首页    期刊浏览 2024年12月02日 星期一
登录注册

文章基本信息

  • 标题:Penalty structures and deterrence in a two-stage model: experimental evidence.
  • 作者:Anderson, Lisa R. ; Deangelo, Gregory ; Emons, Winand
  • 期刊名称:Economic Inquiry
  • 印刷版ISSN:0095-2583
  • 出版年度:2017
  • 期号:October
  • 出版社:Western Economic Association International
  • 摘要:I. INTRODUCTION

    Increasingly harsh penalties characterize traditional crimes such as theft and murder, but also violations of environmental and labor regulations, and tax evasion. This principle of escalating sanctions based on offense history is so widely accepted that it is embedded in many penal codes and sentencing guidelines. (1) Whether or not this weakens deterrence is a question with important policy implications. In a standard utility-maximizing framework, agents will commit first offenses with sufficiently low penalties. Moreover, if the first offense is not detected, agents will continue to commit offenses until they are convicted of a crime. We present experimental evidence that is consistent with this prediction with respect to first offenses.

    Often there are compelling reasons to have an escalating penalty structure (e.g., first-time offenders might have committed a crime by accident). (2) But there are many enforcement situations with no obvious justification for low penalties for first offenders. For example, a firm that has defrauded customers out of large sums of money might be expected to pay a fine equal to consumer harm, regardless of whether it is the firm's first offense. Furthermore, there is recent evidence that escalating sanctions are not always effective at deterring crime. For example, Sloan et al. (2013) show that increasing penalties for domestic violence do not result in reductions in future arrests and convictions. In addition, Mastrobuoni and Rivers (2016) find that incarcerated criminals discount the future at a much higher rate than noncriminals, which implies that increasing penalties may not lead to substantial decreases in recidivism.

Penalty structures and deterrence in a two-stage model: experimental evidence.


Anderson, Lisa R. ; Deangelo, Gregory ; Emons, Winand 等


Penalty structures and deterrence in a two-stage model: experimental evidence.

I. INTRODUCTION

Increasingly harsh penalties characterize traditional crimes such as theft and murder, but also violations of environmental and labor regulations, and tax evasion. This principle of escalating sanctions based on offense history is so widely accepted that it is embedded in many penal codes and sentencing guidelines. (1) Whether or not this weakens deterrence is a question with important policy implications. In a standard utility-maximizing framework, agents will commit first offenses with sufficiently low penalties. Moreover, if the first offense is not detected, agents will continue to commit offenses until they are convicted of a crime. We present experimental evidence that is consistent with this prediction with respect to first offenses.

Often there are compelling reasons to have an escalating penalty structure (e.g., first-time offenders might have committed a crime by accident). (2) But there are many enforcement situations with no obvious justification for low penalties for first offenders. For example, a firm that has defrauded customers out of large sums of money might be expected to pay a fine equal to consumer harm, regardless of whether it is the firm's first offense. Furthermore, there is recent evidence that escalating sanctions are not always effective at deterring crime. For example, Sloan et al. (2013) show that increasing penalties for domestic violence do not result in reductions in future arrests and convictions. In addition, Mastrobuoni and Rivers (2016) find that incarcerated criminals discount the future at a much higher rate than noncriminals, which implies that increasing penalties may not lead to substantial decreases in recidivism.

The literature on optimal law enforcement follows the pioneering work of Becker (1968). (3) However, Becker (1968) does not address the issue of repeat offending. Multiperiod models of criminal enforcement based on this standard economic approach generally find that the optimal penalty structure is either flat or declining. (4) In this paper, we study a two-period version of Becker's (1968) model in a lab experiment to assess whether the declining or flat penalty structures implied by theory lead to greater levels of deterrence than the commonly used increasing penalty structures. (5) We are not aware of any other experimental study that has addressed this question. (6)

We use the basic theoretical framework of Emons (2003,2004) to motivate our experimental design. In a model where criminal acts are strictly undesirable, he shows that greater deterrence is reached when fines are declining over a two-period time horizon. This theoretical result is in stark contrast to the practices embodied in penal codes. In the model, agents live for two stages and may commit an offense in each stage. (7) The agents are wealth constrained; increasing the fine for the first offense means a reduction in the sanction for the second offense and vice versa. The government seeks to minimize enforcement cost. Since the probability of being detected for a first offense is higher than the probability of being detected for two offenses, a high penalty for the first offense is a more effective use of the scarce (money penalty) resource. This result is consistent with Becker's (1968) maximal fine result; in order to minimize enforcement cost, the government uses the agent's entire wealth for sanctions in the first stage. (8)

The model of Emons (2003) assumes risk-neutral agents; however, other theoretical models have suggested individual risk preference may play a role in the decision to commit a crime. Becker (1968) shows that only risk-loving agents will be criminals under an efficient criminal justice system. Friedman (1984) shows, however, that Becker's result is driven by a corner solution where fines approach infinity, and this is not realistic. Neilson and Winter (1997) note that if certain assumptions about expected utility maximization are relaxed, it is possible for offenders to be both risk averse and more sensitive to changes in the certainty of punishment. Recently, Mungan and Klick (2014, 2015) present theoretical models that show criminals do not necessarily need to be risk loving.

We extend the Emons (2003) model to derive predictions for other levels of risk tolerance. We experimentally elicit a measure of individual's risk preference using the method of Holt and Laury (2002). Although the predicted optimal strategy within a penalty structure is generally consistent across most risk preferences, we do find that the predicted optimal strategy changes across penalty structures for subjects who are either risk loving or extremely risk averse. We then test whether subjects in a specific risk category (e.g., risk loving or highly risk averse) are more or less likely to follow the optimal strategy as predicted by theory. We find that extremely risk-averse subjects are more likely to be consistent with theory while risk-loving subjects are significantly less likely to follow predicted behavior.

Recall that Emons (2003) finds that decreasing penalty structures lead to a greater level of deterrence. Our experimental results generally confirm these predictions. We find that decreasing penalty structures result in higher deterrence than increasing or flat penalty structures. However, the decreasing penalty structures have the highest rate of repeat offenses, since the second offense has a relatively small fine. We also perform analyses on the individual decision of whether to commit the offense. In addition to finding greater levels of deterrence when subjects are faced with declining penalty structures, we observe greater offense levels when subjects are male, less risk averse, and have committed offenses in previous rounds.

We also find that being caught under previous penalty structures has a deterrent effect in the current penalty structure, even though the probability of being caught and the fine are independent of previous rounds. This suggests that subjects' perceptions about the risk of being caught are influenced by previous detection. Lochner (2007) reports a similar finding using survey-based data; specifically, young men who engage in criminal behavior and are undetected revise their likelihood of being detected downward while those detected revise their probability upward.

In the next section, we present the model that we test. Section III describes the experimental design; Sections IV, V, and VI present results; and in the final section, we offer a discussion of our results and conclude.

II. PARAMETERIZED MODEL

Agents have initial wealth, w= 10, and maximize expected utility by making decisions in two stages. In each stage, an agent can engage in an illegal activity with a monetary benefit, b = 2. The government seeks to deter individuals from engaging in the illegal activity by choosing a two-part fine structure of the format ([f.sub.1], [f.sub.2]). (9) The first sanction, [f.sub.1], applies to the first-detected offense, and the second sanction, [f.sub.2], applies to the second-detected offense. The government cannot confiscate more than the agent's wealth, thus [f.sub.1] + [f.sub.2] [less than or equal to] w. (10) Throughout the experiment, we set [f.sub.1] + [f.sub.2] = 10 so as to be consistent with Emons (2003). Moreover, the government sets the level of detection that determines the probability that an offense will be detected, p = 1/3. (11) Since we hold p and the overall level of the fines constant, any variation in observed behavior (i.e., the decision to commit) may be attributed to whether fines are increasing or decreasing.

To derive the optimal decision for each fine structure, we compare expected utility levels associated with all possible strategy sets, ([a.sub.1], [a.sub.2]), where [a.sub.1] represents the action taken by the agent in the first stage and [a.sub.2] represents the action taken by the agent in the second stage. We let ([a.sub.1], [a.sub.2]) be represented by 0 if the agent does not engage in the illegal activity and 1 if the agent does engage in the illegal activity. Thus, there are four possible strategy sets to consider that are not history dependent: (0, 0), (1, 1), (0, 1), and (1, 0). The agent also can choose between two history-dependent strategies. First, she commits the criminal act in stage 1 and then commits the criminal act in stage 2 only if she is not detected in stage 1. We call this strategy (1, [1]not detected; 0|other-wise]). Alternatively, she commits the act in stage 1, and then commits the act in stage 2 only if she is detected in stage 1. We call this strategy (1, [0|not detected; 1|otherwise]). (12)

Emons (2003) assumes that agents are risk neutral. However, we know from a plethora of experimental studies that, on average, subjects tend to be slightly risk averse. (13) For this reason, we generalize risk preferences by assuming constant absolute risk aversion. Following Holt and Laury (2002), let

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],

where x denotes income and r measures risk aversion: for r < 0 the agent is risk loving, for r = 0 she is risk neutral, and for r > 0, she is risk averse. The following set of equations describes the expected utilities for all possible strategy sets ([a.sub.1], [a.sub.2])

(1) E [U (0,0)] = U (w)

(2) E[U(1,1)] = [p.sup.2]U(w + 2b - [f.sub.1] - [f.sub.2]) + 2p(1 - p) U (w + 2b - [f.sub.1]) + [(1 - p).sup.2] U (w + 2b)

(3) E[U(0,1)1 = E[U(1, 0)] = pU(w + b - [f.sub.1]) + (1 - p)(w + b)

(4) E [U (1, (1 |not detected; 0| otherwise))] = pU (w + b - [f.sub.1]) + (1 - p) pU (w + 2b - [f.sub.1]) + [(1 - p).sup.2] U (w + 2b)

(5) E[U(1, (0|notdetected; 1 |otherwise))] = [p.sup.2]U (w + 2b - [f.sub.1] - [f.sub.2]) +(1 - p)U(w + b) + (1 - p)pU (w + 2b - [f.sub.1])

Note from Equation (1) that an agent who never plans to commit an offense will not earn the benefit, and will not pay any fines. Hence, her expected utility is her initial wealth, adjusted for her risk preference. For example, if she is risk neutral, then r = 0 and expected utility is equal to wealth. Also note from Equation (3) that if an agent plans to commit an offense in one stage only, expected utility does not vary depending on whether the offense is committed in the first or second stage. In this case, with probability p, the offense will be detected, and the agent will earn her initial wealth (w) plus the benefit of committing the offense (b) minus the fine for being detected for a first offense ([f.sub.1]). And with probability 1 -p, the offense will not be detected, and the agent will earn her initial wealth plus the benefit of committing the offense. The expected utilities for strategies that involve multiple offenses or contingent strategies are less intuitive because of compound probabilities. Following from this set of equations, Table 1 shows the predicted optimal strategy for each penalty structure over a range of risk aversion. We chose the risk-tolerance categories in Table 1 to show the points where the optimal strategy for a particular penalty structure changes with risk tolerance.

Note from the first column of Table 1 that agents will always commit an offense when the penalty is $1 regardless of risk preference, since the benefit ($2) exceeds the penalty ($1). In general, Table 1 shows that the penalty structures with decreasing fines achieve higher deterrence, as indicated by the (0, 0) optimal strategy sets, than the constant or increasing fine schemes. This is even more pronounced for risk-averse agents. Recall that the model assumes rational forward-looking agents who view each stage within a penalty structure as interrelated; whether an agent offends in the first stage depends on the fine for the second offense. This forward-looking behavior is a key assumption of the model for the following reason. The agent can only be apprehended for a second crime after she has already been apprehended for a first crime, meaning that the agent pays the first sanction with probability 1/3 and the second sanction with probability 1/9. Since paying the first fine is more likely than paying the second one, shifting resources from the second to the first sanction increases deterrence. (14) Table 1 also shows that even with relatively high levels of risk aversion, the model predicts that some offenses will be committed in the schemes with increasing sanctions. The constant fine scheme leads to the highest level of predicted offenses and is also the most sensitive to risk tolerance.

III. EXPERIMENTAL DESIGN

We conducted 35 experimental sessions at the College of William and Mary in Virginia, USA. Participants were recruited from oncampus advertisements to participate in paid economics experiments. A total of 367 undergraduate students participated in the experiment and no person was permitted to participate in more than one session. The number of subjects in each session ranged from 4 to 14, and sessions lasted approximately 45 minutes. Subjects began each session by completing the Holt and Laury (2002) lottery choice experiment using the Internet-based Veconlab website. (15)

After completing the lottery choice experiment to elicit a measure of individual risk-aversion, subjects completed another computerized experiment that was programmed and administered using z-tree (Fischbacher 2007). The experiment was divided into five periods, with each period corresponding to a different enforcement regime (i.e., fine structure). (16) Subjects were endowed with $10 at the beginning of each period, and they faced two decision-making stages within the period. In a context-free treatment, subjects could "take a chance" or not. Every time a subject chose to take a chance, she earned an additional $2 but she also faced a 1 in 3 chance of being "checked" and financially penalized. Thus, a subject could earn an additional $4 but could also pay two separate fines each period. Subjects received feedback about whether or not they were checked after every decision made, regardless of whether or not they took a chance. (17) The complete instructions for the context-free experiment are available in the Appendix. Instructions for the lottery choice experiment and all version of the deterrence experiment are available upon request.

All subjects made decisions for each of five different enforcement regimes denoted (1,9), (3,7), (5,5), (7,3), and (9,1), where the first number is the fine associated with the first-detected offense and the second number is the fine for the second-detected offense within a given period. At the beginning of each period, subjects were told the relevant fines for the two stages in that period, but they were not told fines for future periods. In every decision-making period, subjects were asked what decisions they planned to make before they committed to the actual decisions that affected their earnings; below we refer to these responses as the subjects' stated strategies as opposed to the observed behavior with actual earnings. In the discussion that follows, we refer to the enforcement regimes with a higher fine for the second offense as increasing fine regimes (i.e., (1,9) and (3,7)) and the regimes with a higher fine for the first offense as decreasing fine regimes (i.e., (7,3) and (9,1)).

To control for possible order effects, there were two treatments that differed in the order in which enforcement regimes were presented to subjects. Approximately half of the subjects saw the five regimes in the order treatment presented above, with relatively low first-offense fines in periods 1 and 2. The other subjects saw the five regimes in the following order treatment: (9,1), (7,3), (5,5), (3,7), and (1,9). To avoid wealth effects, subjects were told that one of the five periods would be randomly chosen for payment at the end of the experiment. Subject earnings averaged $10.54 for the deterrence experiment.

IV. CONSISTENCY OF BEHAVIOR WITH THEORY

In this section, we first focus on the correlation between theoretical predictions and observed behavior. Regardless of whether or not the experiment was presented to subjects with context, for ease of exposition we use the term "offend" to describe all subject choices that correspond to committing the crime.

A. Descriptive Statistics

We begin our empirical analysis by examining the frequency with which behavior is consistent with the theoretically predicted strategy. (18) Table 2 reports the proportion of subjects in all sessions who play the predicted strategy. (19) Recall that subjects were also asked to state the strategy that they planned to follow in the experiment prior to making actual decisions. Table 2 also reports the proportion of these "stated strategies" that are consistent with theory in parentheses. These results are reported for each of five risk-tolerance categories shown in Table 1, (20)

Looking at the overall level of consistency between theory and behavior, we find that the extremely risk-averse subjects and subjects facing the decreasing penalty structures are most likely to follow the theorized strategy. Risk-loving subjects and subjects who face a constant fine structure are least likely to follow the theorized strategy. Recall that the model predicts the highest level of offenses under this fine structure. We find that the most commonly used strategy in the (5,5) penalty structure is for subjects never to commit an offense. This nonoptimal strategy of (0, 0) was followed by 46% of the subjects. Table 2 also shows that for each penalty structure, actual behavior is closer to theoretical predictions than subjects' stated strategies. (21)

Overall, we find that about two-thirds of subjects choose the predicted optimal strategy in the decreasing fine structures, but for some other penalty structures less than half of the subjects make decisions that are consistent with theory. A possible explanation for inconsistencies between theory and observed behavior is that agents are myopic and treat each stage as a one-shot decision. Consider the simplest example, where agents are risk neutral. In this case, given that the benefit of the crime is $2 and the probability of apprehension is 1/3, myopic risk-neutral agents will commit the act as long as the fine is less than $6. We would expect myopic risk-averse subjects to still commit when the fine is somewhat lower than $6 (the exact amount depends on the risk parameter). But, in situations where myopic behavior predicts offenses will be committed under risk neutrality, we observe offense rates of 75%, 61%, and 35% with the $1 fine, the $3 fine, and the $5 fine, respectively. In the situation where we expect no offenses with myopic behavior under risk neutrality, we observe a 21% offense rate with the $7 fine and a 19% offense rate with the $9 fine. These offense rates do not support the idea that people consider each stage decision separately. These aggregate results also suggest that risk tolerance affects whether or not behavior follows theory.

B. Econometric Analysis of Behavioral Deviations from Theory

As noted above, the observed behavior in our experiment is not always consistent with the predicted optimal choices. Across all risk preferences and penalty structures, only 52% of observed actions follow the predicted strategy. Additionally, 42% of stated strategies are consistent with predicted optimal behavior. (22) In this section, we explore which factors drive a subject to deviate from the predicted behavior. We begin by defining two variables: (1) an indicator for whether the subject's stated strategy is equal to the optimal strategy and (2) an indicator for whether the observed strategy is equal to the optimal strategy. Recall from the experimental design section that we elicit each subject's stated strategy for each penalty structure before they actually face that penalty structure with monetary consequences.

In Table 3 we examine a variety of factors that may be driving deviations from the predicted optimal strategy, as determined by theory. In Model 1, we estimate and provide the marginal effects from a probit model where the outcome is a binary variable for whether the stated strategy is consistent with theoretically predicted behavior. Model 2 presents the marginal effects from the probit regression where the outcome is the binary variable for whether observed behavior is consistent with theory. Consistency with predicted optimal strategy is dependent on the subject's individual risk profile as presented in Table 1. We include indicators for the subject's risk category: risk loving (r < 0), risk neutral (r = 0), risk averse (.75 [greater than or equal to] r > 0), very risk averse (1.17 [greater than or equal to] r >. 75), and extremely risk averse (r > 1.17) groups. The omitted category is risk-neutral subjects. We also include information about whether the subject was caught in the first stage of the penalty structure, the percentage of times that the subject was detected when they committed an offense, as well as information about the penalty structure, presentation order of treatments, dummy variables for the three contexts, and a dummy variable for whether the subject was male.

Our results provide some interesting insights regarding deviations from the predicted optimal strategy. Overall, stated strategies and observed actions are relatively similar in terms of which characteristics are correlated with the probability of being consistent with the optimal strategy. Male subjects are more likely than female subjects to both state a strategy that is consistent with the optimal strategy and choose actual behavior consistent with theory. Risk-loving subjects are approximately 21% more likely to deviate from the optimal strategy than risk-neutral subjects. Extremely risk-averse subjects are more likely to take actions that are consistent with the optimal strategies than risk-neutral subjects; however, this is not the case in their stated strategies. We know from Table 2 that the lowest level of consistency is observed with penalty structure (5,5). Using (5,5) as the reference category in our probit analysis, we confirm that after controlling for subject heterogeneity, the increasing and decreasing penalty structures exhibit higher levels of consistency with theory than the flat penalty structure. Overall, our results indicate that the predictive power of the model depends on the penalty structure and on subject-specific characteristics. (23)

V. CONSISTENCY OF BEHAVIOR ACROSS DECISION-MAKING STAGES

In addition to examining consistency with theory, we next focus on whether individuals make the same decision each time they face the same fine. This analysis provides further evidence that subjects treat the two decision-making stages within a penalty structure as interrelated. Table 4 displays the consistency of behavior across the two stages of the experiment when subjects face the same fine at different stages. Since we are comparing behavior across two decisions for the same subject, we aggregated these results over all risk preference types.

Column 1 shows the total number of subjects who choose not to offend in stage 1 for each penalty structure. Of those subjects who do not offend in stage 1, column 2 shows the number who also did not offend in stage 2. Note that these subjects face the same fine in stage 2 as they did in stage 1, since they did not offend in stage 1. Thus, we would expect subjects who treat each stage as a one-shot decision to make the same decisions in these two stages. Column 3 presents the percentage of subjects who made consistent decisions across stages when facing the same fine. A surprisingly large number of subjects make different decisions across the two stages, despite facing the same fine. The lack of consistency in choosing not to offend across these two columns could be evidence of learning or evidence that the two-stage nature of the problem affects the way subjects make each individual decision. Note also that consistency across columns 1 and 2 is largest for the decreasing fine structures, providing evidence that high first fines deter offenses regardless of stage.

The right-hand side of Table 4 examines an alternative situation where subjects face the same fine in both stages of decision-making; here we focus on the decision to offend. Column 4 shows the number of subjects who offend in stage 1, but are not caught. Column 5 shows how many of those people go on to offend again in stage 2. Again, with subjects who treat each stage as independent, we expect everyone to offend in stage 1 under the increasing and constant fine structures and no one to offend under the decreasing fine structures, regardless of their risk type. Since column 4 is conditional on subjects not being caught in stage 1, the same predictions hold for column 5.

We find very low rates of consistency in offending between the two stages with decreasing and flat penalty structures, and only 60% consistency in the increasing fine structures for this comparison of offending when subjects are facing the same fine. This finding is a puzzle and might be evidence of confusion on the part of subjects about what fine they are actually facing, despite playing practice rounds and having the fine structure explained in detail. Another possible explanation for the lack of consistency is decreasing marginal utility of the $2 gain from offending. Recall that subjects start with $10 and those who offend in stage 1 and are not caught receive $2. Because they start stage 2 with $12, the potential $2 gain from offending in stage 2 adds less utility than it added in stage 1. If this is driving the lack of consistency, we might expect to find different levels of risk tolerance for subjects who are consistent across stages compared with subjects who are not consistent. For most penalty structures, Wilcoxon tests show no difference in risk tolerance between subjects who are not consistent across stages and those who are. However, for penalty structures (5,5) and (7,3), we find that subjects who are not consistent are more risk averse than those who are consistent across stages. (24)

Alternatively, the lack of consistency may be evidence of loss aversion with an endowment effect. The subject has taken the risk to earn $2 in the first stage and succeeded. The potential loss of the fine is more painful now that the subject has $12 relative to the foregone gain of $2 in the second stage, causing some subjects to choose not to take the risk in the second stage. Unfortunately, we cannot test for loss aversion given the experimental design and information collected. Another possible explanation for inconsistency here is an irrational belief by subjects that they are more likely to be caught in stage 2 after avoiding detection in stage 1. Inconsistent choices could also be the result of learning or taking the two-stage decision into account. While we speculate here about what is driving the lack of consistency finding, in Section VI.B we attempt to isolate the factors influencing the general decisions to offend using econometric analysis.

VI. DETERRENCE

Next we turn our attention to identifying which enforcement regimes yield the greatest level of deterrence. We also examine the individual characteristics correlated with the decision to offend.

A. Descriptive Statistics

Figure 1 shows the total number of offenses by decision stage and enforcement regime. The most striking observation is that increasing fine regimes have over twice as many offenses as decreasing fine regimes. (25) The constant fine mechanism has fewer offenses relative to increasing enforcement regimes, but more offenses compared to decreasing fine regimes. In short, we find descriptive evidence consistent with the theoretical prediction that a decreasing, rather than increasing penalty structure, yields greater specific deterrence. (26)

Figure 1 also shows how offense rates vary across the two stages of decision-making. Note that the number of offenses falls sharply between the first and second stage in the increasing fine regimes. This is not surprising since first stage offense rates are relatively high in these two regimes, which means that relatively more people get caught and face the high penalty associated with a second offense in the second stage of these regimes. On the other hand, the number of offenses is fairly constant across the two decision stages in the decreasing sanction schemes. While committing an offense in the first stage is not predicted to be optimal under these schemes, if a subject offends and is caught in the first stage, utility maximization predicts the subject will recommit in the second stage. Note, however, that Figure 1 provides no information about which fine subjects face in the second stage, because it does not distinguish between people who committed an offense and were caught in the first stage and those who were not caught.

Table 5 provides the number of subjects who face the first fine or second fine in stage 2. Subjects who face the first fine in stage 2 either did not commit an offense or they committed an offense and were not caught in the first stage. Subjects who face the second fine in the penalty structure represent those who committed an offense and were caught in the first stage. Consistent with Figure 1, the number of subjects facing the second fine in stage 2 is decreasing with the first fine, as fewer subjects commit an offense at all in the first stage when facing a decreasing penalty structure ((7,3) or (9,1)).

Figure 2 focuses on second stage decisions and provides information about offenses and the specific fine faced by the subject. Panel A of Figure 2 shows that among subjects who face the first fine, there are significantly more second stage offenses in the increasing penalty structures than in the decreasing penalty structures. (27) For those subjects who face the second fine, very few second stage offenses are committed overall, but there are more second stage offenses in the constant and decreasing penalty structures than in the increasing penalty structures. (28)

Panel B of Figure 2 presents the second stage offense data in percentage terms. For each bar in Panel A, we divide the number of offenses committed in that scenario by the total number of decisions made. This figure reveals that recidivism rates among those who were caught in the first stage are much higher in the decreasing penalty structures than in the increasing penalty structures. (29) For example, all 19 subjects who offended and were caught in the first stage under the (9,1) penalty structure offended again in the second stage. As noted above, given that a subject makes the irrational decision to commit a first stage offense in the (7,3) or (9,1) penalty structure and gets caught, the optimal second stage decision is to recidivate.

Overall, the graphs of offense levels and rates suggest that our results are consistent with the theoretical model of Emons (2003); decreasing penalty structures lead to higher levels of deterrence than increasing penalty structures. (30) However, there may also be potentially confounding effects of individual characteristics on offending.

In addition to whether the fine structure is increasing or decreasing, individual subject characteristics may play a role in how likely the subjects are to choose to offend. Figure 3 provides details on how many offenses subjects commit by gender and risk tolerance. Notice that fewer than 20 subjects never commit an offense and only 13 commit 9 or 10 offenses. Figure 3 also shows that female subjects are significantly more likely than male subjects to commit a lower number of offenses. (31) We also divide our sample into those who are risk averse and those who are not risk averse based on their decisions on the Holt and Laury (2002) lottery choice experiment. (32) As the figure suggests, risk-averse subjects commit significantly fewer total offenses than those who are not risk averse. (33)

B. Econometric Analysis of Deterrence

Given that demographic characteristics appear to be correlated with the frequency of offending, we examine the effect of the penalty scheme on deterrence by running an ordered probit of total offenses within a penalty structure controlling for the subject's gender, a dummy for whether the subject is risk averse, context, presentation order treatment, and an indicator for whether the subject was caught in the first stage. (34) Based on these probit results, we calculate the predicted probability that an individual never commits an offense, commits an offense one time, or commits an offense in both stages under a particular penalty structure. These results are presented in Table 6.

Individuals are most likely to commit no offenses in the decreasing penalty regime (where there is a higher first stage penalty). On the other hand, increasing penalty structures have the highest predicted rate of subjects committing two offenses (at 43% and 33%), perhaps because individuals who are not caught in the first stage have high incentives to recidivate. Even after controlling for individual characteristics, the overall implication of Table 6 is that decreasing penalty structures are far more effective in deterring offenses and are more likely to result in zero offenses than increasing penalty structures given our parameterized model. (35)

While Table 6 shows that a decreasing fine structure reduces the overall number of offenses, we have not examined the impact of fine structures on the individual choice to commit offenses in each stage. To do so, we run probit regressions on the individual decision of whether or not to offend in each stage. (36) Table 7 presents the marginal effects from the analysis. (37) We control for subject characteristics (male, dummy for whether the subject is risk averse), the presentation order treatment, the context, the number of times a subject has offended in previous rounds, the number of times a subject has been caught in previous rounds (excluding the first stage of the current round), and an indicator for whether the subject was caught in the first stage of the particular round. (38) To isolate the effect of the penalty structure, in Model 1, we include controls for whether the decision is a second stage decision and an indicator for each penalty structure. (39) Errors are clustered at the subject level to account for potential correlation across the ten individual decisions.

The results at the individual level confirm the aggregate results; the coefficients on the decreasing fine structures (7,3) and (9,1) are significantly different from the omitted category penalty structure (5,5). (40) By disaggregating the data to the individual level decisions, we also observe some phenomena that we did not observe in the aggregated data. Subjects who offend more often are almost 9 percentage points more likely to continue to offend in the particular stage. Moreover, the average marginal effect of an additional instance of being caught in previous penalty structures decreases the likelihood of offending by slightly more than 2 percentage points, even though being caught under a previous penalty structure has no impact on the current period's potential payoffs. This is suggestive of a specific deterrence effect; subjects respond to previous punishment experience even when that previous punishment is not affecting the current cost of offending. Last, we find that being caught in the first stage reduces the probability of offending in the second stage by about 15 percentage points (in addition to the 16 percentage point reduction in probability of offending that exists for the average second stage decision). (41)

Model 2 addresses the issue of the penalty structure in a slightly different way. Instead of including indicator variables for each penalty structure, we include an indicator variable to capture whether subjects are making decisions under an increasing fine scheme. We also include a variable to capture the separate effect of the specific fine faced by the subject. The qualitative results from Model 1 hold, with one exception. The coefficient on the indicator variable for being caught in the first stage is no longer significant. Model 2 reveals that, independent of the specific fine faced for any given decision, facing an increasing penalty structure increases the probability a subject will commit an offense by slightly more than 5%. This provides additional evidence that subjects take the two-stage nature of the decision into account when making decisions and are less deterred by increasing penalty structures.

Recall that one implication of Becker (1968) is that criminals tend to be risk-seeking. We repeat the analysis of Model 2 in Table 7 with the inclusion of an interaction between risk aversion and type of penalty structure (increasing penalty vs. decreasing/flat penalty structure). We then predict the probability of offending in order to examine whether the likelihood of offending for types of subjects varies across increasing and decreasing/flat penalty structures. The predicted probability of offending for nonrisk-averse subjects is .468 in the decreasing/flat penalty structures and .452 in the increasing penalty structures, which is not significantly different. Alternatively, risk-averse subjects respond significantly differently to the penalty structures. For risk-averse subjects, the predicted probability of offending in decreasing/flat penalty structures is .359 and .435 for increasing penalty structures. (42) It appears that the differential in offense rates across penalty structures is largely due to the subjects who are risk averse rather those who are not. (43)

VII. CONCLUSION

There is a large literature on optimal law enforcement following the pioneering work of Becker (1968). For example, Emons (2003, 2004) presents multiperiod models of criminal enforcement based on the standard Becker approach and finds that decreasing penalties result in greater deterrence. As is standard in this literature, he models the law enforcer's joint choice of the probability of detection and the penalty if detected. A number of experimental papers have examined the trade-off between the probability of detection and the penalty if detected in a repeated one-shot decision. (44) To our knowledge, however, we present the first experimental study to examine whether increasing or decreasing penalty schemes are better at deterring risky behavior.

We chose the basic model of Emons (2003) as the starting point for our design. We find that decreasing, rather than increasing, sanction schemes provides higher deterrence in our repeated decision-making situation. Although numerous arguments have been put forth for the use of increasing penalty schemes, our results suggest that decreasing penalty schemes yield higher rates of deterrence. The relative simplicity of the model might explain why the theoretical prediction is different from the increasing sanctions we observe in most penal codes. For example, the model does not include costs to criminals other than the fine, and thus, does not take into account a potential desire of policymakers to educate first offenders or to minimize stigma. A related concern is that someone might be erroneously convicted of a first offense. Additionally, the model does not include political aspects of policymaking such as the fear that harsh sanctions might be viewed as unjust. By incorporating special features, some multiperiod models support the use of escalating penalties in a Becker-style model. (45) A natural extension of our study is to incorporate more complicated theoretical assumptions into our experimental design.

Although we find evidence that decreasing penalties provide higher deterrence, observed behavior is only consistent with the theoretical prediction in 52% of the decision-making periods. When we examine the relationship between individual characteristics and consistency with theory, we find that extreme risk preferences (risk loving and extremely risk averse) are correlated with the likelihood of consistency, as well as the gender of the subject. Consistency with theory also increases with previous detection, suggesting the penalty and potential effect on expected utility become more salient as the subject experiences being caught.

Additionally, we explore some behavioral features of the decision-making process that are not predicted by the rational decision-making model. We observe greater offense levels when subjects are male, less risk averse, and have committed offenses in previous rounds. We also observe that being caught under previous penalty structures has a small deterrence effect in the current penalty structure, even though both the probability of being caught and the fine are independent of previous rounds. Even after controlling for the specific fine a subject faces, we find that the probability of committing an offense is higher under an increasing penalty regime. When we examine subject responses to current fines faced, we also find evidence that subjects treat the choice to offend in each stage as part of a two-stage interrelated decision (i.e., subjects consider the full penalty structure of the period) and do not respond solely to the amount of the fine.

APPENDIX

SCREENSHOTS OF EXPERIMENT

This experiment consists of 5 periods with 2 stages each, so you will make a total of 10 decisions. At the end of the experiment, we will randomly pick one of the 5 periods to determine your payoff. Ail of the periods are equally likely to be chosen to determine your payoff, so you should think carefully about each of the10 decisions.

Please enter the given ID in here

In each period you will have two stages in which you have to decide if you want to TAKE A CHANCE or NOT TAKE A CHANCE. You begin each period with $10. Each time you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will earn an extra $2. In every stage you face the possibility of being observed, if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are observed then you will lose money. If you choose to NOT TO TAKE A CHANCE and are observed you will not lose money, but you will also not earn extra money.

To determine whether or not you are being observed, the computer will generate a random number equally likely to be 1,2, or 3. If the random number is 3, you will be observed. Hence, the chance of being observed is 1 in 3. You will lose money only if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED.

Each of the 5 periods has a different payoff structure, so be sure that you understand the payoff structure in each period before you make your decisions.

Now you will play a practice period to help you understand how the game works. This practice period will have 2 stages just like the 5 actual periods you will play in a moment. Because this is a practice period, your decisions in this period will NOT affect your actual earnings today.

Remember: You begin with an initial payment of $10.

Every time you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will receive an extra $2, but you face a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED. If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED, then you will lose money as described on the next screen. If you choose to NOT TAKE A CHANCE, and you are OBSERVED, then you will not lose money, but you will also not earn extra money.

Before we start the practice period, we would like to know what your strategy wiH most likely look like. The table below will help you understand the payoff that you will receive for different possible decisions.

You begin with an initial payment of $10. If you are OBSERVED and It is the first time you have been OSBERVED in this practice period, you will lose $1. If you are OBSERVED and it is the second time you have been OBSERVED in this practice period, you will lose $9.

Before we start the practice period we would like to know what your strategy will most likely look like.

In every stage, if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will always receive an extra $2 but you face a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED.

If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the first time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the practice period, you will lose $1. If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the practice period, you will lose $9.

In the 1st stage I would most likely choose to

TAKE A CHANCE NOT TAKE A CHANCE

Before we start the practice period we would like to know what your strategy will most likely look like.

In every stage, if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will always receive an extra $2 but you face a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED.

If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the first time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the practice period, you will lose $1. If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the practice period, you will lose $9.

If I was OBSERVED in the 1st stage, in the 2nd stage I would most likely choose to

* TAKE A CHANCE * NOT TAKE A CHANCE

If I was NOT OSERVED in the 1st stage, in the 2nd stage I would most likely choose to

* TAKE A CHANCE

* NOT TAKE A CHANCE

In the 1st stage you chose to TAKE A CHANCE.

Practice Period - Stage 1

Remember: You begin with an initial payment of $10.

Every time you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will receive an extra $2. In every stage you face a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED. If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and you are OBSERVED, then you will lose money as described below. If you choose to NOT TAKE A CHANCE and you are OBSERVED, then you will not lose money, but you also win not earn extra money. There is a possibility you will lose money if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED. (Note: In each stage you face the possibility of losing money only if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE. However, you wifl only earn extra money if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE.)

If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and It is the first time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the practice period, you will lose $1.

If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and It is the second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE, and have been OBSERVED in the practice period, you will lose $9.

PLEASE CHOOSE NOW

* TAKE A CHANCE

* NOT TAKE A CHANCE

Practice Period 1--Stage 1

You have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE. Are you sure about your choice?

You have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE.

As this is just a practice period, NO ONE was OBSERVED.

Therefore your payoff would be $10 + $2 = $12.

Practice Period 1--Stage 2

Once again, you must choose whether you want to TAKE A CHANCE or NOT TAKE A CHANCE. Every time you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will receive an additional $2. There is a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED. If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and you are OBSERVED, then you win lose money as described below. If you choose to NOT TAKE A CHANCE and you are OBSERVED you will not lose money, but you will also not earn extra money.

If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the first time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the practice period, you will lose $1.

If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the practice period, you will lose $9.

PLEASE CHOOSE NOW

* TAKE A CHANCE

* NOT TAKE A CHANCE

Practice Period 1--Stage 2

You have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE. Are you sure about your choice?

You have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE.

As this is just a practice period. NO ONE was OBSERVED.

Therefore your payoff for the practice period would be $14.

Questions?

If you have any questions about the game or If something Is unclear please raise your hand and we will come to your desk to answer It.

Get Ready!

Now you will start playing the actual gamel

This Is the 1st period!

Before we start the 1st period, we would like to know what your strategy will most likely look like. The table below will help you understand the payoff that you will receive for different possible decisions.

You begin with an initial payment of $10. If you are OBSERVED and it is the first time you have been OSBERVED in this practice period, you will lose $1. If you are OBSERVED and it is the second time you have been OBSERVED in this practice period, you will lose $9.

Before we start the 1st period we would like to know what your strategy will most likely look like.

In every stage, if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will always receive an extra $2 but you face a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED.

If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the first time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the 1st period, you will lose $1. If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the 1st period, you will lose $9.

In the 1st stage I would most likely choose to

* TAKE A CHANCE

* NOT TAKE A CHANCE

Before we start the 1st period we would like to know what your strategy will most likely look like.

In every stage, if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will always receive an extra $2 but you face a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED.

If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the first time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the 1st period, you will lose $1. If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the 1st period, you will lose $9.

In the 1st stage you chose to TAKE A CHANCE.

If I was OBSERVED in the 1st stage, in the 2nd stage I would most likely choose to

* TAKE A CHANCE * NOT TAKE A CHANCE

If I was NOT OBSERVED in the 1st stage, in the 2nd stage I would most likely choose to

* TAKE A CHANCE

* NOT TAKE A CHANCE

Period 1 - Stage 1

Remember You begin with an initial payment of $10.

Every time you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will receive an extra $2. In every stage you face a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED. If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and you are OBSERVED, then you will lose money as described below. If you choose to NOT TAKE A CHANCE and you are OBSERVED, then you will not lose money, but you also will not earn extra money. There Is a possibility you will lose money if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED. (Note: In each stage you face the possibility of losing money only if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE. However, you will only earn extra money If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE.)

If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and It is the first time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the 1st period, you will lose $1. If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE, and have been OBSERVED in the 1st period, you will lose $9.

PLEASE CHOOSE NOW

* TAKE A CHANCE

* NOT TAKE A CHANCE

Period 1 - Stage 1

You have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE. Are you sure about your choice?

You have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE. Because you were NOT OBSERVED you will not lose money.

Therefore your payoff is $10 + $2 = $12.

Period 1 - Stage 2

Once again, you must choose whether you want to TAKE A CHANCE or NOT TAKE A CHANCE. Every time you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will receive an additional $2. There is a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED. If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and you are OBSERVED, then you will lose money as described below If you choose to NOT TAKE A CHANCE and you are OBSERVED you will not lose money, but you will also not earn extra money.

If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and It is the first time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the 1st period, you will lose $1.

If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the 1st period, you will lose $9.

PLEASE CHOOSE NOW

* TAKE A CHANCE

* NOT TAKE A CHANCE

Period 1 - Stage 2

You have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE. Are you sure about your choice?

You have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE. Because you were OBSERVED you will lose money.

Therefore your payoff tor this period is $13

This Is the 2nd period!

Before we start the 2nd period, we would like to know what your strategy will most likely look like. The table below will help you understand the payoff that you will receive for different possible decisions.

You begin with an initial payment of $10. If you are OBSERVED and it is the first time you have been OSBERVED in this practice period, you will lose $3. If you are OBSERVED and it is the second time you have been OBSERVED in this practice period, you will lose $7.

Before we start the 2nd period we would like to know what your strategy will most likely look like.

In every stage, if you choose to TAKE A CHANCE you will always receive an extra $2 but you face a 1 in 3 chance of being OBSERVED.

If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the first time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the 2nd period, you will lose $3. If you choose to TAKE A CHANCE and are OBSERVED and it is the second time you have chosen to TAKE A CHANCE and have been OBSERVED in the 2nd period, you will lose $7.

In the 1st stage I would most likely choose to

* TAKE A CHANCE

* NOT TAKE A CHANCE

doi: 10.1111/ecin.12464

REFERENCES

Anderson, L., and M. Mellor. "Predicting Health Behaviors with an Experimental Measure of Risk Preference." Journal of Health Economics, 27(5), 2008, 1260-74.

--. "Are Risk Preferences Stable? Comparing an Experimental Measure with a Validated Survey-Based Measure." Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 39(2), 2009, 137-60.

Anderson, L., and S. Stafford. "Punishment in a Regulatory Setting: Experimental Evidence from the VCM." Journal of Regulatory Economics, 24(1), 2003, 91-110.

Arlen, J., and E. Taylor. Experimental Law and Economics. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar Publishing, 2008.

Baik, K. H., and I.-G. Kim. "Optimal Punishment When Individuals May Learn Deviant Values." International Review of Law and Economics, 21, 2001, 271-85.

Bar-Ilan, A., and B. Sacerdote. "Response to Fines and Probabilities in a Natural Experiment." Journal of Law and Economics, 47(1), 2004, 1-17.

Bebchuck, L., and L. Kaplow. "Optimal Sanctions When Individuals Are Imperfectly Informed about the Probability of Apprehension." Journal of Legal Studies, 21, 1993, 365-70.

Becker, G. "Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach." Journal of Political Economy, 76, 1968, 169-217.

Ben-Shahar, O. "Playing without a Rulebook": Optimal Enforcement When Individuals Learn the Penalty only by Committing the Crime." International Review of Law and Economics, 17, 1997,409-21.

Brandts, J., and G. Chamess. "Truth or Consequences: An Experiment." Management Science, 49, 2003, 116-30.

--. "The Strategy versus the Direct-Response Method: A First Survey of Experimental Comparisons." Experimental Economics, 14, 2011, 375-98.

Brosig, J., J. Weimann, and C. L. Yang. "The Hot versus Cold Effect in a Simple Bargaining Experiment." Experimental Economics, 6, 2003, 75-90.

Bumovski, M., and Z. Safra. "Deterrence Effects of Sequential Punishment Policies: Should Repeat Offenders Be More Severely Punished?" International Review of Law and Economics, 14, 1994, 341-50.

Camerer, C., and E. Talley. "Experimental Law and Economics," in Handbook of Law and Economics, edited by M. Polinsky and S. Shavell. Amsterdam: North-Holland, 2007, 1619-50.

Casari, M., and T. Cason. "The Strategy Method Lowers Measured Trustworthy Behavior." Economics Letters, 103, 2009, 157-59.

Chu, C., S. Hu, and T. Huang. "Punishing Repeat Offenders More Severely." International Review of Law and Economics, 20, 2000, 127-40.

Curry, P., and M. Doyle. "Integrating Market Alternatives into the Economic Theory of Optimal Deterrence." Economic Inquiry, 54(4), 2016, 1873-83.

Dana, D. A. "Rethinking the Puzzle of Escalating Penalties for Repeat Offenders." The Yale Law Journal, 110, 2001,733-83.

DeAngelo, G., and G. Charness. "Deterrence, Expected Cost, Uncertainty and Voting: Experimental Evidence." Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 44(1), 2012, 73-100.

Emons, W. "A Note on the Optimal Punishment for Repeat Offenders." International Review of Law and Economics, 23, 2003, 253-59.

--. "Subgame Perfect Punishment for Repeat Offenders." Economic Inquiry, 42, 2004, 496-502.

--. "Escalating Penalties for Repeat Offenders." International Review of Law and Economics, 27, 2007, 170-78.

Engel, C. Behavioral Law and Economics: Empirical Methods, Vol. 01. Bonn, Germany: Preprints of the Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods, 2013.

Fellner, G., R. Sausgruber, and C. Traxler. "Testing Enforcement Strategies in the Field: Threat, Moral Appeal, and Social Information." Journal of the European Economic Association, 11(3), 2013, 634-60.

Fischbacher, U. "z-Tree: Zurich Toolbox for Ready-made Economic Experiments." Experimental Economics, 10(2), 2007, 171-8.

Friedman, D. "Efficient Institutions for the Private Enforcement of Law," Journal of Legal Studies, 13, 1984, 379-97.

Friesen, L. "Certainty of Punishment versus Severity of Punishment: An Experimental Investigation." Southern Economic Journal, 79, 2012, 399-421.

Funk, P. "On the Effective Use of Stigma as a Crime-deterrent." European Economic Review, 48, 2004, 715-28.

Garoupa, N. "The Theory of Optimal Law Enforcement." Journal of Economic Surveys, 11, 1997, 267-95.

Garoupa, N., and M. Jellal. "Dynamic Law Enforcement with Learning." Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 20, 2004, 192-206.

Harel, A., and U. Segal. "Criminal Law and Behavioral Law and Economics: Observations on the Neglected Role of Uncertainty in Deterring Crime." American Law and Economics Review, 1, 1999, 276-312.

Holt, C., and S. Laury. "Risk Aversion and Incentive Effects." American Economic Review, 92, 2002, 1644-55.

Lochner, L. "Individual Perceptions of the Criminal Justice System." American Economic Review, 97, 2007, 444-60.

Mastrobuoni, G., and D. A. Rivers. "Criminal Discount Factors and Deterrence." IZA Discussion Papers No. 9769, 2016.

McAdams, R. H., and T. S. Ulen. "Behavioral Criminal Law and Economics." Public Law & Legal Theory Working Papers No. 244, 2008.

McCannon, B. "Differentiating between First and Repeat Offenders." Contemporary Economic Policy, 27, 2009, 76-85.

Miceli, T. "Escalating Penalties for Repeat Offenders: Why Are They So Hard to Explain?" Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 169, 2013, 587-604.

Miceli, T., and C. Bucci. "A Simple Theory of Increasing Penalties for Repeat Offenders." Review of Law & Economics, 1, 2005, 5.

Miles, S., and D. Pyne. "Deterring Repeat Offenders with Escalating Penalty Schedules: A Bayesian Approach." Economics of Governance, 16, 2015, 229-50.

Motchenkova, E. "Cost Minimizing Sequential Punishment Policies for Repeat Offenders." Applied Economics Letters, 21, 2014, 360-65.

Mungan, M. "Repeat Offenders: If They Learn, We Punish Them More Severely." International Review of Law and Economics, 30, 2010, 173-77.

--. "Optimal Warning Strategies: Punishment Ought Not to Be Inflicted Where the Penal Provision Is Not Properly Conveyed." Review of Law & Economics, 9, 2013,303-39.

--. "A Behavioral Justification for Escalating Penalties." International Review of Law and Economics, 37, 2014, 189-97.

Mungan, M., and J. Klick. "Forfeiture of Illegal Gains, Attempts, and Implied Risk Preferences." Journal of Legal Studies, 43(1), 2014, 137-53.

--. "Discounting and Criminals' Implied Risk Preferences." Review of Law & Economics, 11, 2015, 19-23.

Neilson, W., and H. Winter. "On Criminals' Risk Attitudes." Economics Letters, 55, 1997, 97-102.

Polinsky, M., and D. Rubinfeld. "A Model of Fines for Repeat Offenders." Journal of Public Economics, 46, 1991, 291-306.

Polinsky, M., and S. Shavell. "On Offense History and the Theory of Deterrence." International Review of Law and Economics, 18, 1998, 305-24.

--. "The Economic Theory of Public Enforcement of Law." Journal of Economic Literature, 38, 2000, 45-76.

Rasmusen, E. "Stigma and Self-fulfilling Expectations of Criminality." Journal of Law and Economics, 39, 1996, 519-43.

Rubinstein, A. "An Optimal Conviction Policy for Offenses that May Have Been Committed by Accident," in Applied Game Theory, edited by S. Brams, A. Schotter, and G. Schwodiauer. Wurzburg, Germany: Physica-Verlag, 1979,406-13.

Schildberg-Horisch, H., and C. Strassmair. "An Experimental Test of the Deterrence Hypothesis." Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 28(3), 2012, 447-59.

Sloan, F., A. Platt, L. Chepke, and C. Blevins. "Deterring Domestic Violence: Do Criminal Sanctions Reduce Repeat Offenses?" Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 46(1), 2013, 51-80.

Sonnemann, U., C. F. Camerer, C. R. Fox, and T. Langer. "How Psychological Framing Affects Economic Market Prices in the Lab and Field." Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 110, 2013: 11779-84.

Tietelbaum, J., and K. Zeiler, eds. Research Handbook on Behavioral Law and Economics. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar Publishing, 2015.

LISA R. ANDERSON, GREGORY DEANGELO, WINAND EMONS, BETH FREEBORN and HANNES LANG *

* The views expressed are those of the author and do not represent those of the Federal Trade Commission or any individual Commissioner. We would like to thank Emmanuel Dechenaux, Heiko Karle, Dan Rubinfeld, Sergio de Souza, participants at the 2014 Southern Economic Association Meetings Society for Ecological Economics. We also thank the editor and two anonymous referees.

Anderson: Professor, Department of Economics, 127 Morton Hall, College of William and Mary, Williamsburg, VA 23187. Phone 757-221-2359, Fax 757-221-1175, E-mail [email protected]

DeAngelo: Assistant Professor of Economics, College of Business and Economics, West Virginia University, 1601 University Avenue, Morgantown, WV 26506. Phone 304293-4039, E-mail [email protected]

Emons: Professor, Department of Economics, University of Bern, Hochschulstrasse 4,3012 Bern, Switzerland. Phone +41 31 631 39 22, E-mail [email protected]

Freeborn: Economist, Federal Trade Commission, 600 Pennsylvania Avenue, NW Washington, DC 20580. Phone 202-326-2837, E-mail [email protected]

Lang: Research Associate, Technical University Munich, 85354 Freising, Germany. Phone + 49 (0) 8161 71-5135, E-mail hanneslangl @gmail.com

(1.) For example, in the United States under the Clean Water Act, the maximum penalties are doubled for subsequent offenses and the Immigration Reform and Control Act imposes minimum fines of $250 for a first offense, $2,000 for a second offense, and $3,000 for subsequent offenses. In Switzerland, the fine for traveling without a valid ticket on a regional train is 100 SFR for the first offense, 140 SFR for the second offense, and 170 SFR for any further offense. See Polinsky and Shavell (1998) for more examples.

(2.) See, for example, Rubinstein (1979), Chu, Hu, and Huang (2000), Emons (2007), Ben-Shahar (1997), and Bebchuck and Kaplow (1993) for models that allow crimes to be committed by accident. In related work, criminals might be uninformed (Mungan 2013), may lack self-control (Mungan 2014), or may commit crimes by experimenting (McCannon 2009; Miceli 2013). Curry and Doyle (2016) also show that optimal penalties are increasing with criminal history in a model where voluntary trade is a possible alternative to the criminal activity.

(3.) See Garoupa (1997) or Polinsky and Shavell (2000) for surveys of the earlier law enforcement literature.

(4.) See, for example, Bumovski and Safra (1994) and Emons (2003, 2004).

(5.) In addition to deterring criminal behavior, legal systems also seek to sanction those who violate laws with criminal penalties and fines. For the purposes of this paper, we abstract away from the notion of punishment and assume that legal systems solely seek to optimize deterrence.

(6.) Behavioral and experimental economics have been used to investigate theoretical concepts in many subdisciplines within economics, but are less prevalent in studying issues within law and economics. See Tietelbaum and Zeiler (2015), Camerer and Talley (2007), McAdams and Ulen (2008), Arlen and Taylor (2008), and Engel (2013) for reviews of the literature. Limited work has focused on the exact nature and context of enforcement. In a large-scale field experiment examining different enforcement strategies to collect fees from consumers, Fellner, Sausgruber, and Traxler (2013) show that making a high detection regime salient to potential offenders has a significant deterrence effect.

(7.) Emons (2003) also assumes that the benefit to the offender is smaller than the harm caused by the offense. Our experiment does not address the harm aspect of the offense, because our focus is on agent behavior, and agent utility is not affected by the harm caused to society. Adding "harm to society" in our experimental framework in a way that affects subject payoffs would lead to strategic interactions between players and make it harder for us to isolate the effect of the penalty structure on behavior.

(8.) If sanctions are less than total wealth, sanctions can be increased and the probability of apprehension lowered so as to keep deterrence constant. In related theoretical work, Motchenkova (2014) shows that the results of Emons (2003, 2004) also hold for more than two periods; however, she does not allow for history-dependent strategies.

(9.) Note that if the benefit to the activity, b, is sufficiently large, the predictions of the model will not hold.

(10.) While there is research that focuses on sanctions that exceed an individual's wealth (see Polinsky and Shavell 2000), we focus on situations where monetary sanctions do not exceed an individual's wealth. This focus is sensible in a lab experiment. In practice, we cannot take funds from participants. Additionally, situations where sanctions exceed wealth typically involve excessively criminal acts, which we do not attempt to model in the lab.

(11.) Behavior is anticipated to vary with the probability of apprehension (Bar-Ilan and Sacerdote 2004). We reduce this dimension of variation by holding the probability fixed throughout the experiment.

(12.) Note that both of the history-dependent strategies involve the agent committing the crime in the first stage, because there is no chance of paying a fine in the first stage if the crime is not committed.

(13.) For example, Anderson and Mellor (2009) report that 75% of their subjects are risk averse.

(14.) Emons (2003) determines the optimal sanction scheme in the sense of Becker (1968), that is, the scheme that minimizes the cost of enforcement. In terms of our example, the probability of apprehension is minimized at 0.25 by choosing the (10,0) sanction scheme. However, in this experiment, we fix the probability of apprehension at 1/3 and focus on the potential differences in deterrence from increasing versus decreasing penalty structures.

(15.) See Anderson and Mellor (2008) for more details about how to derive the measure of risk tolerance, r, from this lottery choice experiment.

(16.) At the beginning of each session, subjects also participated in a "practice" period with hypothetical earnings.

(17.) In addition to the context-free treatment, there were three additional treatments that varied only in the way the decision was presented to subjects. In the context treatments, decisions were presented as "driving over the speed limit," "cheating on your taxes," and "shoplifting." Each subject made decisions using only one of the four contexts. We ran both context free and framed experiments to examine how subjects treated specific proscribed behavioral environments in comparison to a sterile risk environment, since previous research has shown considerable differences (see, e.g., Sonnemann et al. 2013). While this aspect of the experiment is not the focus of this paper, we do include controls for context in the econometric analysis that follows.

(18.) The full dataset is available upon request.

(19.) In determining whether or not behavior is consistent with a history-dependent strategy, we only observe actions on one path of the strategy. For example, we cannot distinguish between someone playing (1,1) or (1|1 if not detected) if that person is not caught in first stage.

(20.) Note that seven subjects made an irrational decision in the Holt and Laury (2002) experiment by choosing a certain lower payoff in one situation. We were not able to impute a risk-tolerance parameter for those subjects, resulting in 360 subjects with risk preference information.

(21.) We also perform Wilcoxon tests to test whether the proportion of subjects who state a strategy consistent with theory is significantly different from the proportion of subjects who follow a strategy consistent with optimal behavior. For each test, the p value is .000

(22.) As noted above, the proportion of subjects who state a strategy consistent with the predicted optimal is significantly lower than the proportion of subjects whose observed behavior is consistent with predicted theory. This observation is consistent with Brandts and Charness (2003), Brosig, Weimann, and Yang (2003), and Casari and Cason (2009) on the benefits of incentivized elicitation versus hypothetical elicitation. See Brandts and Charness (2011) for a review of observed differences and similarities in the use of direct response versus strategy methods.

(23.) The results are qualitatively the same when we repeated the analysis of Table 3 using both logit and linear probability models. These results are available upon request.

(24.) The p value is .056 for penalty structure (5,5) and is .001 for penalty structure (7,3).

(25.) Recall that subjects saw one of two order treatments in the experiment, starting with the (1,9) penalty structure regime and proceeding to the (9,1) regime (Treatment 1) or the reverse order where subjects saw the (9,1) penalty first (Treatment 2). In the figures that follow, we pool the data from the two presentation orders because we find that the qualitative comparisons between the different penalty structures within a presentation order treatment are consistent across treatments. For example, there are always more offenses in the (1,9) penalty structure than in the (3,7) penalty structure, regardless of whether (1,9) is seen first or last. However, it is worth noting that we find significant differences in overall levels of offending across presentation order treatments. For this reason, we include controls for treatment in all econometric analyses below.

(26.) We also find statistical evidence that decreasing penalty structures yield greater deterrence. Wilcoxon tests show that the average number of offenses are significantly different across all but one of the penalty structures, with p values all smaller than .001. The only exception is the pair (7,3) and (9,1), which does not have significantly different numbers of offenses (p value equal to .323).

(27.) Wilcoxon tests show that the number of second stage offenses for subjects facing the first fine are significantly higher in penalty structures (1,9) and (3,7) relative to the other penalty structures (p values equal .000 comparing (1,9) to (5,5), (7,3), and (9,1) and comparing (3,7) to the constant and decreasing penalty structures). In addition, the constant fine structure (5,5) results in significantly more second stage offenses than the decreasing penalty structures (p value is .0192 comparing to (7,3) and .0037 comparing to (9,1)). The decreasing penalty structures (7,3), and (9,1) do not have significantly different numbers of second stage offenses when subjects face the first fine.

(28.) The following pairs are found to have significantly different numbers of second stage offenses conditional on being caught in the first stage with p values equal to .000: (1,9) and (5,5); (1,9) and (7,3); (1,9) and (9,1); (3,7) and (5,5); (3,7) and (7,3); and (3,7) and (9,1). In addition, these pairs are also significantly different: (5,5) and (9,1) (p value = .001), and (7,3) and (9,1) (p value = .011). In other words, conditional on being caught in the first stage the two increasing penalty structures are not significantly different from one another in the second stage offenses, and (5,5) does not result in significantly more offenses than (7,3).

(29.) As noted in the previous footnote, penalty structures (9,1) and (7,3) have significantly higher repeat offense rates than (1,9) and (3,7). However, it is important to remember that fewer subjects have the chance to be a repeat offender in the decreasing penalty scenarios because few subjects choose to offend in the first stage of a decreasing penalty structure.

(30.) We repeat our analysis separately for each context and the results remain consistent; decreasing penalty structures result in fewer offenses than increasing penalty structures, regardless of the context. These results are available upon request.

(31.) The average number of times a female subject offends is 3.78 compared with 4.41 for male subjects. A Wilcoxon test rejects the hypothesis these are equal (p value = .002). One subject did not report gender on the survey, thus the total number of female and male subjects is 366.

(32.) Previously, we examined consistency with theoretical predictions across a more fine categorization of risk groups (risk loving, risk neutral, risk averse, very risk averse, and extremely risk averse). For the analysis on offending, we consolidate into risk averse and not risk averse for ease of presentation. Results using the finer risk preference categories are not qualitatively different and are available upon request.

(33.) Subjects who are not risk averse offend an average of 4.79 times and subjects who are risk averse offend an average of 3.87 times. The p value for the Wilcoxon testis .002. Recall that seven subjects made an irrational decision in the Holt and Laury (2002) experiment by choosing a certain lower payoff in one situation, resulting in 360 subjects with risk preference information.

(34.) Marginal effects from the ordered probit regression using the margins command in STATA14 are available upon request. We find that being risk averse increases the likelihood of not offending and decreases the likelihood of offending 1 or 2 times. Male subjects are also significantly less likely to offend zero times, and significantly more likely to offend 1 or 2 times.

(35.) The marginal effects of the penalty structures are all negative and significant relative to the baseline penalty structure of (1,9) with p values equal to .000. In addition, we perform pairwise Wald tests of the coefficients on the penalty structures. Each penalty structure is significantly different from the other with p values equal to .000 except for the pair (7,3) and (9,1).

(36.) Note that when we look at individual decisions, each subject makes ten decisions, thus the total number of observations is now 3,590 (359 individuals with nonmissing demographic information times ten decisions per subject).

(37.) The results for both Model 1 and Model 2 of Table 7 are qualitatively the same when we repeat using either logit or linear probability regression analysis. These results are available upon request.

(38.) We separate whether a subject was caught in the first stage of the current round from the total number of times caught because being caught in the current penalty structure directly affects the fine the subject is facing when making her decision. In terms of coding the variable, we set "caught in the first stage" to be 0 for observations in the first stage and 1 for observations in the second stage. We also include a control for second stage decision.

(39.) Model 1 also includes an interaction term for presentation order treatment and penalty structure.

(40.) Consistent with our previous results, Wald tests show the coefficients on penalty structures are all significantly different from one another (p values equal to .000) with the exception of the pair (7,3) and (9,1).

(41.) Table 7 includes both first and second stage decisions, which allows us to disentangle the effect of the total number of times that a subject has been caught in the experiment from whether they were caught in the first stage of the current period. For robustness, we repeated the analysis of Model 1 in Table 7 for only stage 2 decisions, controlling for whether the subject offended in the first stage. The results are qualitatively similar to what we present in Table 7 in terms of how risk aversion, penalty structure, number of times caught in previous periods, and caught in first stage are correlated with likelihood of offending in the second stage. The coefficient estimate on gender, however, is no longer significant.

(42.) The p value for the test of whether the predicted probabilities are different across penalty structures for nonrisk-averse subjects is .675. For risk-averse subjects, the predicted probabilities are significantly different with a p value of .001.

(43.) While it is worth noting that less than a quarter of our subjects are not risk averse, we would expect that 79 nonrisk-averse subjects would provide enough power to identify significant differences at the 10% or 15% level.

(44.) See, for example, Anderson and Stafford (2003), Harel and Segal (1999), DeAngelo and Chamess (2012), Friesen (2012), and Schildberg-Horisch and Strassmair (2012).

(45.) For example, Polinsky and Rubinfeld (1991) assume that offenders differ in their propensities to commit socially undesirable acts. Some other models incorporate a learning-by-doing effect of crime (Baik and Kim 2001; Garoupa and Jellal 2004; Miles and Pyne 2015; Mungan 2010). Another strand of literature justifying escalating penalties focuses on the stigma effect of a criminal conviction, which acts as a supplement to formal criminal penalties in deterring some offenders (Dana 2001; Funk 2004; Miceli and Bucci 2005; Rasmusen 1996). In other related work, Polinsky and Shavell (1998) find that, in some cases, it is optimal to punish old first-time offenders less severely than old repeat offenders and young first-time offenders. Recently, Curry and Doyle (2016) developed a model of crime that includes the possibility of legal voluntary trade; the results of this model are that optimal penalties minimize the costs of the crime and penalties are increasing in criminal history.
TABLE 1

Predicted Optimal Strategy by Risk Type and Penalty Structure

                                  Penalty Structure

Range of Risk     [f.sub.1] = $l   [f.sub.1] = $3   [f.sub.1] = $5
Aversion          [f.sub.1] = $9   [f.sub.1] = $7   [f.sub.1] = $5

r < 0             (1, 1|not        (1, 1|not        (1, 1)
(Risk loving)     detected,        detected,
                  0|otherwise)     0|otherwise)

r = 0             (1, 1|not        (1, 1|not        (1, 1)
(Risk neutral)    detected,        detected,
                  0|otherwise)     0|otherwise)

0 < r [less       (1, 1|not        (1, 1|not        (1, 1)
than or equal     detected,        detected,
to] .75           0|otherwise)     0|otherwise)
(Risk averse)

.75 < r [less     (1, 1|not        (1, 1|not        (1, 1|not
than or equal     detected,        detected,        detected,
to] 1.17 (Very    0|otherwise)     0|otherwise)     0|otherwise)
risk averse)

r > 1.17          (1, 1|not        (1, 1|not        (0, 0)
(Extremely        detected,        detected,
risk averse)      0|otherwise)     0|otherwise)

                               Penalty Structure

Range of Risk       [f.sub.1] = $7      [f.sub.1] = $9
Aversion            [f.sub.1] = $3      [f.sub.1] = $1

r < 0             (1, 0|not detected.   (0,0)
(Risk loving)     1|otherwise)

r = 0             (0, 0) or (1, 0|not   (0,0)
(Risk neutral)    detected,
                  1|otherwise)

0 < r [less       (0. 0)                (0, 0)
than or equal
to] .75
(Risk averse)

.75 < r [less     (0,0)                 (0, 0)
than or equal
to] 1.17 (Very
risk averse)

r > 1.17          (0,0)                 (0,0)
(Extremely
risk averse)

TABLE 2

Consistency of Behavior with Theory

                    Penalty Structure
                    % Observed Strategies (Stated Strategies)
                    Consistent with Theory

Range of Risk       [f.sub.1] = $1   [f.sub.1] = $3   [f.sub.1] = $5
Aversion            [f.sub.2] = $9   [f.sub.2] = $7   [f.sub.2] = $5

r< 0                     0.33             0.20             0.27
Risk loving             (0.27)           (0.27)           (0.13)
(n = 15)

r = 0                    0.59             0.52             0.31
Risk neutral            (0.55)           (0.48)           (0.20)
(n = 64)

0 < r < .75              0.57             0.47             0.17
Risk averse             (0.49)           (0.36)           (0.07)
(n= 182)

.75 < r < 1.17           0.64             0.48             0.23
Very risk averse        (0.54)           (0.36)           (0.19)
(n = 66)

r > 1.17                 0.68             0.37             0.74
Extremely               (0.42)           (0.26)           (0.53)
risk averse
(n = 33)

Overall level            0.57             0.46             0.25
of consistency          (0.50)           (0.37)           (0.15)
(by penalty
structure)

                    Penalty Structure
                    % Observed Strategies (Stated Strategies)
                    Consistent with Theory

Range of Risk       [f.sub.1] = $7   [f.sub.1] = $9      Overall
Aversion            [f.sub.2] = $3   [f.sub.2] = $1      Level of
                                                       Consistency

r< 0                     0.07             0.67             0.31
Risk loving             (0.00)           (0.47)           (0.23)
(n = 15)

r = 0                    0.61             0.56             0.52
Risk neutral            (0.48)           (0.45)           (0.43)
(n = 64)

0 < r < .75              0.63             0.69             0.51
Risk averse             (0.54)           (0.50)           (0.39)
(n= 182)

.75 < r < 1.17           0.76             0.75             0.57
Very risk averse        (0.60)           (0.71)           (0.48)
(n = 66)

r > 1.17                 0.74             0.74             0.65
Extremely               (0.58)           (0.68)           (0.49)
risk averse
(n = 33)

Overall level            0.64             0.68
of consistency          (0.52)           (0.54)
(by penalty
structure)

TABLE 3

Average Marginal Effects on Likelihood of Consistency with
Optimal Strategy

                                Dependent               Dependent
                             Variable = 1 if         Variable = 1 if
                           Stated Strategy Is     Observed Strategy Is
                            Predicted Optimal       Predicted Optimal
                          Strategy; 0 Otherwise   Strategy; 0 Otherwise
                                 Model 1                 Model 2
                            (Stated Strategy)      (Observed Actions)

Risk loving (r < 0)            -0.203 ***              -0.209 ***
                                 (0.05)                  (0.05)

Risk averse (.75                 -0.045                  -0.017
[greater than or equal           (0.03)                  (0.04)
to] r > 0)

Very risk averse (1.17            0.022                   0.014
[greater than or equal           (0.04)                  (0.04)
to] r > .75)

Extremely risk averse             0.033                 0.116 **
(r > 1.17)                       (0.06)                  (0.05)

Male                            0.087 ***               0.059 **
                                 (0.03)                  (0.03)

Percentage of detected           0.0549                  0.0586
chances taken                    (1.31)                  (1.53)

Caught in first stage             0.011                 0.142 ***
of current period                (0.03)                  (0.03)

Penalty structure (1,9)         0.367 ***               0.332 ***
                                 (0.031)                 (0.031)

Penalty structure (3,7)         0.231 ***               0.206 ***
                                 (0.030)                 (0.033)

Penalty structure (7,3)         0.384 ***               0.407 ***
                                 (0.032)                 (0.034)

Penalty structure (9,1)         0.413 ***               0.456 ***
                                 (0.031)                 (0.035)
N                                 1,795                   1,795

Notes: Standard errors in parentheses. Standard errors are clustered
at the subject level. Additional controls include indicators
for each of the presented contexts, an indicator for the presentation
order treatment, and interactions of the presentation treatment
by penalty structure.

* Significance at 10%; ** significance at 5%; *** significance at 1%.

TABLE 4

Behavioral Consistency across the Two Stages of the Experiment

                (1)            (2)              (3)

              Do Not     Do Not Offend in        %
             Offend in     Stage 1 and      Consistent
Fine          Stage 1     Do Not Offend     Decisions =
Structure                   in Stage 2        (2)/(l)

(1,9)           54              26             0.48
(3,7)           114             72             0.63
(5,5)           215            169             0.79
(7,3)           284            236             0.83
(9,1)           295            251             0.85

                  (4)                  (S)                (6)

               Offend in            Offend in              %
              Stage 1 and          Stage 1 and         Consistent
Fine         Are Not Caught     Are Not Caught and     Decisions
Structure                     Also Offend in Stage 2   = (5)/(4)

(1,9)             211                  127                0.60
(3,7)             166                   99                0.60
(5,5)             109                   42                0.39
(7,3)              55                   18                0.33
(9,1)              54                   18                0.33

Note: The total number of subjects who participated
in the experiment is 367.

TABLE 5

Number of Subjects Facing Each Fine in Stage 2

Fine         Face First Fine     Face Second
Structure      in Stage 2      Fine in Stage 2

(1,9)              265               102
(3,7)              280               87
(5,5)              324               43
(7,3)              339               28
(9,1)              348               19

TABLE 6

Predicted Probabilities of Outcomes

Penalty      No Offenses   One Offense   Two Offenses
Structure

(1,9)           0.160         0.408         0.431
(3,7)           0.232         0.443         0.325
(5,5)           0.424         0.418         0.158
(7,3)           0.603         0.320         0.077
(9,1)           0.628         0.305         0.067

FIGURE 1
Total Offenses by Decision Stage and Penalty Structure

        First Stage   Second Stage

(1.9)     313           173
(3,7)     253           159
(5,5)     152           113
(7,3)      83            86
(9,1)      73            81

Note: For each penalty structure, there are 367 subjects making
decisions in two stages, thus the maximum number of
offenses for each decision stage is 367.

Note: Table made from bar graph.

FIGURE 2
Second Stage Offenses by Penalty Structure

Panel A: Total Offenses

        Face First Fine   Face Second Fine

(1.9)       155               18
(3,7)       141               18
(5,5)        88               25
(7,3)        66               20
(9,1)        62               19

Panel B: Offense Rates

        Face First Fine   Face Second Fine

(1,9)      .585              .176
(3,7)      .504              .207
(5,5)      .272              .581
(7,3)      .195              .714
(9,1)      .178                 1

Note: Table made from bar graph.

FIGURE 3
Offenses by Gender and Risk Aversion

                 First Stage   Second Stage

No Context         .513          .348
Speeding           .459          .3
Cheat on Taxes     .392          .281
Shoplifting        .431          .362

Note: Table made from bar graph.
COPYRIGHT 2017 Western Economic Association International
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 2017 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

联系我们|关于我们|网站声明
国家哲学社会科学文献中心版权所有