The legitimacy of global governance institutions.
Buchanan, Allen ; Keohane, Robert O.
"Legitimacy" has both a normative and a sociological
meaning. To say that an institution is legitimate in the normative sense
is to assert that it has the right to rule--where ruling includes
promulgating rules and attempting to secure compliance with them by
attaching costs to noncompliance and/or benefits to compliance. An
institution is legitimate in the sociological sense when it is widely
believed to have the right to rule. (1) When people disagree over
whether the WTO is legitimate, their disagreements are typically
normative. They are not disagreeing about whether they or others believe
that this institution has the right to rule; they are disagreeing about
whether it has the right to rule. (2) This essay addresses the normative
dimension of recent legitimacy discussions.
We articulate a global public standard for the normative legitimacy
of global governance institutions. This standard can provide the basis
for principled criticism of global governance institutions and guide
reform efforts in circumstances in which people disagree deeply about
the demands of global justice and the role that global governance
institutions should play in meeting them. We stake out a middle ground
Between an increasingly discredited conception of legitimacy that
conflates legitimacy with international legality understood as state
consent, on the one hand, and the unrealistic view that legitimacy for
these institutions requires the same democratic standards that are now
applied to states, on the other.
Our approach to the problem of legitimacy integrates conceptual
analysis and moral reasoning with an appreciation of the fact that
global governance institutions are novel, still evolving, and
characterized by reasonable disagreement about what their proper goals
are and what standards of justice they should meet. Because both
standards and institutions are subject to change as a result of further
reflection and action, we do not claim to discover timeless necessary
and sufficient conditions for legitimacy. Instead, we offer a principled
proposal for how the legitimacy of these institutions ought to be
assessed--for the time being. Essential to our account is the idea that
to be legitimate a global governance institution must possess certain
epistemic virtues that facilitate the ongoing critical revision of its
goals, through interaction with agents and organizations outside the
institution. A principled global public standard of legitimacy can help
citizens committed to democratic principles to distinguish legitimate
institutions from illegitimate ones and to achieve a reasonable
congruence in their legitimacy assessments. Were such a standard widely
accepted, it could bolster public support for valuable global governance
institutions that either satisfy the standard or at least make credible
efforts to do so.
"Global governance institutions" covers a diversity of
multilateral entities, including the World Trade Organization (WTO), the
International Monetary Fund (IMF), various environmental institutions,
such as the climate change regime built around the Kyoto Protocol,
judges' and regulators' networks, the UN Security Council, and
the new International Criminal Court (ICC). (3) These institutions are
like governments in that they issue rules and publicly attach
significant consequences to compliance or failure to comply with
them--and claim the authority to do so. Nonetheless, they do not attempt
to perform anything approaching a full range of governmental functions.
These institutions do not seek, as governments do, to monopolize the
legitimate use of violence within a permanently specified territory, and
their design and major actions require the consent of states.
Determining whether global governance institutions are
legitimate--and whether they are widely perceived to be so--is an urgent
matter. Global governance institutions can promote international
cooperation and also help to construct regulatory frameworks that limit
abuses by nonstate actors (from corporations to narcotraffickers and
terrorists) who exploit transnational mobility. At the same time,
however, they constrain the choices facing societies, sometimes limit
the exercise of sovereignty by democratic states, and impose burdens as
well as confer benefits. For example, states must belong to the WTO in
order to participate effectively in the world economy, yet WTO
membership requires accepting a large number of quite intrusive rules,
authoritatively applied by its dispute settlement system. Furthermore,
individuals can be adversely affected by global rules--for example, by
the blacklists maintained by the Security Council's Sanctions
Committee (4) or the WTO's policies on intellectual property in
"essential medicines." If these institutions lack legitimacy,
then their claims to authority are unfounded and they are not entitled
to our support.
Judgments about institutional legitimacy have distinctive practical
implications. Generally speaking, if an institution is legitimate, then
this legitimacy should shape the character of both our responses to the
claims it makes on us and the form that our criticisms of it take. We
should support or at least refrain from interfering with legitimate
institutions. Further, agents of legitimate institutions deserve a kind
of impersonal respect, even when we voice serious criticisms of them.
Judging an institution to be legitimate, if flawed, focuses critical
discourse by signaling that the appropriate objective is to reform it,
rather than to reject it outright.
It is important not only that global governance institutions be
legitimate, but that they are perceived to be legitimate. The perception
of legitimacy matters, because, in a democratic era, multilateral
institutions will only thrive if they are viewed as legitimate by
democratic publics. If one is unclear about the appropriate standards of
legitimacy or if unrealistically demanding standards are assumed, then
public support for global governance institutions may be undermined and
their effectiveness in providing valuable goods may be impaired.
ASSESSING LEGITIMACY
The Social Function of Legitimacy Assessments
Global governance institutions are valuable because they create
norms and information that enable member states and other actors to
coordinate their behavior in mutually beneficial ways. (5) They can
reduce transaction costs, create opportunities for states and other
actors to demonstrate credibility, thereby overcoming commitment
problems, and provide public goods, including rule-based, peaceful
resolutions of conflicts. (6) An institution's ability to perform
these valuable functions, however, may depend on whether those to whom
it addresses its rules regard them as binding and whether others within
the institution's domain of operation support or at least do not
interfere with its functioning. It is not enough that the relevant
actors agree that some institution is needed; they must agree that this
institution is worthy of support. So, for institutions to perform their
valuable coordinating functions, a higher-order coordination problem
must be solved. (7)
Once an institution is in place, ongoing support for it and
compliance with its rules are sometimes simply a matter of self-interest
from the perspective of states, assuming that the institution actually
achieves coordination or other benefits that all or at least the more
powerful actors regard as valuable. (8) Similarly, once the rule of the
road has been established and penalties for violating it are in place,
most people will find compliance with it to be rational from a purely
selfinterested point of view. In the latter case, no question of
legitimacy arises, because the sole function of the institution is
coordination and the choice of the particular coordination point raises
no issues on which people are likely to disagree. Global governance
institutions are not pure coordination devices in the way in which the
rule of the road is, however. Even though all may agree that some
institution or other is needed in a specific domain (the regulation of
global trade, for example), and all may agree that any of several
particular institutions is better than the noninstitutional alternative,
different parties, depending upon their differing interests and moral
perspectives, will find some feasible institutions more attractive than
others. The fact that all acknowledge that it is in their interest to
achieve coordinated support for some institution or other may not be
sufficient to assure adequate support for any particular institution.
The concept of legitimacy allows various actors to coordinate their
support for particular institutions by appealing to their common
capacity to be moved by moral reasons, as distinct from purely strategic
or exclusively self-interested reasons. If legitimacy judgments are to
perform this coordinating function, however, actors must not insist that
only institutions that are optimal from the standpoint of their own
moral views are acceptable, since this would preclude coordinated
support in the face of diverging normative views. More specifically,
actors must not assume that an institution is worthy of support only if
it is fully just. We thus need a standard of legitimacy that is both
accessible from a diversity of moral standpoints and less demanding than
a standard of justice. Such a standard must appeal to various
actors' capacities to be moved by moral reasons, but without
presupposing more moral agreement than exists.
Legitimacy and Self-Interest
It is one thing to say that an institution promotes one's
interests and another to say that it is legitimate. As Andrew Hurrell points out, the rule-following that results from a sense of legitimacy
is "distinguishable from purely self-interested or instrumental
behaviour on the one hand, and from straightforward imposed or coercive rule on the other." (9) Sometimes self-interest may speak in favor
of treating an institution's rules as binding; that is, it can be
in one's interest to take the fact that an institution issues a
rule as a weighty reason for complying with it, independently of a
positive assessment of the content of particular rules. This would be
the case if one is likely to do better, from the standpoint of
one's own interest, by taking the rules as binding than one would
by evaluating each particular rule as to how complying with it would
affect one's interests. Yet clearly it makes sense to ask whether
an institution that promotes one's interests is legitimate. So
legitimacy, understood as the right to rule, is a moral notion that
cannot be reduced to rational self-interest. To say that an institution
is legitimate implies that it has the right to rule even if it does not
act in accordance with the rational self-interest of everyone who is
subject to its rule.
There are advantages in achieving coordinated support for
institutions on the basis of moral reasons, rather than exclusively on
the basis of purely self-interested ones. First, the appeal to moral
reasons is instrumentally valuable in securing the benefits that only
institutions can provide because, as a matter of psychological fact,
moral reasons matter when we try to determine what practical attitudes
should be taken toward particular institutional arrangements. For
example, we care not only about whether an environmental regulation
regime reduces air pollutants and thereby produces benefits for all, but
also whether it fairly distributes the costs of the benefits it
provides. Given that there is widespread disagreement as to which
institutional arrangement would be optimal, we need to find a shared
evaluative perspective that makes it possible for us to achieve the
coordinated support required for effective institutions without
requiring us to disregard our most basic moral commitments. Second, and
perhaps most important, if our support for an institution is based on
reasons other than self-interest or the fear of coercion, it may be more
stable. What is in our self-interest may change as circumstances change
and the threat of coercion may not always be credible, and moral
commitments can preserve support for valuable institutions in such
circumstances.
For questions of legitimacy to arise there must be considerable
moral disagreement about how institutions should be designed. Yet for
agreement about legitimacy to be reached, there must be sufficient
agreement on the sorts of moral considerations that are relevant for
evaluating alternative institutional designs. The practice of making
legitimacy judgments is grounded in a complex belief--namely, that while
it is true that institutions ought to meet standards more demanding than
mere mutual benefit (relative to some relevant noninstitutional
alternative), they can be worthy of our support even if they do not
maximally serve our interests and even if they do not measure up to our
highest moral standards. (10)
Legitimacy requires not only that institutional agents are
justified in carrying out their roles, but also that those to whom
institutional rules are addressed have content-independent reasons to
comply with them, and that those within the domain of the
institution's operations have content-independent reasons to
support the institution or at least to not interfere with its
functioning. (11) One has a content-independent reason to comply with a
rule if and only if one has a reason to comply regardless of any
positive assessment of the content of that rule. For example, I have a
content-independent reason to comply with the rules of a club to which I
belong if I have agreed to follow them and this reason is independent of
whether I judge any particular rule to be a good or useful one. If I
acknowledge an institution as having authority, I thereby acknowledge
that there are content-independent reasons to comply with its rules or
at least to not interfere with their operation. Legitimacy disputes
concern not merely what institutional agents are morally permitted to do
but also whether those to whom the institution addresses its rules
should regard it as having authority.
The debate about the legitimacy of global governance institutions
engages both the perspective of states and that of individuals. Indeed,
as recent mass protests against the WTO suggest, politically mobilized
individuals can adversely affect the functioning of global governance
institutions, both directly, by disrupting key meetings, and indirectly,
by imposing political costs on their governments for their support of
institutional policies. Legitimacy in the case of global governance
institutions, then, is the right to rule, understood to mean both that
institutional agents are morally justified in making rules and
attempting to secure compliance with them and that people subject to
those rules have moral, content-independent reasons to follow them
and/or to not interfere with others' compliance with them.
If it becomes widely believed that an institution does not measure
up to standards of legitimacy, then the result may be a lack of
coordination, at least until the institution changes to conform to the
standards or a new institution that better conforms to them replaces it.
Thus, it would be misleading to say simply that the function of
legitimacy judgments is to achieve coordinated support for institutions;
rather, their function is to make possible coordinated support based on
moral reasons, while at the same time supplying a critical but realistic
minimal moral standard by which to determine whether institutions are
worthy of support.
Justice and Legitimacy
The foregoing account of the social function of legitimacy
assessments helps clarify the relationship between justice and
legitimacy. Collapsing legitimacy into justice undermines the valuable
social function of legitimacy assessments. There are two reasons not to
insist that only just institutions have the right to rule. First, there
is sufficient disagreement on what justice requires that such a standard
for legitimacy would thwart the eminently reasonable goal of securing
coordinated support for valuable institutions on the basis of moral
reasons. Second, even if we all agreed on what justice requires,
withholding support from institutions because they fail to meet the
demands of justice would be self-defeating from the standpoint of
justice itself, because progress toward justice requires effective
institutions. To mistake legitimacy for justice is to make the best the
enemy of the good.
COMPETING STANDARDS OF LEGITIMACY
Having explicated our conception of legitimacy, we now explore
standards of legitimacy: the conditions an institution must satisfy in
order to have the right to rule. In this section we articulate three
candidates for the appropriate standard of legitimacy--state consent,
consent by democratic states, and global democracy--and argue that each
is inadequate.
State Consent
The first view is relatively simple. Global governance institutions
are legitimate if (and only if) they are created through state consent.
In this conception, legitimacy is simply a matter of legality. Legally
constituted institutions, created by states according to the recognized
procedures of public international law and consistent with it, are ipso
facto legitimate or at the very least enjoy a strong presumption of
legitimacy. (12) Call this the International Legal Pedigree View (the
Pedigree View, for short). A more sophisticated version of the Pedigree
View would require the periodic reaffirmation of state consent, on the
grounds that states have a legitimate interest in determining whether
these institutions are performing as they are supposed to. (13)
The Pedigree View fails because it is hard to see how state consent
could render global governance institutions legitimate, given that many
states are non-democratic and systematically violate the human rights of
their citizens and are for that reason themselves illegitimate. State
consent in these cases cannot transfer legitimacy for the simple reason
that there is no legitimacy to transfer. To assert that state consent,
regardless of the character of the state, is sufficient for the
legitimacy of global governance institutions is to regress to a
conception of international order that fails to impose even the most
minimal normative requirements on states. Indeed, once we abandon that
deeply defective conception of international order, it is hard to see
why state consent is even a necessary condition for legitimacy.
It might be argued, however, that even though the consent of
illegitimate states cannot itself make global governance institutions
legitimate, there is an important instrumental justification for
treating state consent as a necessary condition for their legitimacy:
doing so provides a check on the tendency of stronger states to exploit
weak ones. In other words, persisting in the fiction that all
states--irrespective of whether they respect the basic rights of their
own citizens--are moral agents worthy of respect serves an important
value. This conception of the state, however, is not a fiction that
those who take human rights seriously can consistently accept.
The proponent of state consent might reply as follows: "My
proposal is not that we should return to the pernicious fiction of the
Morality of States. Instead, it is that we should agree, for good
cosmopolitan reasons, to regard a global governance institution as
legitimate only if it enjoys the consent of all states."
Withholding legitimacy from global governance institutions, no matter
how valuable they are, simply because not all states consent to them,
however, would purport to protect weaker states at the expense of giving
a legitimacy veto to tyrannies. The price is too high. Weak states are
in a numerical majority in multilateral institutions. Generally
speaking, they are less threatened by the dominance of powerful states
within the institutions than they are by the actions of such powerful
states acting outside of institutional constraints.
The Consent of Democratic States
The idea that state consent confers legitimacy is much more
plausible when restricted to democratic states. On reflection, however,
the mere fact of state consent, even when the state in question is
democratic and satisfies whatever other conditions are appropriate for
state legitimacy, is not sufficient for the legitimacy of global
governance institutions.
From the standpoint of a particular weak democratic state,
participation in global governance institutions such as the WTO is
hardly voluntary, since the state would suffer serious costs by not
participating. Yet "substantial" voluntariness is generally
thought to be a necessary condition for consent to play a legitimating
role. (14) Of course, there may be reasonable disagreements over what
counts as substantial voluntariness, but the vulnerability of individual
weak states is serious enough to undercut the view that the consent of
democratic states is by itself sufficient for legitimacy.
There is another reason why the consent of democratic states is not
sufficient for the legitimacy of global governance institutions: the
problem of reconciling democratic values with unavoidable
"bureaucratic discretion" that plagues democratic theory at
the domestic level looms even larger in the global case. The problem is
that for a modern state to function, much of what state agents do will
not be subject to democratic decisions, and saying that the public has
consented in some highly general way to whatever it is that state agents
do is clearly inadequate. The difficulty is not in identifying chains of
delegation stretching from the individual citizen to state agents, but
rather that at some point the impact of the popular will on how
political power is used becomes so attenuated as to be merely nominal.
Given how problematic democratic authorization is in the modern state
and given that global governance institutions require lengthening the
chain of delegation, democratic state consent is not sufficient for
legitimacy.
Still, the consent of democratic states may appear to be necessary,
if not sufficient, for the legitimacy of global governance institutions.
Indeed, it seems obvious that for such an institution to attempt to
impose its rules on democratic states without their consent would
violate the right of self-determination of the people of those states.
Matters are not so simple, however. A democratic people's right of
self-determination is not absolute. If the majority persecutes a
minority, the fact that it does so through democratic processes does not
render the state in question immune to sanctions or even to
intervention. One might accommodate this fact by stipulating that a
necessary condition for the legitimacy of global governance institutions
is that they enjoy the consent of states that are democratic and that do
a credible job of respecting the rights of all their citizens.
This does not mean that all such states must consent. A few such
states may willfully seek to isolate themselves from global governance
(Switzerland only joined the UN in 2002). Furthermore, democratic states
may engage in wars that are unnecessary and unjust, and resist pressures
from international institutions to desist. It would hardly delegitimize a global governance institution established to constrain unjust warfare
that it was opposed by a democratic state that was waging an unjust war.
A more reasonable position would be that there is a strong presumption
that global governance institutions are illegitimate unless they enjoy
the ongoing consent of democratic states. Let us say, then, that ongoing
consent by rights-respecting democratic states constitutes the
democratic channel of accountability. (15)
However valuable the democratic channel of accountability is, it is
not sufficient. First, as already noted, the problem of bureaucratic
discretion that attenuates the power of majoritarian processes at the
domestic level seems even more serious in the case of global
bureaucracies. Second, not all the people who are affected by global
governance institutions are citizens of democratic states, so even if
the ongoing consent of democratic states fosters accountability, it may
not foster accountability to them. If--as is the case at
present--democratic states tend to be richer and hence more powerful
than nondemocratic ones, then the requirement of ongoing consent by
democratic states may actually foster a type of accountability that is
detrimental to the interests of the world's worst-off people. From
the standpoint of any broadly cosmopolitan moral theory, this is a deep
flaw of domestic democracies as ordinarily conceived: government is
supposed to be responsive to the interests and preferences of the
"sovereign people"--the people whose government it is--not all
people or even all people whose legitimate interests will be seriously
affected by the government's actions. (16) For these reasons, the
consent of democratic states seems insufficient. The idea that the
legitimacy of global governance institutions requires democracy on a
grander scale may seem plausible.
Global Democracy
Because democracy is now widely thought to be the gold standard for
legitimacy in the case of the state, it may seem obvious that global
governance institutions are legitimate if and only if they are
democratic. And since these institutions increasingly affect the welfare
of people everywhere, surely this must mean that they ought to be
democratic in the sense of giving everyone an equal say in how they
operate. Call this the Global Democracy View.
The most obvious difficulty with this view is that the social and
political conditions for democracy are not met at the global level and
there is no reason to think that they will be in the foreseeable future.
At present there is no global political structure that could provide the
basis for democratic control over global governance institutions, even
if one assumes that democracy requires little direct participation by
individuals. Any attempt to create such a structure in the form of a
global democratic federation that relies on existing states as federal
units would lack legitimacy, and hence could not confer legitimacy on
global governance institutions, because, as has already been noted, many
states are themselves undemocratic or lack other qualities necessary for
state legitimacy. Furthermore, there is at present no global public--no
worldwide political community constituted by a broad consensus
recognizing a common domain as the proper subject of global collective
decision-making and habitually communicating with one another about
public issues. Nor is there consensus on a normative framework within
which to deliberate together about a global common interest. Indeed,
there is not even a global consensus that some form of global
government, much less a global democracy, is needed or appropriate.
Finally, once it is understood that it is liberal democracy, democracy
that protects individual and minority rights, that is desirable, the
Global Democracy View seems even more unfeasible. Democracy worth
aspiring to is more than elections; it includes a complex web of
institutions, including a free press and media, an active civil society,
and institutions to check abuses of power by administrative agencies and
elected officials.
Global governance institutions provide benefits that cannot be
provided by states and, as we have argued, securing those benefits may
depend upon these institutions being regarded as legitimate. The value
of global governance institutions, therefore, warrants being more
critical about the assumption that they must be democratic on the
domestic model and more willing to explore an alternative conception of
their legitimacy. In the next section we take up this task.
A COMPLEX STANDARD OF LEGITIMACY
Desiderata for a Standard of Legitimacy
Our discussion of the social function of legitimacy assessments and
our critique of the three dominant views on the standard of legitimacy
for global governance institutions (state consent, democratic state
consent, and global democracy) suggest that a standard of legitimacy for
such institutions should have the following characteristics:
1. It must provide a reasonable public basis for coordinated
support for the institutions in question, on the basis of moral reasons
that are widely accessible in spite of the persistence of significant
moral disagreement--in particular, about the requirements of justice.
2. It must not confuse legitimacy with justice but nonetheless must
not allow that extremely unjust institutions are legitimate.
3. It must take the ongoing consent of democratic states as a
presumptive necessary condition, though not a sufficient condition, for
legitimacy.
4. Although the standard should not make authorization by a global
democracy a necessary condition of legitimacy, it should nonetheless
promote the key values that underlie demands for democracy.
5. It must properly reflect the dynamic character of global
governance institutions: the fact that not only the means they employ,
but even their goals, may and ought to change over time.
6. It must address the two problems we encountered earlier: the
problem of bureaucratic discretion and the tendency of democratic states
to disregard the legitimate interests of foreigners.
The standard of legitimacy must therefore incorporate mechanisms
for accountability that are both more robust and more inclusive than
that provided by the consent of democratic states.
Moral Disagreement and Uncertainty
The first desideratum of a standard of legitimacy is complex and
warrants further explication and emphasis. We have noted that a central
feature of the circumstances of legitimacy is the persistence of
disagreement about, first, what the proper goals of the institution are
(given the limitations imposed by state sovereignty properly conceived),
second, what global justice requires, and third, what role if any the
institution should play in the pursuit of global justice. Moral
disagreement is not unique to global governance institutions, but
extends also to the appropriate role of the state.
There are two circumstances in the case of global governance
institutions, however, that exacerbate the problem of moral
disagreement. First, in the case of the state, democratic processes, at
least ideally, provide a way of accommodating these disagreements, by
providing a public process that assures every citizen that she is being
treated as an equal, through the electoral process, while, as we have
seen, democracy is unavailable at the global level. Second, although
there is a widespread perception, at least among cosmopolitans broadly
speaking, that there is serious global injustice and that the effective
pursuit of global justice requires a significant role for global
institutions, it is not possible at present to provide a principled
specification of the division of institutional labor for pursuing global
justice. In part the problem is that there is no unified system of
global institutions within which a fair and effective allocation of
institutional responsibilities for justice can be devised. How
responsibilities for justice ought to be allocated among global
institutions and between states and global institutions depends chiefly
on the answers to two questions: What are the proper responsibilities of
states in the pursuit of global justice, taking into account the proper
scope of state sovereignty (because this will determine how extensive
the role of global institutions should be), and what are the
capabilities of various global institutions for contributing to the
pursuit of global justice? But neither of these questions can be
answered satisfactorily at present, in part because global governance
institutions are so new and in part because people have only recently
begun to think seriously about achieving justice on a global scale. So
the difficulty is not just that there is considerable moral disagreement
about the proper goals of global governance institutions and about the
role these institutions should play in the pursuit of global justice;
there is also moral uncertainty. (17) A plausible standard of legitimacy
for global governance institutions must somehow accommodate the facts of
moral disagreement and uncertainty.
Three Substantive Criteria
We begin with a set of institutional attributes that have
considerable intuitive appeal: minimal moral acceptability, comparative
benefit, and institutional integrity.
Minimal Moral Acceptability. Global governance institutions, like
institutions generally, must not persist in committing serious
injustices. If they do so, they are not entitled to our support. On our
view, the primary instance of a serious injustice is the violation of
human rights. We also believe that the most plausible conception of
human rights is what might be called the basic human interest
conception. This conception, which we can only sketch in broad outlines
here, builds on Joseph Raz's insight that rights generally are
normative relations (in particular, duties and entitlements), which, if
realized, provide important protections for interests. (18) On this
view, to justify the claim that R is a right, one must identify an
interest, support the claim that the interest is of sufficient moral
importance to ground duties, explain why the duties are owed to the
right holders, and make the case that if the normative relations in
question are satisfied, significant protection for the interest will be
achieved. Certain rights are properly called human rights because the
duties they entail provide especially important protections for basic
human interests, given the standard threats to those interests in our
world.
What the standard threats are can change over time. For example,
when human societies create legal systems and police and courts to
enforce laws, they also create new opportunities for damaging basic
human interests. For this reason, the content of particular human
rights, and even which rights are included among the human rights, may
also change, even though the basic interests that ground them do not.
For example, all human beings, regardless of where or when they exist,
have a basic interest in physical security, but in a society with a
legal system backed by the coercive power of the state, adequate
protection of this interest requires rights of due process and equal
protection under the law.
There is disagreement among basic interest theorists of human
rights as to exactly what the list of human rights includes and how the
content of particular rights is to be filled out. There is agreement,
however, that the list includes the rights to physical security, to
liberty (understood as at least encompassing freedom from slavery,
servitude, and forced occupations), and the right to subsistence.
Assuming that this is so, we can at least say this much: global
governance institutions (like institutions generally) are legitimate
only if they do not persist in violations of the least controversial
human rights. This is a rather minimal moral requirement for legitimacy.
Yet in view of the normative disagreement and uncertainty that
characterize our attitudes toward these institutions, it might be hard
at present to justify a more extensive set of rights that all such
institutions are bound to respect. It would certainly be desirable to
develop a more meaningful consensus on stronger human rights standards.
What this suggests is that we should require global governance
institutions to respect minimal human rights, but also expect them to
meet higher standards as we gain greater clarity about the scope of
human rights.
For many global governance institutions, it is proper to expect
that they should respect human rights, but not that they should play a
major role in promoting human rights. Nonetheless, a theory of
legitimacy cannot ignore the fact that in some cases the dispute over
whether a global governance institution is legitimate is in large part a
disagreement over whether it is worthy of support if it does not
actively promote human rights. A proposal for a standard of legitimacy
for global governance institutions must take into account the fact that
some of these institutions play a more direct and substantial role in
securing human rights than others.
When we see the injustices of our world and appreciate that
ameliorating them requires institutional actions, we are quick to
attribute obligations to institutions and then criticize them for
failing to fulfill those obligations. It is one thing to say that it
would be a good thing if a particular global governance institution took
on certain functions that would promote human rights, however, and quite
another to say that it has a duty to do so and that this duty is of such
importance that failure to discharge it makes the institution
illegitimate. There are two mistakes to be avoided here. The first is
"duty dumping," that is, arbitrarily assuming that some
particular institution has a duty simply because it has the resources to
fulfill it and no other actor is doing so. (19) Duty dumping not only
makes unsupported attributions of institutional responsibility; it also
distracts attention from the difficult task of determining what a fair
distribution of the burdens--among individuals and institutions--for
protecting the human rights in question would be. The second error
derives from the first: if one uncritically assumes that the institution
has a duty to provide X and also assumes that X is a central matter of
justice (as is the case with human rights), then one may conclude that
the institution's failure to provide X is such a serious injustice
as to rob the institution of legitimacy. But the fact that an
institution could provide X and the fact that X is a human right does
not imply that in refraining from providing X the institution commits a
serious injustice. That conclusion would only follow if it were
established that the institution has a duty of justice to provide X.
Merely pointing out that the institution could provide X--or even
showing that it is the only existing institution that can do so--is not
sufficient to show that it has a duty of justice or any duty at all to
provide X.
We seem to be in a quandary. Contemporary institutions have to
operate in an environment of moral disagreement and uncertainty, which
limits the demands we can reasonably place on them to respect or protect
particular human rights. Furthermore, to be sufficiently general, an
account of legitimacy must avoid moral requirements that only apply to
some global governance institutions. These considerations suggest the
appropriateness of something like the minimal moral acceptability
requirement, understood as refraining from violations of the least
controversial human rights. On the other hand, the standard of
legitimacy should somehow reflect the fact that part of what is at issue
in disputes over the legitimacy of some of these institutions is whether
they should satisfy more robust demands of justice. In other words, the
standard should acknowledge the fact that where the issue of legitimacy
is most urgent, there is likely to be deep moral disagreement and
uncertainty.
In our view, the way out of this impasse is to build the conditions
needed for principled, informed deliberation about moral issues into the
standard of legitimacy itself. The standard of legitimacy should require
minimal moral acceptability, but should also accommodate and even
encourage the possibility of developing more determinate and demanding
requirements of justice for at least some of these institutions, as a
principled basis for an institutional division of labor regarding
justice emerges.
Comparative Benefit. This second substantive condition for
legitimacy is relatively straightforward. The justification for having
global governance institutions is primarily if not exclusively
instrumental. The basic reason for states or other addressees of
institutional rules to take them as binding and for individuals
generally to support or at least to not interfere with the operation of
these institutions is that they provide benefits that cannot otherwise
be obtained. If an institution cannot effectively perform the functions
invoked to justify its existence, then this insufficiency undermines its
claim to the right to rule.
"Benefit" here is comparative. The legitimacy of an
institution is called into question if there is an institutional
alternative, providing significantly greater benefits, that is feasible,
accessible without excessive transition costs, and meets the minimal
moral acceptability criterion. The most difficult issues, as discussed
below, concern trade-offs between comparative benefit and our other
criteria. Legitimacy is not to be confused with optimal efficacy and
efficiency. The other values that we discuss are also important in their
own right; and in any case, institutional stability is a virtue.
Nevertheless, if an institution steadfastly remains instrumentally
suboptimal when it could take steps to become significantly more
efficient or effective, this could impugn its legitimacy in an indirect
way: it would indicate that those in charge of the institution were
either grossly incompetent or not seriously committed to providing the
benefits that were invoked to justify the creation of the institution in
the first place. For instance, as of the beginning of 2006 the United
Nations faced the issue of reconstituting a Human Rights Commission that
had been discredited by the membership of states that notoriously abuse
human rights, with Libya serving as chair in 2003. (20)
Institutional Integrity. If an institution exhibits a pattern of
egregious disparity between its actual performance, on the one hand, and
its self-proclaimed procedures or major goals, on the other, its
legitimacy is seriously called into question. The United Nations
Oil-for-Food scandal is a case in point. The Oil-for-Food Program was
devised to enable Iraqi oil to be sold, under strict controls, to pay
for food imports under the UN-mandated sanctions of the 1990s. The
purpose was both to prevent malnutrition in Iraq and to counter Iraqi
propaganda holding the United Nations responsible for the deaths of
hundreds of thousands of Iraqi children, without relieving the pressure
on Saddam Hussein's regime to get rid of its supposed weapons of
mass destruction. Yet it led to a great deal of corruption. Oil-for-Food
became a huge program, permitting the government of Iraq to sell $64.2
billion of oil to 248 companies, and enabling 3,614 companies to sell
$34.5 billion of humanitarian goods to Iraq. Yet more than half of the
companies involved paid illegal surcharges or kickbacks to Saddam and
his cronies, resulting in large profits for corporations and pecuniary benefits for some program administrators, including at least one
high-level UN official. (21) The most damning charge is that neither the
Security Council oversight bodies nor the Office of the
Secretary-General followed the UN's prescribed procedures for
accountability. At least when viewed in the light of the historical
record of other, perhaps less egregious failures of accountability in
the use of resources on the part of the UN, these findings have raised
questions about the legitimacy of the Security Council and the
secretariat.
It also appears that an institution should be presumed to be
illegitimate .if its practices or procedures predictably undermine the
pursuit of the very goals in terms of which it justifies its existence.
Thus, for example, if the fundamental character of the Security
Council's decision-making process renders that institution
incapable of successfully pursuing what it now acknowledges as one of
its chief goals--stopping large-scale violations of basic human
rights--this impugns its legitimacy. To take another example, Randall
Stone has shown that the IMF during the 1990s inconsistently applied its
own standards with respect to its lending, systematically relaxing
enforcement on countries that had rich and powerful patrons. (22)
Similarly, if the WTO claims to provide the benefits of trade
liberalization to all of its members, but consistently develops policies
that exclude its weaker members from the benefits of liberalization,
this undermines its claim to legitimacy. If an institution fails to
satisfy the integrity criterion, we have reason to believe that key
institutional agents are either untrustworthy or grossly incompetent,
that the institution lacks correctives for these deficiencies, and that
the institution is therefore unlikely to be effective in providing the
goods that would give it a claim to our support.
Integrity and comparative benefit are related but distinct. If
there are major discrepancies between an institution's behavior and
its prescribed procedures and professed goals, then we can have little
confidence that it will succeed in delivering the benefits it is
supposed to provide. Integrity, however, is a more forward-looking,
dynamic virtue than comparative benefit, which measures benefit solely
in terms of the current situation. If an institution satisfies the
criterion of integrity, there is reason to be confident that
institutional actors will not only deliver the benefits that are now
taken to constitute the proper goals of institutional activity, but also
that they will be able to maintain the institution's effectiveness
if its goals change.
Epistemic Aspects of Legitimacy
Minimal moral acceptability, comparative benefit, and institutional
integrity are plausible presumptive substantive requirements for the
legitimacy of global governance institutions. It would be excessive to
claim that they are necessary conditions simpliciter, because there
might be extraordinary circumstances in which an institution would fail
to satisfy one or two of them, yet still reasonably be regarded as
legitimate. This might be the case if there were no feasible and
accessible alternative institutional arrangement, if the
noninstitutional alternative were sufficiently grim, and if there was
reason to believe that the institution had the resources and the
political will to correct the deficiency. How much we expect of an
institution should depend, inter alia, upon how valuable the benefits it
provides are and whether there are acceptable, feasible alternatives to
it. For example, we might be warranted in regarding an institution as
legitimate even though it lacked integrity, if it were nonetheless
providing important protections for basic human rights and the
alternatives to relying on it were even less acceptable. In contrast,
the fact that an institution is effective in incrementally liberalizing
trade would not be sufficient to rebut the presumption that it is
illegitimate because it abuses human rights. (23)
Our three substantive conditions are best thought of as what Rawls
calls "counting principles": the more of them an institution
satisfies, and the higher the degree to which it satisfies them, the
stronger its claim to legitimacy. (24)
There are two limitations on the applicability of these three
criteria, however. The first is the problem of factual knowledge: being
able to make reasonable judgments about whether an institution satisfies
any of the three substantive conditions requires considerable
information about the workings of the institution and their effects in a
number of domains, as well as about the likely effects of feasible
alternatives. Some institutions may not only fail to supply the needed
information, however; they may, whether deliberately or otherwise, make
such information either impossible for outsiders to obtain or make
obtaining it prohibitively costly. Even if the institution does not try
to limit access to the relevant information, it may not be accessible,
in suitably integrated, understandable form.
The second difficulty with taking the three substantive conditions
as jointly sufficient for legitimacy is the problem of moral
disagreement and uncertainty noted earlier. Even if there is sufficient
agreement on what counts as the violation of basic human rights, there
are ongoing disputes about whether some global governance institutions
should meet higher moral standards. As emphasized above, there is not
only disagreement but also uncertainty as to the role that some of these
institutions should play in the pursuit of global justice, chiefly
because we do not have a coherent idea of what the institutional
division of labor for achieving global justice would look like.
Furthermore, merely requiring that global governance institutions
not violate basic human rights is unresponsive to the familiar complaint
that rich countries unfairly dominate them, and that even if they
provide benefits to all, the richer members receive unjustifiably
greater benefits. Although all parties may agree that fairness matters,
however, there are likely to be disagreements about what fairness would
consist of, disputes about whether fairness would suffice or whether
equality is required, and about how equality is to be understood and
even over what is to be made equal (welfare, opportunities, resources,
and so on). So, quite apart from the issue of what positive role, if
any, these institutions should play in the pursuit of global justice,
there is disagreement about what standards of fairness they should meet
internally. There is also likely to be disagreement about how unfair an
institution must be to lack legitimacy. A proposal for a public global
standard of legitimacy must not gloss over these disagreements.
In the following sections we argue that the proper response to both
the problem of factual knowledge and the problem of moral disagreement
and uncertainty is to focus on what might be called the
epistemic-deliberative quality of the institution, the extent to which
the institution provides reliable information needed for grappling with
normative disagreement and uncertainty concerning its proper functions.
To lay the groundwork for that argument we begin by considering two
items that are often assumed to be obvious requirements for the
legitimacy of global governance institutions: accountability and
transparency.
Accountability. Critics of global governance institutions often
complain that they lack accountability. To understand the strengths and
limitations of accountability as a gauge of legitimacy, we start with a
skeletal but serviceable analysis of accountability. Accountability
includes three elements: first, standards that those who are held
accountable are expected to meet; second, information available to
accountability holders, who can then apply the standards in question to
the performance of those who are held to account; and third, the ability
of these accountability holders to impose sanctions--to attach costs to
the failure to meet the standards. The need for information about
whether the institution is meeting the standards accountability holders
apply means that a degree of transparency regarding the
institution's operations is essential to any form of
accountability.
It is misleading to say that global governance institutions are
illegitimate because they lack accountability and to suggest that the
key to making them legitimate is to make them accountable. Most global
governance institutions, including those whose legitimacy is most
strenuously denied, include mechanisms for accountability. (25) The
problem is that existing patterns of accountability are morally
inadequate. For example, the World Bank has traditionally exhibited a
high degree of accountability, but it has been accountability to the
biggest donor countries, and the Bank therefore has to act in conformity
with their interests, at least insofar as they agree. This kind of
accountability does not ensure meaningful participation by those
affected by rules or due consideration of their legitimate interests.
(26) A high degree of accountability in this case may serve to
perpetuate the defects of the institution.
So accountability per se is not sufficient; it must be the right
sort of accountability. At the very least, this means that there must be
effective provisions in the structure of the institution to hold
institutional agents accountable for acting in ways that ensure
satisfaction of the minimal moral acceptability and comparative benefit
conditions. But accountability understood in this narrow way is not
sufficiently dynamic to serve as an assurance of the legitimacy of
global governance institutions, given that in some cases there is
serious disagreement about what the goals of the institution should be
and, more specifically, about what role if any the institution should
play in the pursuit of global justice. The point is that what the terms
of accountability ought to be--what standards of accountability ought to
be employed, who the accountability holders should be, and whose
interests the accountability holders should represent--cannot be
definitively ascertained without knowing what role, if any, the
institution should play in the pursuit of global justice.
Therefore, what might be called narrow
accountability--accountability without provision for contestation of the
terms of accountability--is insufficient for legitimacy, given the facts
of moral disagreement and uncertainty. Because what constitutes
appropriate accountability is itself subject to reasonable dispute, the
legitimacy of global governance institutions depends in part upon
whether they operate in such a way as to facilitate principled,
factually informed deliberation about the terms of accountability. There
must be provisions for revising existing standards of accountability and
current conceptions of who the proper accountability holders are and
whose interests they should represent.
Transparency. Achieving transparency is often touted as the proper
response to worries about the legitimacy of global governance
institutions. (27) But transparency by itself is inadequate. First, if
transparency means merely the availability of accurate information about
how the institution works, it is insufficient even for narrow
accountability--that is, for ensuring that the institution is accurately
evaluated in accordance with the current terms of accountability. If
information about how the institution operates is to serve the end of
narrow accountability, it must be (a) accessible at reasonable cost, (b)
properly integrated and interpreted, and (c) directed to the
accountability holders. Furthermore, (d) the accountability holders must
be adequately motivated to use it properly in evaluating the performance
of the relevant institutional agents. Second, if, as we have suggested,
the capacity for critically revising the terms of accountability is
necessary for legitimacy, information about how the institution works
must be available not only to those who are presently designated as
accountability holders, but also to those who may contest the terms of
accountability.
Broad transparency is needed for critical revisability of the terms
of accountability. Both institutional practices and the moral principles
that shape the terms of accountability must be revisable in the light of
critical reflection and discussion. (28) Under conditions of broad
transparency, information produced initially to enable institutionally
designated accountability holders to assess officials' performance
may be appropriated by agents external to the institution, such as
nongovernmental organizations (NGOs) and other actors in transnational
civil society, and used to support more fundamental criticisms, not only
of the institution's processes and structures, but even of its most
fundamental goals and its role in the pursuit of global justice.
One especially important dimension of broad transparency is
responsibility for public justification. (29) Institutional actors must
offer public justifications of at least the more controversial and
consequential institutional policies and must facilitate timely critical
responses to them. Potential critics must be in a position to determine
whether the public justifications are cogent, whether they are
consistent with the current terms of accountability, and whether, if
taken seriously, these justifications call for revision of the current
terms of responsibility. To help ensure this dimension of broad
transparency, it may be worthwhile to draw on, while adapting, the
notice and comment procedures of administrative law at the domestic
level. (30)
Earlier we noted that although comparative benefit, minimal moral
acceptability, and integrity are reasonable presumptive necessary
conditions for legitimacy, it may be difficult for those outside the
institution to determine whether these conditions are satisfied. We
suggest that broad transparency can serve as a proxy for satisfaction of
the minimal moral acceptability, comparative benefit, and integrity
criteria. For example, it may be easier for outsiders to discover that
an institution is not responding to demands for information relevant to
determining whether it is violating its own prescribed procedures, than
to determine whether in fact it is violating them. Similarly, it may be
very difficult to determine whether an institution is comparatively
effective in solving certain global problems, but much easier to tell
whether it generates--or systematically restricts access to--the
information outsiders would need to evaluate its effectiveness. If an
institution persistently fails to cooperate in making available to
outsiders the information that would be needed to determine whether the
three presumptive necessary conditions are satisfied, that by itself
creates a presumption that it is illegitimate.
Legitimate global governance institutions should possess three
epistemic virtues. First, because their chief function is to achieve
coordination, they must generate and properly direct reliable
information about coordination points; otherwise they will not satisfy
the condition of comparative benefit. Second, because accountability is
required to determine whether they are in fact performing their current
coordinating functions efficiently and effectively requires narrow
transparency, they must at least be transparent in the narrow sense.
They must also have effective provisions for integrating and
interpreting the information current accountability holders need and for
directing it to them. Third, and most demanding, they must have the
capacity for revising the terms of accountability, and this requires
broad transparency: institutions must facilitate positive information
externalities to permit inclusive, informed contestation of their
current terms of accountability. There must be provision for ongoing
deliberation about what global justice requires and how the institution
in question fits into a division of institutional responsibilities for
achieving it.
Overcoming Informational Asymmetries
A fundamental problem of institutional accountability is that
insiders generally have better information about the institution than
outsiders. Outsiders can determine whether institutions enjoy the
consent of states, and whether states are democratic; but it may be very
difficult for them to reach well-informed conclusions about the minimal
moral acceptability, comparative benefit, and integrity conditions. Our
emphasis on epistemic institutional virtues is well suited to illuminate
these problems of asymmetrical information.
First, if institutional agents persist in failing to provide public
justifications for their policies and withhold other information
critical to the evaluation of institutional performance, we have good
reason to believe the institution is not satisfying the substantive
criteria for legitimacy. (31) Second, there may be an asymmetry of
knowledge in the other direction as well, and this can have beneficial
consequences for institutional accountability. Consider issue areas such
as human rights and the environment, which are richly populated with
independent NGOs that seek to monitor and criticize national governments
and global governance institutions and to suggest policy alternatives.
Suppose that in these domains there is a division of labor among
external epistemic actors. Some individuals and groups seek information
about certain types of issues, while others focus on other aspects, each
drawing on distinct but in some cases overlapping groups of experts.
Still others specialize in integrating and interpreting information
gathered by other external epistemic actors.
The fact that the information held by external epistemic actors is
dispersed will make it difficult for institutional agents to know what
is known about their behavior or to predict when potentially damaging
information may be integrated and interpreted in ways that make it
politically potent. The institutional agents' awareness of this
asymmetry will provide incentives for avoiding behavior for which they
may be criticized. A condition of productive uncertainty will exist:
although institutional agents will know that external epistemic actors
do not possess the full range of knowledge that they do, they will know
that there are many individuals and organizations gathering information
about the institution. Further, they will know that some of the
information that external epistemic actors have access to can serve as a
reliable proxy for information they cannot access. Finally, they will
also know that potentially damaging information that is currently
harmless because it is dispersed among many external epistemic agents
may at any time be integrated and interpreted in such a way as to make
it politically effective, but they will not be able to predict when this
will occur. Under these conditions, institutional agents will have
significant incentives to refrain from behavior that will attract
damning criticism, despite the fundamental asymmetry of knowledge
between insiders and outsiders.
This is not to say that the effects of transparency will always be
benign. Indeed, under some circumstances transparency can have malign
effects. As David Stasavage points out, "open-door bargaining ...
encourages representatives to posture by adopting overly aggressive
bargaining positions that increase the risks of breakdown in
negotiations." (32) When issues combine highly charged symbolic
elements with the need for incentives, conflicts between transparency
and efficiency may be severe. Our claim is not that outcomes are
necessarily better the more transparent institutions are. Rather, it is
that the dispersal of information among a plurality of external
epistemic actors provides some counterbalance to informational
asymmetries favoring insiders. There should be a very strong but
rebuttable presumption of transparency, because the ills of too much
transparency can be corrected by deeper, more sophisticated public
discussion, whereas there can be no democratic response to secret action
by bureaucracies not accountable to the public.
Furthermore, if national legislatures are to retain their
relevance--if what we have called the democratic accountability channel
is to be effective--they must be able to review the policies of global
governance institutions. (33) For legislatures to have information
essential to performing these functions, they need a flow of information
from transnational civil society. Monitoring is best done
pluralistically by transnational civil society, whereas the sanctions
aspects of accountability are more effectively carried out by
legislatures. With respect both to the monitoring and sanctioning
functions, broad transparency is conducive to the principled
revisability of institutions and to their improvement through
increasingly inclusive criticism and more deeply probing discussion over
time.
Institutional agents generally have incentives to prevent outsiders
from getting information that may eventually be interpreted and
integrated in damaging ways and to deprive outsiders of information that
can serve as a reliable proxy to assess institutional legitimacy. The
very reasons that make the epistemic virtues valuable from the
standpoint of assessing institutional legitimacy may therefore tempt institutional agents to ensure that their institutions do not exemplify these virtues. But institutional agents are also aware that it is
important for their institutions to be widely regarded as legitimate.
Outsiders deprived of access to information are likely to react as does
the prospective buyer of a used car who is prevented from taking it to
an independent mechanic. They will discount the claims of the insiders
and may conclude that the institution is illegitimate. So if there is a
broad consensus among outsiders that institutions are not legitimate
unless they exemplify the epistemic virtues, institutional agents will
have a weighty reason to ensure that their institutions do so.
Contestation and Revisability: Links to External Actors and
Institutions
We have argued that the legitimacy of global governance
institutions depends upon whether there is ongoing, informed, principled
contestation of their goals and terms of accountability. This process of
contestation and revision depends upon activities of actors outside the
institution. It is not enough for the institutions to make information
available. Other agents, whose interests and commitments do not coincide
too closely with those of the institution, must provide a check on the
reliability of the information, integrate it, and make it available in
understandable, usable form, to all who have a legitimate interest in
the operations of the institution. Such activities can produce positive
feedback, in which appeal to standards of legitimacy by the external
epistemic actors not only increases compliance with existing standards
but also leads to improvements in the quality of these standards
themselves. For these reasons, in the absence of global democracy, and
given the limitations of the democratic channel described earlier,
legitimacy depends crucially upon not only the epistemic virtues of the
institution itself but also on the activities of external episternic
actors. Effective linkage between the institution and external epistemic
actors constitutes what might be called the transnational civil society
channel of accountability.
The needed external epistemic actors, if they are effective, will
themselves be institutionally organized. (34) Institutional legitimacy,
then, is not simply a function of the institution's
characteristics; it also depends upon the broader institutional
environment in which the particular institution exists. To borrow a
biological metaphor, ours is an ecological conception of legitimacy.
All three elements of our complex standard of legitimacy are now in
place. First, global governance institutions should enjoy the ongoing
consent of democratic states. That is, the democratic accountability
channel must function reasonably well. Second, these institutions should
satisfy the substantive criteria of minimal moral acceptability,
comparative benefit, and institutional integrity. Third, they should
possess the epistemic virtues needed to make credible judgments about
whether the three substantive criteria are satisfied and to achieve the
ongoing contestation and critical revision of their goals, their terms
of accountability, and ultimately their role in a division of labor for
the pursuit of global justice, through their interaction with effective
external epistemic agents.
The Complex Standard frames the legitimacy of global governance
institutions as both dynamic and relational. Its emphasis on the
conditions for ongoing contestation and critical revision of the most
basic features of the institutions captures the exceptional moral
disagreement and uncertainty that characterize the circumstances of
legitimacy for this type of institution. While acknowledging the facts
of moral disagreement and uncertainty, the Complex Standard includes
provisions for developing more robust moral requirements for
institutions over time. The Complex Standard also makes it clear that
whether the institution is legitimate does not depend solely upon its
own characteristics, but also upon the epistemic-deliberative
relationships between the institution and epistemic actors outside it.
A Place for Democratic Values in the Absence of Global Democracy
Earlier we argued that it is a mistake to hold global governance
institutions to the standard of democratic legitimacy that is now widely
applied to states. We now want to suggest that when the Complex Standard
of legitimacy we propose is satisfied, important democratic values will
be served. For purposes of the present discussion we will assume, rather
than argue, that among the most important democratic values are the
following: first, equal regard for the fundamental interests of all
persons; second, decision-making about the public order through
principled, collective deliberation; and third, mutual respect for
persons as beings who are guided by reasons.
If the Complex Standard of legitimacy we propose is satisfied, all
three of these values will be served. To the extent that connections
between the institutions and external epistemic actors provide access to
information that is not restricted to certain groups but available
globally, it becomes harder for institutions to continue to exclude
consideration of the interests of certain groups, and we move closer
toward the ideal of equal regard for the fundamental interests of all.
Furthermore, by making information available globally, networks of
external epistemic actors are in effect addressing all people as
individuals for whom moral reasons, not just the threat of coercion,
determine whether they regard an institution's rules as
authoritative. Finally, if the Complex Standard of legitimacy is
satisfied, every feature of the institution becomes a potential object
of principled, informed, collective deliberation, and eligibility for
participation in deliberation will not be restricted by institutional
interests. (35)
Consistency with Democratic Sovereignty
One source of doubts about the legitimacy of global governance
institutions is the worry that they are incompatible with democratic
sovereignty. Our analysis shows why and how global governance should
constrain democratic sovereignty. The standard of legitimacy we propose
is designed inter alia to help global governance institutions correct
for the tendency of democratic governments to disregard the interests
and preferences of those outside their own publics. It does this chiefly
in two ways. First, the emphasis on the role of external institutional
epistemic actors in achieving broad accountability helps to ensure more
inclusive representation of interests and preferences over time. Second,
the requirement of minimal moral acceptability, understood as
nonviolation of basic human rights, provides an important protection for
the most vulnerable: if this condition is met, democratic publics cannot
ignore the most serious "negative externalities" of their
policy choices. Global governance institutions that satisfy our standard
of legitimacy should not be viewed as undermining democratic
sovereignty, but rather as enabling democracies to function justly.
A legitimate global order will include human rights institutions
that promote the conditions for the proper functioning of democracy (the
right to basic education, the right to freedom of expression and
association, and so on) in countries that are democratizing and help
sustain these conditions in countries that already have democratic
institutions. Critics of global governance institutions that claim they
are illegitimate because they constrain democratic sovereignty either
beg the question by assuming that the "will of the people"
should not be constrained so as to take into account the interests of
those outside their polity or they underestimate the extent to which
democracy depends upon global governance institutions.
Having articulated the Complex Standard, and indicated how it
reflects several key democratic values, we can now show, briefly, how it
satisfies the desiderata for a standard of legitimacy we set out
earlier.
1. The Complex Standard provides a reasonable basis for coordinated
support of institutions that meet the standard, support based on moral
reasons that are widely accessible in the circumstances under which
legitimacy is an issue. To serve the social function of legitimacy
assessments, the Complex Standard only requires a consensus on the
importance of not violating the most widely recognized human rights,
broad agreement that comparative benefit and integrity are also
presumptive necessary conditions of legitimacy, and a commitment to
inclusive, informed deliberation directed toward resolving or at least
reducing the moral disagreement and uncertainty that characterize our
practical attitudes toward these institutions. In other words, the
Complex Standard steers a middle course between requiring more moral
agreement than is available in the circumstances of legitimacy and
abandoning the attempt to construct a more robust, shared moral
perspective from which to evaluate global governance institutions. In
particular, the Complex Standard acknowledges that the role that these
institutions ought to play in a more just world order is both deeply
contested and probably not knowable at present.
2. In requiring only minimal moral acceptability at present, the
Complex Standard acknowledges that legitimacy does not require justice,
but at the same time affirms the intuition that extreme injustice,
understood as violation of the most widely recognized human rights, robs
an institution of legitimacy.
3. The Complex Standard takes the ongoing consent of democratic
states to be a presumptive necessity, though not a sufficient condition
for legitimacy.
4. The Complex Standard rejects the assumption that global
governance institutions cannot be legitimate unless there is global
democracy, but at the same time promotes some of the key democratic
values, including informed, public deliberation conducted on the
assumption that every individual has standing to participate and the
requirement that key institutional policies must be publicly justified.
5. The Complex Standard reflects a proper appreciation of the
dynamic, experimental character of global governance institutions and of
the fact that not only the means they employ but even the goals they
pursue may and probably should change over time.
6. The Complex Standard's requirement of a functioning
transnational civil society channel of accountability--an array of
overlapping networks of external epistemic actors--helps to compensate
for the limitations of accountability through democratic state consent.
The central argument of this essay can now be summarized. The
Complex Standard provides a reasonable basis for agreement in legitimacy
assessments of global governance institutions. When the comparative
benefit condition is satisfied, the institution provides goods that are
not readily obtainable without it. These goods, however, can be reliably
provided only if coordination is achieved, and achieving coordination
without excessive costs requires that the relevant agents regard the
institution's rules as presumptively binding--that is, that they
take the fact that the rule is issued by the institution as a
content-independent reason for compliance. The instrumental value of
institutions that satisfy the comparative benefit condition also gives
individuals generally a content-independent reason not to interfere with
the functioning of the institutions. Satisfaction of the minimal moral
acceptability condition rules out the more serious moral objections that
might otherwise undercut the instrumental reasons for supporting the
institution. Satisfaction of the other conditions of the Complex
Standard, taken together, provides moral reasons to support or at least
not interfere with the institution. Among the most important of these
reasons is that the institution has epistemic virtues that facilitate
the development of more demanding standards and the progressive
improvement of the institution itself. Thus, when a global governance
institution meets the demands of the Complex Standard, there is
justification for saying that it has the right to rule, not merely that
it is beneficial.
CONCLUSION
In this essay we have offered a proposal for a public standard of
legitimacy for global governance institutions. These institutions supply
important benefits that neither states nor traditional treaty-based
relationships among states can provide, but they are quite new, often
fragile, and still evolving. Politically mobilized challenges to the
legitimacy of these institutions jeopardize the support they need to
function effectively, in spite of the fact that these challenges are
typically unprincipled and possibly grounded in unrealistic demands that
confuse justice with legitimacy. A principled global public standard of
legitimacy could facilitate more responsible criticism while at the same
time providing guidance for improvement, through a process of
institutionalized, collective learning, both about what it is reasonable
to expect from global governance institutions and about how to achieve
it. Our hope is that the proposal offered in this paper serves these
purposes.
Allen Buchanan and Robert O. Keohane *
* The authors are grateful to Sahar Akhtar, Christian Barry, Thomas
Christiano, Michael Doyle, Nicole Hassoun, Andrew Hurrell, Nan Keohane,
Avery Kolers, Joseph S. Nye, John Tasioulas, and two anonymous referees
for their helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper, and to
William Alford, Ryan Goodman, and Gerald L. Neuman for valuable
criticisms and suggestions when such a version was presented at Harvard
Law School, November 3, 2005. We are particularly grateful to comments
by Charles Beitz and a number of other colleagues made at a workshop on
the normative and empirical evaluation of global governance, Princeton
University, February 17-18, 2006. Further useful comments were made at
the conference on "Legitimacy and International Law" at the
Max Planck Institute for Comparative Public Law and International Law,
Heidelberg, Germany, June 13-14, 2006.
(1) A thorough review of the sociological literature on
organizational legitimacy can be found in Mark C. Suchman,
"Managing Legitimacy: Strategic and Institutional Approaches,"
Academy of Management Review 20, no. 3 (1995), pp. 571-610.
(2) For an excellent discussion of the inadequacy of existing
standards of legitimacy for global governance institutions, see Daniel
Bodansky, "The Legitimacy of International Governance: A Coming
Challenge for International Environmental Law?" American Journal of
International Law 93, no. 3 (1999), pp. 596-624. For an impressive
earlier book on the subject, see Thomas Franck, The Power of Legitimacy
Among Nations (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990). Franck's
account focuses on the legitimacy of rules more than institutions and in
our judgment does not distinguish clearly enough between the normative
and sociological senses of legitimacy.
(3) A large and growing literature exists on global governance.
See, for example, Aseem Prakash and Jeffrey A. Hart, eds., Globalization and Governance (London: Routledge, 1999); Joseph S. Nye and John D.
Donahue, eds., Governance in a Globalizing World (Washington: Brookings
Institution Press, 200o); and David Held and Anthony McGrew, eds.,
Governing Globalization (London: Polity Press, 2002).
(4) Erika de Wet, "The Security Council as
Legislator/Executive in Its Fight against Terrorism and against
Proliferation of Weapons of Mass Destruction: The Question of
Legitimacy" (presentation at the conference "Legitimacy and
International Law," Max Planck Institute for Comparative Public Law
and International Law, Heidelberg, Germany, June 14, 2006).
(5) The emphasis here on the coordinating function should not be
misunderstood: global governance institutions do not merely coordinate
state actions in order to satisfy preexisting state preferences. As our
analysis will make clear, they can also help shape state preferences and
lead to the development of new norms and institutional goals.
(6) Robert O. Keohane, After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in
the World Political Economy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984
[20th anniversary edition, 2005]).
(7) James D. Fearon, "Bargaining, Enforcement, and
International Cooperation," International Organization 52, no. 2
(Spring 1998), pp. 269-306.
(8) This is a major theme of Russell Hardin, Liberalism,
Constitutionalism, and Democracy (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1999).
(9) Andrew Hurrell, "Legitimacy and the Use of Force: Can the
Circle Be Squared?" Review of International Studies 31, supp. S1
(2005), p. 16.
(10) Legitimacy can also be seen as providing a "focal
point" that helps strategic actors select one equilibrium solution
among others. For the classic discussion of focal points, see Thomas C.
Schelling, The Strategy of Conflict (Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1960), ch. 3. For a critique of theories of cooperation on the
basis of focal point theory, and an application to the European Union,
see Geoffrey Garrett and Barry Weingast, "Ideas, Interests, and
Institutions: Constructing the European Community's Internal
Market," in Judith Goldstein and Robert O. Keohane, eds., Ideas and
Foreign Policy: Beliefs, Institutions and Political Change (Ithaca:
Cornell University Press, 1993), esp. pp. 178-85.
(11) Most contemporary analytic philosophical literature on
legitimacy tends to focus exclusively on the legitimacy of the state and
typically assumes a very strong understanding of legitimacy. In
particular, it is assumed that legitimacy entails (1) a
content-independent moral obligation to comply with all institutional
rules (not just content-independent moral reasons to comply and/or a
content-independent moral obligation to not interfere with others'
compliance), (2) being justified in using coercion to secure compliance
with rules, and (3) being justified in using coercion to exclude other
actors from operating in the institution's domain. (See, for
example, Christopher Heath Wellman and A. John Simmons, Is There a Duty
to Obey the Law? For and Against [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2005]). It is far from obvious, however, that this very strong
conception is even the only conception of legitimacy appropriate for the
state, given what is sometimes referred to as the "unbundling"
of sovereignty into various types of decentralized states and the
existence of the European Union. Be that as it may, this state-centered
conception is too strong for global governance institutions, which
generally do not wield coercive power or claim such strong authority.
For a more detailed development of this point, see Allen Buchanan,
"The Legitimacy of International Law," in Samantha Besson and
John Tasioulas, eds., The Philosophy of International Lave (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, forthcoming).
(12) This view was forcefully expressed by Professor Yoram Dinstein
of Tel Aviv University, in comments on a draft of this essay.
(13) For a more detailed discussion, see Allen Buchanan, Justice,
Legitimacy and Self-Determination: Moral Foundations for International
Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), esp. ch. 5.
(14) For a perceptive discussion of how consent to new
international trade rules in the Uruguay Round (1986-94) was merely
nominal, since the alternatives for poor countries were so unattractive,
see Richard H. Steinberg, "In the Shadow of Law or Power?
Consensus-based Bargaining and Outcomes in the GATT/WTO,"
International Organization 56, no. 2 (2002), pp. 339-74.
(15) How the requirement of ongoing consent should be
operationalized is a complex question we need not try to answer here;
one possibility would be that the treaties creating the institution
would have to be periodically reaffirmed.
(16) Buchanan, "The Legitimacy of International Law."
(17) For a valuable discussion that employs a different conception
of normative uncertainty, see Monica Hlavac, "A Developmental
Approach to the Legitimacy of Global Governance Institutions"
(unpublished paper).
(18) See Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1986), n. 17.
(19) Allen Buchanan and Matthew DeCamp, "Responsibility for
Global Health," Transnational Medicine (forthcoming).
(20) In March 2005, Secretary-General Kofi Annan called for the
replacement of the Commission on Human Rights (fifty-three members
elected from slates put forward by regional groups) with a smaller Human
Rights Council elected by a two-thirds vote of members of the General
Assembly (see his report 'tin Larger Freedom," A/59/2005,
para. 183).
(21) For the report of the Independent Inquiry Committee into the
United Nations Oil-for-Food Program (the Volcker Committee), dated
October 27, 2005, see www.iic-offp.org/story27oct05.htm.
(22) Randall W. Stone, "The Political Economy of IMF Lending
in Africa," American Political Science Review 98, no. 4 (2004), pp.
577-91. See also Randall W. Stone, Lending Credibility: The
International Monetary Fund and the Post-Communist Transition
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002).
(23) We are indebted to Andrew Hurrell for this example.
(24) John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1971).
(25) Ruth W. Grant and Robert O. Keohane, "Accountability and
Abuses of Power in World Politics," American Political Science
Review 99, no. 1 (2005), pp. 29-44. See also Robert O. Keohane and
Joseph S. Nye, "Redefining Accountability for Global
Governance," in Miles Kahler and David A. Lake, eds., Governance in
a Global Economy: Political Authority in Transition (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 2003), pp. 386-411.
(26) For a discussion, see Ngaire Woods, "Holding
Intergovernmental Institutions to Account," Ethics &
International Affairs 17, no. 1 (2003), pp. 69-80.
(27) Ann Florini, The Coming Democracy (Washington, D.C.: Island
Press, 2003).
(28) For a discussion of the role of critical revisability in
practical reasoning, with parallels to theoretical reasoning, see Mien
Buchanan, "Revisability and Rational Choice," Canadian Journal
of Philosophy 5, no. 3 (1975), pp. 395-408.
(29) For an illuminating account of the legitimacy of health care
institutions that emphasizes responsibility for justifications, see
Norman Daniels and James Sabin, "Limits to Health Care: Fair
Procedures, Democratic Deliberation, and the Legitimacy Problem for
Insurers," Philosophy & Public Affairs 26, no. 4 (1997), pp.
303-50.
(30) See Richard B. Stewart, "Administrative Law in the
Twenty-First Century," New York University Law Review 78, no. 2
(2003), pp. 437-60; and Benedict Kingsbury, Nikon Kirsch, and Richard B.
Stewart, "The Emergence of Global Administrative Law," Law and
Contemporary Problems 68, nos. 3 and 4 (2005). See also Daniel Esty,
"Toward Good Global Governance: The Role of Administrative
Law" (paper presented at a conference on global administrative law,
New York University, April 21-23, 2005). See also John Wickham,
"Toward a Green Multilateral Investment Framework: NAFTA and the
Search for Models," Georgetown International Environmental Law
Review 12, no. 3 (2000), pp. 617-46; James Salzman," Labor Rights,
Globalization, and Institutions: The Role and Influence of the
Organization for Economic Cooperation and Development," Michigan
Journal of International Law 21, no. 4 (2000), pp. 769-848; and OECD,
Getting to Grips with Globalization: The OECD in a Changing World
(Paris: OECD Publications, 2004).
(31) The analogy in the economics of information is to the market
for used cars. A potential buyer of a used car would be justified in
inferring poor quality if the seller were unwilling to let him have the
car thoroughly examined by a competent mechanic. See George A. Akerlof,
"The Market for Lemons: Quality Uncertainty and the Market
Mechanism," Quarterly Journal of Economics 84, no. 3 (1970), pp.
488-500.
(32) David Stasavage, "Open-Door or Closed-Door? Transparency
in Domestic and International Bargaining," International
Organization 58, no. 4 (2004), pp. 667-704.
(33) On the role of legislatures with respect to the legitimacy of
an international legal order, see Rudiger Wolfrum, "Legitimacy in
International Law: Some Introductory Considerations" (paper
prepared for the conference "Legitimacy in International Law"
at the Max Planck Institute for Comparative Public Law and International
Law, Heidelberg, Germany, June 13-14, 2006).
(34) We use the term "external epistemic actor" here
broadly, to include individuals and groups outside the institution in
question who gain knowledge about the institution, interpret and
integrate such knowledge, and exchange it with others, in ways that are
intended to influence institutional behavior, whether directly or
indirectly (through the mediation of the activities of other individuals
and groups).
(35) On our view, the legitimacy of global governance institutions,
at present at least, does not require participation in the critical
evaluation of institutional goals and policies by all who are affected
by them; but if the standard of legitimacy we recommend were accepted,
opportunities for participation would expand.