $5
r < 0 (1, 1|not (1, 1|not (1, 1)
(Risk loving) detected, detected,
0|otherwise) 0|otherwise)
r = 0 (1, 1|not (1, 1|not (1, 1)
(Risk neutral) detected, detected,
0|otherwise) 0|otherwise)
0 < r [less (1, 1|not (1, 1|not (1, 1)
than or equal detected, detected,
to] .75 0|otherwise) 0|otherwise)
(Risk averse)
.75 < r [less (1, 1|not (1, 1|not (1, 1|not
than or equal detected, detected, detected,
to] 1.17 (Very 0|otherwise) 0|otherwise) 0|otherwise)
risk averse)
r > 1.17 (1, 1|not (1, 1|not (0, 0)
(Extremely detected, detected,
risk averse) 0|otherwise) 0|otherwise)
Penalty Structure
Range of Risk [f.sub.1] = $7 [f.sub.1] = $9
Aversion [f.sub.1] = $3 [f.sub.1] = $1
r < 0 (1, 0|not detected. (0,0)
(Risk loving) 1|otherwise)
r = 0 (0, 0) or (1, 0|not (0,0)
(Risk neutral) detected,
1|otherwise)
0 < r [less (0. 0) (0, 0)
than or equal
to] .75
(Risk averse)
.75 < r [less (0,0) (0, 0)
than or equal
to] 1.17 (Very
risk averse)
r > 1.17 (0,0) (0,0)
(Extremely
risk averse)
TABLE 2
Consistency of Behavior with Theory
Penalty Structure
% Observed Strategies (Stated Strategies)
Consistent with Theory
Range of Risk [f.sub.1] = $1 [f.sub.1] = $3 [f.sub.1] = $5
Aversion [f.sub.2] = $9 [f.sub.2] = $7 [f.sub.2] = $5
r< 0 0.33 0.20 0.27
Risk loving (0.27) (0.27) (0.13)
(n = 15)
r = 0 0.59 0.52 0.31
Risk neutral (0.55) (0.48) (0.20)
(n = 64)
0 < r < .75 0.57 0.47 0.17
Risk averse (0.49) (0.36) (0.07)
(n= 182)
.75 < r < 1.17 0.64 0.48 0.23
Very risk averse (0.54) (0.36) (0.19)
(n = 66)
r > 1.17 0.68 0.37 0.74
Extremely (0.42) (0.26) (0.53)
risk averse
(n = 33)
Overall level 0.57 0.46 0.25
of consistency (0.50) (0.37) (0.15)
(by penalty
structure)
Penalty Structure
% Observed Strategies (Stated Strategies)
Consistent with Theory
Range of Risk [f.sub.1] = $7 [f.sub.1] = $9 Overall
Aversion [f.sub.2] = $3 [f.sub.2] = $1 Level of
Consistency
r< 0 0.07 0.67 0.31
Risk loving (0.00) (0.47) (0.23)
(n = 15)
r = 0 0.61 0.56 0.52
Risk neutral (0.48) (0.45) (0.43)
(n = 64)
0 < r < .75 0.63 0.69 0.51
Risk averse (0.54) (0.50) (0.39)
(n= 182)
.75 < r < 1.17 0.76 0.75 0.57
Very risk averse (0.60) (0.71) (0.48)
(n = 66)
r > 1.17 0.74 0.74 0.65
Extremely (0.58) (0.68) (0.49)
risk averse
(n = 33)
Overall level 0.64 0.68
of consistency (0.52) (0.54)
(by penalty
structure)
TABLE 3
Average Marginal Effects on Likelihood of Consistency with
Optimal Strategy
Dependent Dependent
Variable = 1 if Variable = 1 if
Stated Strategy Is Observed Strategy Is
Predicted Optimal Predicted Optimal
Strategy; 0 Otherwise Strategy; 0 Otherwise
Model 1 Model 2
(Stated Strategy) (Observed Actions)
Risk loving (r < 0) -0.203 *** -0.209 ***
(0.05) (0.05)
Risk averse (.75 -0.045 -0.017
[greater than or equal (0.03) (0.04)
to] r > 0)
Very risk averse (1.17 0.022 0.014
[greater than or equal (0.04) (0.04)
to] r > .75)
Extremely risk averse 0.033 0.116 **
(r > 1.17) (0.06) (0.05)
Male 0.087 *** 0.059 **
(0.03) (0.03)
Percentage of detected 0.0549 0.0586
chances taken (1.31) (1.53)
Caught in first stage 0.011 0.142 ***
of current period (0.03) (0.03)
Penalty structure (1,9) 0.367 *** 0.332 ***
(0.031) (0.031)
Penalty structure (3,7) 0.231 *** 0.206 ***
(0.030) (0.033)
Penalty structure (7,3) 0.384 *** 0.407 ***
(0.032) (0.034)
Penalty structure (9,1) 0.413 *** 0.456 ***
(0.031) (0.035)
N 1,795 1,795
Notes: Standard errors in parentheses. Standard errors are clustered
at the subject level. Additional controls include indicators
for each of the presented contexts, an indicator for the presentation
order treatment, and interactions of the presentation treatment
by penalty structure.
* Significance at 10%; ** significance at 5%; *** significance at 1%.
TABLE 4
Behavioral Consistency across the Two Stages of the Experiment
(1) (2) (3)
Do Not Do Not Offend in %
Offend in Stage 1 and Consistent
Fine Stage 1 Do Not Offend Decisions =
Structure in Stage 2 (2)/(l)
(1,9) 54 26 0.48
(3,7) 114 72 0.63
(5,5) 215 169 0.79
(7,3) 284 236 0.83
(9,1) 295 251 0.85
(4) (S) (6)
Offend in Offend in %
Stage 1 and Stage 1 and Consistent
Fine Are Not Caught Are Not Caught and Decisions
Structure Also Offend in Stage 2 = (5)/(4)
(1,9) 211 127 0.60
(3,7) 166 99 0.60
(5,5) 109 42 0.39
(7,3) 55 18 0.33
(9,1) 54 18 0.33
Note: The total number of subjects who participated
in the experiment is 367.
TABLE 5
Number of Subjects Facing Each Fine in Stage 2
Fine Face First Fine Face Second
Structure in Stage 2 Fine in Stage 2
(1,9) 265 102
(3,7) 280 87
(5,5) 324 43
(7,3) 339 28
(9,1) 348 19
TABLE 6
Predicted Probabilities of Outcomes
Penalty No Offenses One Offense Two Offenses
Structure
(1,9) 0.160 0.408 0.431
(3,7) 0.232 0.443 0.325
(5,5) 0.424 0.418 0.158
(7,3) 0.603 0.320 0.077
(9,1) 0.628 0.305 0.067
FIGURE 1
Total Offenses by Decision Stage and Penalty Structure
First Stage Second Stage
(1.9) 313 173
(3,7) 253 159
(5,5) 152 113
(7,3) 83 86
(9,1) 73 81
Note: For each penalty structure, there are 367 subjects making
decisions in two stages, thus the maximum number of
offenses for each decision stage is 367.
Note: Table made from bar graph.
FIGURE 2
Second Stage Offenses by Penalty Structure
Panel A: Total Offenses
Face First Fine Face Second Fine
(1.9) 155 18
(3,7) 141 18
(5,5) 88 25
(7,3) 66 20
(9,1) 62 19
Panel B: Offense Rates
Face First Fine Face Second Fine
(1,9) .585 .176
(3,7) .504 .207
(5,5) .272 .581
(7,3) .195 .714
(9,1) .178 1
Note: Table made from bar graph.
FIGURE 3
Offenses by Gender and Risk Aversion
First Stage Second Stage
No Context .513 .348
Speeding .459 .3
Cheat on Taxes .392 .281
Shoplifting .431 .362
Note: Table made from bar graph.
COPYRIGHT 2017 Western Economic Association International
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 2017 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.