Occupy: Edmund Burke.
Green, Jonathan
The Intellectual Life of Edmund Burke: From the Sublime and
Beautiful to American Independence, David Bromwich, Harvard University
Press, 500 pages
David Bromwich's monograph proposes to answer the question:
"What did it mean to think like Edmund Burke?" For John Morley
and the Victorian Whigs, thinking like Burke meant thinking like a cool,
calculating utilitarian. For Russell Kirk and the so-called New
Conservatives of the 1950s, Burke was a Christian Romantic--a principled
defender of the "moral imagination" of the West against its
secular assailants. In the late '90s, Luke Gibbons and Uday Mehta
summoned Burke as a critic of 18th-century imperialism and a defender of
the dispossessed peoples of India and Ireland.
More recently, a series of new biographies set out to resurrect his
reputation as the father of modern conservatism. In Jesse Normans Edmund
Burke: The First Conservative, we see him as a reform-minded statesman,
a free-marketeer,
and a critic of the French revolutionaries' utopian schemes.
Drew Maciag presents him as a champion of civil society, patriotic
allegiances, and the moral and political wisdom handed down over the
ages. And in Yuval Levin's The Great Debate, Burke and his
arch-nemesis, Thomas Paine, are held up as the authors of present-day
conservatism and liberalism, respectively.
But in The Intellectual Life of Edmund Burke, Bromwich has little
use for this recent scholarship. The Sterling Professor of English at
Yale University informs us that "no historian today would repeat
the commonplace that Burke was the father of modern conservatism."
Burke the Christian, Burke the Romantic, Burke the market
capitalist--all of these are conspicuously absent from his study. The
reasons are not mysterious. Bromwich is a man of the left--he is on the
editorial board of Dissent--and he thinks that Burke has something
important to offer his allies. Saying what this is involves a good deal
of ground clearing.
Bromwich picks his terrain carefully. The Intellectual Life of
Edmund Burke turns our attention away from Burke's critique of the
French Revolution--fertile ground for his conservative interpreters--and
towards the less-studied years of his early career. Beginning with
Burke's upbringing and education in Ireland, Bromwich follows him
as he emigrates to England and begins a short-lived career as a man of
letters in the 1750s. This brief period gave rise to his Vindication of
Natural Society and his Philosophical Enquiry Into the Origin of Our
Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful, two dense works in which Burke
sought to explain the complex relations between art and morality, beauty
and fear, human nature and social convention. Bromwich is a literary
critic rather than a historian, and his prowess as an interpreter is on
clear display as he leads us through Burke's difficult yet
rewarding arguments.
After a rich discussion of Burke the philosopher, Bromwich
considers his entry into politics. Here we see Burke as the British
Parliament's foremost critic of royal prerogative, as a steadfast
defender of American Independence, and as an important strategist for
the Rockingham wing of the Whig party. Along the way Bromwich unpacks
Burke's Thoughts on the Present Discontents, in which he defended
organized parties as an essential check on executive power, and gives us
a sympathetic account of Burke's intransigent, oft-maligned
opposition to George III. (Bromwich is at work on a second volume that
will examine Burke's career from the end of the American War
through the French Revolution. For a less literary, more historical take
on Burke, readers can look forward to Richard Bourke's biography
forthcoming from Princeton University Press.)
[ILLUSTRATION OMITTED]
Throughout his narrative Bromwich keeps the Reflections on the
Revolution in France in view, but he is keen to resituate Burke's
critique of the revolutionaries' ideology within the context of his
earlier writings and speeches. The result is a Burke that is
significantly more liberal--and more republican--than recent
interpreters have acknowledged. As a corrective, this is a welcome
addition to the literature. Eschewing the stale conservative categories
that have too often limited historians' appraisals of Burke,
Bromwich gives us something much closer to an exegesis.
Through close examination of Burke's writings and speeches, he
extracts and distills the complex, varied, and sometimes discordant
elements of Burke's worldview. The individual chapters of
Bromwich's book can feel disjointed at times. But his insights as
an interpreter are invariably rewarding, and they constitute the real
strength of this study.
Yet Bromwich does not intend The Intellectual Life of Edmund Burke
to be just a corrective. He is out to discover a new Burke, one that has
been occluded in the recent scholarship but that offers lessons for
contemporary politicians. In this respect his study is at best
tendentious and at worst misleading.
According to Bromwich, Burke's importance must be understood
in terms of a theological crisis in the late 18th century. This was,
Bromwich tells us, the crisis of "secularization." In the old
Thomist view of politics, the state was a practical extension of the
moral law. But in Burke's day, Bromwich explains, this vision of
politics had become increasingly untenable. In its absence, what
arguments could be levied against the Machiavellian image of politics as
an amoral arena in which statesmen recognize only the dictates of power
and prestige? If statesmen are to obey gods higher than the will to
power or the logic of the market, then in the wake of religion's
collapse a new justification for political morality is needed. This is
what Bromwich thinks he has found in Burke.
Again and again Bromwich repeats Burke's mantra that "the
principles of true politics are those of morality enlarged, and I
neither now do nor ever will admit of any other." For Burke, he
argues, political morality was grounded in the natural human ability to
empathize with one's fellow man. Rather than divine command,
Burkean morality is based on human psychology:
Burke believed that secularization
had increased, was increasing, and
could not be reversed. He devoted
none of his energy to programmatic
efforts to reverse the process.
He supposed that enlightenment,
properly understood, was
the name for the development by
which we move from fear of God
to fear of man. This change ... entails
a displacement of religious by
moral authority and the accompanying
intuition that the idea of the
good is prior to the idea of God.
Burke's politics, according to Bromwich, acknowledged no
bounds of race, creed, or language: instead he was animated by a
cosmopolitan desire for "common good of humankind."
As a philosophical account of morality, this may or may not be
plausible. But as an answer to Bromwich's question--what did it
mean to think like Burke?--it is predicated on a bald-faced anachronism.
As anyone familiar with 18th-century British culture will acknowledge,
none of Burke's peers--not even Tom Paine or Joseph Priestly--were,
by our standards, secular. There were efforts to rationalize and
demystify Anglicanism, surely, but not even the harshest critics of the
established church hoped to generate a post-Christian account of
morality. There were secular moralists in France, of course, but these
were the exact radicals Burke excoriated in his Reflections. To suggest
that he embraced "secularization" in 18th-century Britain is
like arguing that Plato was a Christian or that Machiavelli was a
neoconservative. The option was just not on the table.
Bromwich's interpretation of Burke as a political moralist
grows even stranger when he begins to speculate about what Burke would
say to our present-day politicians. Take just two examples. At one
point, Bromwich argues that "in politics as in morality, the means
must justify themselves. Means, though it troubles us to think so,
always alter the character of the actor." As a description of
Burke's moral compass, this is plausible enough. From this premise,
Bromwich goes on to infer that as a matter of principle Burke would have
opposed the torture of terror suspects under the Bush administration. It
is perhaps not coincidental that Bromwich has himself written at great
length on this very subject.
Elsewhere, he explains that in a secularized world, men cannot be
the judges of their own actions. Once God no longer serves as a
sovereign moral judge, the consensus of one's peers must act as an
ersatz source of authority. This means, Bromwich surmises, that Burke
would have supported something like the modern United Nations. "If
there is a later development that one can say with confidence that Burke
would have favored, from clear, unmixed, and unmistakable hints in his
writings on every subject, that development is the rise of a body of
international laws to civilize the conduct of nations."
Taken as vague injunctions, Bromwich's prescriptions are well
and good: means and ends must cohere, yes, and absolute power must be
checked. But the highly stipulative conclusions that he draws from
them--that Burke anticipated 20th-century multilateralism or that he can
help us address the moral dilemmas of the war on terror--give of a
strong impression that Bromwich is telling us more about his own
politics than Burke's. The ex cathedra tone in which he asserts,
without evidence, that Burke was "a doubter through and
through" does little to quiet this feeling. And the frequent
bait-and-switch tactic of moving from, say, the Wilkes riots in the
1760s to Occupy Wall Street--Bromwich argues that since Burke defended
the former he would have supported the latter--tends to spoil what are
otherwise genuinely insightful passages in his study.
Too often, historians and political theorists treat Burke as little
more than an avatar for advancing their own agendas. In this sense, it
is hard to blame Bromwich from recoiling at the conservative readings of
Burke that have predominated in recent years: it is indeed disingenuous
to paint him as a laissez-faire capitalist or as an apologist for
Western Christendom, and Bromwich is right to disavow these
over-determined interpretations. As a critical reader, he is quite good
at attempting to understand Burke on his own terms. But when he turns
away from exegesis, in order to tailor a Burke for the contemporary
secular left, does Bromwich not fall into the same trap as his rivals?
The challenge and the promise of reading Burke is that he upends the
hackneyed categories that frame modern political discourse. Giving us a
Burke in Bromwich's image, The Intellectual Life of Edmund Burke
leaves this promise unrealized.
Jonathan Green is a doctoral student at the University of
Cambridge, studying Burke's reception in 19th-century Germany.