The Political Aspects of Islamic Philosophy: Essays in Honor of Muhsin S. Mahdi.
Najjar, Fauzi M.
This volume consists of nine essays written in honor of Muhsin S.
Mahdi, James Richard Jewett Professor of Arabic at Harvard University,
by his former students. It is a tribute to the "dean of Islamic
Philosophy", a scholar who has created a school of thought, the
central theme of which permeates the writings of his distinguished
students. In the introduction, Charles E. Butterworth, the most
illustrious of Mahdi's disciples, underscores the importance of
this theme, the political aspects of Islamic philosophy, to the
understanding of the proper relationship between religion and politics,
an understanding "fundamental to our appreciation of the way Greek
political philosophy was transmitted to the medieval Islamic world and,
through it, to us" (p. 2). Butterworth concludes the introduction
with a moving and highly merited tribute to the "teacher", by
whom the authors of these essays have been schooled.
Strict space limitations preclude more than a very brief account of
this original and important work of scholarship. In the first essay,
"Al-Kindi and the Beginnings of Islamic Political Philosophy"
Charles E. Butterworth examines al-Kindi's "practical"
works, such as the Treatise on the Number of Aristotle's Books and
What is Needed to Attain Philosophy, Treatise on the Device for Driving
Away Sorrows, and Treatise on the Utterances of Socrates. In the first,
Abu Yusuf Ibn Ishaq al-Kindi (d. 866) concludes that Aristotle's
philosophy "offers insufficient guidance for the attainment of
man's goal, human virtue", (p. 34) Neither metaphysics nor
divine science can offer such guidance, because they are accessible to
only a few. Pointing to the "need for political philosophy"
al-Kindi laid down the foundation upon which Abu Nasr al-Farabi (d. 950)
later erected a full-fledged Islamic political philosophy.
Butterworth's stimulating interpretation frees al-Kindi's work
from its traditional Mu tazilite cast, placing him at the source of
Islamic political philosophy.
Equally interesting is Paul E. Walker's "The Political
Implications of al-Razi's Philosophy." Muhammad Ibn Zakariyya
al-Razi (d. 925), the famous physician and most important representative
of Natural Philosophy, did not, we are told, show any interest in
politics or political philosophy as such. Yet, analysis of his
philosophical and ethical doctrines reveals that they have serious
political implications, in the sense that philosophers are just as good
as, if not better than, prophets in having a role in forming societies
and laws", (p. 94). The essay is as much an analysis of the views
of Abu Hatim al-Razi (d. 936), the Isma ili advocate, who contested the
"heretical" doctrines of his namesake, as it is an analysis of
those of Abu Bakr.
The third essay, "The Theoretical and Practical Dimensions of
Happiness as Portrayed in Political Treatises of al-Farabi," by
Miriam Galston, is reprinted with minor modifications from her book
Politics and Excellence: The Political Philosophy of Alfarabi. It is a
thorough examination of al-Farabi's notion of happiness. Happiness
is equated with the end of human life. Three alternative understandings
of happiness are delineated: happiness as theoretical activity
exclusively, as political activity exclusively, and a combination of the
two in which the theoretical and practical aspects are both part of the
essence or defining structure of happiness. Although he stresses that
supreme happiness is a state transcending political existence, al-Farabi
also recognizes its human origin. Supreme happiness is identical with
theoretical perfection, the preserve of the philosopher. But the
philosopher must rule in order to guarantee some semblance of happiness
to others. As Galston puts it, al-Farabi implies that
"contemplation both makes possible and finds completion in
action."
Prophecy occupies a central place in the political philosophy of
the falasifah. It is through their philosophical account of the nature
of prophecy that they sought to introduce philosophy into the Islamic
society of their time. In "The Philosopher-Prophet in
Avicenna's Political Philosophy," James W. Morris gives an
in-depth analysis of Avicenna's philosophic theory of prophecy, and
his political doctrine underlying it. It is in his political teaching
that Avicenna could dispute the belief in prophetic inspiration without
compromising its social necessity. Prophecy presents itself as an
essentially political fact, and not a source of certain theoretical
knowledge. Avicenna's theory of prophecy is, in Morris's
words, "largely designed to counter that dangerous misunderstanding
of philosophy as simply a handmaiden to some higher revealed wisdom,
while at the same time using the popular appeal of such reasoning to
draw a wider audience to the study of philosophy", (p. 154).
The place of the philosopher in society is one of the major themes
in Plato's Republic. It is also of particular importance in Islamic
political philosophy. In "The Place of the Philosopher in the City
According to Ibn Bajjah" Steven Harvey expounds the views of this
philosopher of the Muslim West. Following in al-Farabi's footsteps,
Ibn Bajjah (d. 1138) maintains that the philosopher is indispensable for
the establishment of the virtuous city. However, the philosopher is
unable to reform society, and therefore, will have to follow a course of
thought and action that would guarantee him happiness or perfection in
an imperfect city. By achieving this end, he will live a life of his
own, and become a "stranger." Ibn Bajjah's treatise, the
Governance of the Solitary, is a prescription for attaining this end.
There is no disagreement between Ibn Bajjah (Avempace to the Latin
world) and al-Farabi while the latter expressed the view that for the
philosopher to fashion a virtuous city is a matter of chance, the former
eliminated even such a remote possibility.
The tradition of Islamic political philosophy, founded by al-Farabi
is also traced in Abu Bakr Ibn Tufayl's famous philosophical novel,
Hayy Ibn Yaqzan. Hillel Fradkin, in "The Political Thought of Ibn
Tufayl," concludes that, despite appearances, there is an important
political teaching in the thought of the Spanish Muslim philosopher,
which may be summarized as follows; although the true life of wisdom
transcends political life, it can only be fully understood in
contradistinction to it.
In "The Scope and Methods of Rhetoric in Averroes' Middle
Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric" Michael Blaustein
elucidates both Aristotle's and Averroes, views on the subject. The
Muslim philosopher differs from the Greek master in emphasis rather than
in principle. He "expands the scope of rhetoric to include
theoretical subjects" and adapts its use to an Islamic audience,
whereby religion can serve as a rhetorical device to persuade the
multitude to pursue the moral virtues arrived at by philosophic inquiry.
The last two essays deal with the political thought of two
religious philosophers: Shihab al-Din al-Suhrawardi (d. 1191), and Qutb
al-Din al-Shirazi (d. 1310). In "The Source and Nature of
Authority: A Study of al-Suhrawardi's Illuminationist Political
Doctrine," Hossein Ziai examines the whole corpus and activities of
the author of the famous work Hikmat al-Ishraq, unveiling an important
illuminationist political doctrine. He defines it as "the simple
stipulation of a commonly known political proposition, namely, that wise
rulers are the only ones fit to rule" (p. 310). The wise ruler,
God's viceregent, is identified as the "enlightened
philosopher, one who combines to a perfect degree discursive and
intuitive wisdom" (p.322). Thus defined, an illuminationist
political doctrine may not seem out of place in a discourse on Islamic
political philosophy.
"The Political Thought of Qutb al-Din al-Shirazi," by
John Walbridge, demonstrates how al-Shirazi's political thought was
inspired by the political philosophy of al-Farabi the "Mirrors for
Princes" literature, and the political thought of Nasir al-Din
al-Tusi. The result is a set of reflections on how a king should rule,
and the role of religion in establishing a just political order. They
are more of the nature of advices to rulers than a political philosophy
as such.
This is a fabulous collection, meticulously researched, written and
edited. The authors should feel great satisfaction in having lived up to
the expectations of their teacher, who in turn should be proud of his
disciples.