Justifying preventive force: reply to Steven Lee.
Buchanan, Allen ; Keohane, Robert O.
Steven Lee offers a probing and fair-minded critique of our effort
to show that the preventive use of military force could be justified if
the decision to undertake preventive action was reached through an
appropriate institutional process. Our responses to his thoughtful
criticisms will help to clarify both the moral-philosophical arguments
and the institutional proposal presented in our earlier paper.
THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PREVENTIVE WAR AND LIMITED PREVENTIVE FORCE
Lee correctly points out that there are likely to be significant
moral differences between preventive war and more limited uses of
preventive force, such as a missile strike to destroy a nuclear
facility. (1) We heartily agree, and concede that our paper may not have
adequately emphasized this important point. However, we also believe
that the institutional decision-making process we recommend can take
this distinction into account, by requiring credible evidence, subject
to vigorous contestation, if the claim is made that war and territorial
occupation rather than a more limited use of force is necessary to avert
a threat. In addition, as Lee notes, the decision-making process we
propose would include measures to help ensure that the just war
requirement of proportionality is satisfied, which would in turn require
a careful consideration, ex ante, of the considerable risks that
toppling a regime might engender.
THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PREVENTIVE INTERVENTION AND HUMANITARIAN
INTERVENTION
According to Lee, we "run together preventive intervention and
humanitarian intervention, two categories that should be kept
distinct" because "humanitarian intervention ... like
traditional self-defense, involves avoiding harms that have already
begun to occur" (p. 106).
On the contrary, humanitarian intervention, as usually understood,
is military action undertaken not only to stop harms that are already
occurring, but also to prevent new harms--to different individuals--that
are about to be committed. For example, if UN forces had intervened to
stop the genocide in Rwanda, they would not have limited their action to
interrupting the harmful actions that were actually occurring at that
time, but also would have acted to disarm and detain genocidaires who
were poised to attack still more people. However, it is still useful,
perhaps, to distinguish between humanitarian intervention in the usual
sense and preventive military intervention to protect people in other
countries from massive human rights violations, using the latter term to
refer only to cases where the massive violations of human rights to be
averted are expected to occur sometime in the future, but not
imminently. Nothing we say in the article is inconsistent with this
suggestion.
MEETING THE DEONTOLOGICAL OBJECTION
Lee claims that the most compelling objection to our argument is
deontological in character: we have not rebutted the claim that
"preventive action cannot be justified because the target of the
intervention has done nothing to make itself morally liable for the
intervention. Actual aggression can make the aggressor liable to attack,
but expected aggression cannot" (p. 104). Our argument that
prevention can be justified was twofold. First, many preventive actions
are directed against actions already planned, in which case the planning
constitutes an act justifying an armed response so long as concrete
steps have been taken to begin to implement the plan. We invoked the
analogy of the law of conspiracy to refer to such cases. Second,
preventive action may be justified even in the absence of a conspiracy,
when the potential victim has reasonable grounds for believing that
unless he acts he will be subject to an unjust attack that will result
in his death or serious bodily injury. This is also the case with
respect to individual self-defense.
Lee seems to accept our proposition that planning an aggressive
attack itself constitutes conduct that could justify intervention. His
objection to our analogy with conspiracy law is merely that evidence for
such conduct might be difficult to find. This objection, however, would
be an argument for institutions that could more effectively produce
reliable evidence, not an argument against intervention per se. His more
fundamental objection relates to the second case, under which there may
be a justified expectation of future attack but there has been no
conspiracy. Lee's position is that the potential attacker cannot be
morally liable to the use of force against him because he has not yet
acted wrongfully.
But this argument fails to note that there are two distinct ways in
which the potential attacker (A) can be morally liable. First, A can
have done something, in a fairly robust sense, that makes him morally
liable: A has either attacked B or is imminently attacking B, or, as we
have argued, has wrongfully imposed a dire risk on B by forming a plan
to attack B and taking the first steps to execute the plan, even if the
harm is not imminent. Second--and more controversially--it may be the
case that B reasonably believes that A has wrongfully imposed a dire
risk on him even though A has not yet even formed a plan of attack, much
less begun to execute it.
Admittedly, when it is reasonable for B to believe that A has
wrongfully imposed a dire risk on him, it is normally the case that A
will have undertaken some threatening course of conduct (for example,
formed a plan of attack and begun to execute it). But this need not
always be the case. A may have done things that are not in fact aimed at
B's destruction, but that B may nonetheless reasonably interpret as
imposing a dire risk upon him, perhaps because A has often behaved
aggressively toward him or others in the past. In such cases, because of
the risk that his past aggressive behavior will cause B and others to
mistakenly suppose that he intends to act aggressively toward B in the
future, A may have a duty to provide B with assurances that he does not
intend to attack. The nature and extent of this duty would be determined
by a consideration of the costs that it is reasonable for A to bear with
respect to providing such assurances. In that sense there is an
essential symmetry: the nature and scope of the right of self-defense is
determined by the burdens of self-restraint that it is reasonable for
individuals to bear, both as potential actors in self-defense and as
potential targets of self-defensive action.
This account effectively addresses the deontotogical objection. It
shows that in virtually any actual case of justified self-defense the
target will in fact have done something wrong, such as forming and
beginning to execute a plan of attack. It is not the case, however, that
to be morally liable to the use of defensive force one must have done
something wrong.
JUSTIFYING PREVENTION, NOT JUST PREEMPTION
In arguing that there is no categorical moral prohibition against
engaging in the preventive use of force, we invoke a hypothetical
example. A state has reliable information, from multiple sources, that a
terrorist group has a deadly virus in its remote base camp, that it
plans to release the virus in a major city, and that if the virus is not
destroyed in its present location, later efforts to thwart the attack
will almost certainly fail. Lee writes, "If the use of this weapon
is imminent, as the story suggests, then a military strike to destroy
the weapon would count as preemption rather than prevention. If its use
is in fact not imminent, then it is not clear that force is justified,
given the possibility of other options" (p. 106). In the example as
we describe it, the harm is not imminent--for example, it may take
several weeks for the virus to reach the target city. Furthermore, we
described the example to make clear that there are not "other
options" than a preventive strike; if the virus is not destroyed in
the terrorists' base camp, and allowed to be moved from that
location, there will be no way of determining where it has gone and
little prospect of intercepting it at a point where the threat has
become imminent. So the example stands as a case where preventive action
is prima facie justified.
After praising our institutional scheme for its ingenuity, Lee
asserts that it would be inapplicable "in just those situations
where preventive intervention would be called for." Preventive
intervention would be justified "only when the expected aggression
to be prevented would involve a sudden and massive violation of human
rights. In many or most cases of this sort, however, the exigencies of
the situation would not allow for the ex ante part of the process
[prescribed in our institutional proposal]." The difficulty, he
thinks, is that the "publicity that would attend that part of the
process would forewarn the expected aggressor ... allowing a dispersal
its forces" (p. 101). But if the potential aggressor were deterred
from continued depredations by fear of intervention, the objective of
action would be achieved without the costs of war. This would seem not
to be a cost but a clear benefit of our proposal for instituting
mechanisms for ex ante accountability.
There could be a significant problem, here: in some cases, there
might not be time to go through the entire deliberative process we
outline. Under such circumstances, a state or group of states might
nonetheless be justified in undertaking preventive action without prior
approval--but only if there were adequate provisions for an impartial
evaluation ex post as to whether invoking the "emergency
exception" to prior approval was justified. A fully fleshed-out
proposal would need to include such provisions.
(1) Steven Lee, "A Moral Critique of the Cosmopolitan
Institutional Proposal," Ethics & International Affairs 19, no.
2 (2005), pp. 99-107. All in-text citation references are to this
article.