Decisiveness and accountability as part of a principled response to nonstate threats: "a threat to one is a threat to all": nonstate threats and collective security.
Keohane, Robert O.
The moral authority of an institution depends on the belief that it
is legitimate by those who are to be governed by its rules or who
support it. Legitimacy implies a right to make rules. This fight is
conferred either through the quality of the processes used to produce
the rules--"inputs'--or the quality of the results
achieved--"outputs." Input legitimacy is achieved through
following established procedures of authorization and activity that are
consistent with standards conforming to prevailing concepts of fairness,
even if not of perfect justice. The procedures must include considerable
transparency, mechanisms for accountability, and integrity--that is, a
pattern of practices consistent with the stated purposes of the
institution. Output legitimacy is achieved through a record of
accomplishments that can be judged, on the whole, to be good--and,
crucially, better than any feasible alternative institutional
arrangements would have produced.
The central institutions of the United Nations have substantially
lost moral authority since the Millennium Summit of 2000. The inability
to act on issues involving the use of force, the failure at the 2005
World Summit to agree on a definition of terrorism, the Oil-for-Food
scandal, and the perceived cronyism of so many delegations have
undermined the moral authority of the General Assembly and the Security
Council.
Principled responses to international problems are always desirable
for ethical reasons. At a time when the legitimacy of international
institutions is challenged, they become important also for political
reasons. If an international organization loses legitimacy, its
effectiveness suffers. Without legitimacy, the best the United Nations
could do with respect to threats by nonstate actors, the topic of this
roundtable, would be to serve as a channel for concerted state action.
Its decisions would merely reflect the individual decisions of powerful
states without significant input from UN leadership, thus undermining
any belief that the decisions are worthy of respect because they have
the imprimatur of the UN.
NONSTATE THREATS
In discussing nonstate threats, I emphasize such human actions as
the use of nuclear weapons by terrorists and the creation of diseases
through biological processes. I distinguish between
"threats"--which I limit to potentially very harmful
conditions created deliberately by human beings--and two other
categories of problems: (1) adverse changes in our social or natural
environment created inadvertently by human beings (such as climate
change, or violence possibly engendered by increasing acceptance of
violence in the media); or (2) more fundamental social problems, such as
world poverty and premature death due to preventable disease. The latter
two categories of problems are very serious-quite possibly more so than
nonstate threats--but I focus in these brief remarks on threats as
defined above. (1)
When does a threat become so severe that international action is
essential? In my view, this occurs when one of the following three
conditions obtains:
* When it could directly affect all of us (such as biological
terrorism)
* When the enormity of intentional harm is so great as to
profoundly affect our view of the human race (such as the Holocaust
during World War II, Rwanda in 1994, or a possible explosion of a
nuclear weapon by terrorists)
* When clear abuses are preventable at moderate cost (such as
Bosnia in 1993, or probably Sudan now). In such cases, a failure to act
implicates us and affects our fundamental view of ourselves and our
species.
Under any of these conditions, acceptance of an unacceptable
practice may be as problematic, and thus pose almost as much of a
threat, as the occasional bad practice itself. Acceptance of evil
affects our moral character and therefore shapes our response to other
abuses. We can live with occasional acts of terrorism and probably will
have to. We cannot live so easily with a failure to attempt to take
action, much less with the justification of the willful killing of
innocent people to intimidate others in a political cause. We may not be
able to do much about such justifications, but we should not respect
them as morally valid statements. Ethical concerns should not, however,
be divorced from considerations of efficacy. A key feature of threats is
that timely strategic action may be required to prevent their
materialization. Prompt, targeted action may be required to respond to
these threats; such action may well involve the use of force; and the
actions themselves may have to be shielded by some degree of secrecy to
be effective. The problem I wish to address is how to engage in decisive
strategic action in a principled way: without violating the principles
for which those of us who believe both in democracy and human rights
stand.
THE PRINCIPLE OF ACCOUNTABILITY
My fellow roundtable participants have mentioned a number of
important principles. The key principle that I want to discuss--which is
not necessarily the "most important," whatever that would
mean--is accountability. Accountability is a democratic principle. It
means that policy-makers have to "give an account" to
accountability holders--publics or otherwise. This requires three
things: (1) a set of standards to which they are held to account; (2)
relevant information available to the accountability holders; and (3)
the ability of the accountability holders to sanction the policy-makers.
Democratic accountability is participatory and facilitates popular
rule. But much accountability simply follows from delegation and is
designed to prevent abuses of power; for example, the executive
leadership of the World Bank is accountable to a board of state
representatives. In the United States and other democracies, there is a
more or less coherent public, and democratic accountability is feasible.
At the global level, now, it is not. So the "domestic analogy"
does not work. But other methods of accountability exist when we think
of it in terms of limitations on the abuse of power.
As the table on page 222 indicates, several types of accountability
mechanisms are already in place in world politics. Hierarchical and
supervisory mechanisms exist by which those entities that delegated
powers--states or larger-scale multilateral organizations--supervise the
exercise of those powers. Fiscal mechanisms also exist, ensuring that
international organizations will respond to their supervisors (even if
grudgingly) for fear of having funding cut off. The Oil-for-Food scandal
illustrates the weakness of UN supervisory and fiscal mechanisms and the
need to assure that UN financial procedures provide for more
accountability. Legal and market accountability are less directly
relevant to the UN, although they are highly relevant, respectively, to
legalized bodies such as the World Trade Organization, with its Dispute
Settlement Mechanism, and to multinational corporations. Peer
accountability refers to ways in which organizations may criticize the
operations of similar organizations. Were the central organs of the UN
to lose respect both among governments and other international
organizations, the consequences for its effectiveness, and ultimately
for funding, would be significant. Finally, reputation matters. The
reputational accountability of the United Nations refers to the fact
that, as emphasized in this article, a loss of reputation for the United
Nations would have a negative impact on its legitimacy and its
effectiveness.
The table below lists seven nonelectoral methods of accountability.
It is important to strengthen accountability mechanisms, which are
weak in general in world politics. They are weak in the UN, in NGOs,
with respect to multinational corporations, and in the governmental
networks discussed by Anne-Marie Slaughter. (2) They are particularly
weak relative to great powers, such as the United States, which are only
accountable internally to national publics, rather than externally to
outsiders whose lives they affect. The most successful solution to the
accountability problems of domestic bureaucracies has been
administrative law, and as a result, it is worthwhile to begin to
develop a coherent system of global administrative law. (3)
The Oil-for-Food scandal demonstrates that the UN needs more
systematic processes to assure accountability. So, in a broader sense,
does the Security Council when authorizing or not authorizing the use of
force, as the 2002-3 debates before the Iraq war demonstrate. Security
Council authorization is like someone writing a blank check: the council
neither directs the use of the military forces involved, nor can it hold
the great powers that use them accountable for their actions. The UN has
no systematic procedures for monitoring military activities that it
authorizes. The Security Council has no established practices either of
interrogating leaders of the states employing force or of modifying
authorizations in light of such questioning. Finally, it cannot punish
powerful states that exceed the limits of UN authorization.
As a result, even when a strong case for forcible action can be
made, states not in the inner circle of interveners are bound to be
skeptical. The gap between proclaimed future actions and the actual
deeds is often large. Without the ability to hold the interveners
accountable, and impose sanctions on them if they violate their pledges
or if their justifications for intervention turn out to be wildly wrong,
these states may prefer to take the course of inaction. Accountability
can therefore be a precondition for decisiveness: for the willingness of
large numbers of states to support forcible interventions.
Accountability is compatible with decisiveness because it operates
ex post, to assess decisions and assign rewards and penalties to
decision-makers, rather than ex ante, to control decisions. Ex ante,
arrangements may be agreed to for ex post accountability, but the
essence of accountability is that the accountability holders observe
actions by power wielders, which they judge according to a set of
standards. Holding power wielders accountable avoids the twin dangers of
indecisiveness due to group decision-making with multiple vetoes and
irresponsible, arbitrary action. As the table indicates, various
mechanisms of accountability can be devised that do not involve
elections. So it should in principle be possible to structure
institutions such as the UN to make them more accountable, on the basis
of public standards, without reducing their capacity for decisive
action.
THE NEED FOR ACTION TO ENHANCE UN LEGITIMACY
Unfortunately, the 2005 World Summit and the subsequent General
Assembly session did not produce the combination of decisiveness and
accountability that the UN needs. Many states seem so much to fear
concentration of power at the UN in the hands of the secretary-general
and the great powers that they would prefer the UN not to have the
ability to act at all. But either the UN will gain greater capacity for
decisive action, including both enhanced cohesion in the Security
Council and more powers for the secretary-general to run the
organization itself, or it will be weakened. Weakening can take place in
at least two ways: through greater unilateralism and reliance on
"coalitions of the willing," as in the case of the United
States' war against Saddam Hussein and occupation of Iraq; or
through more reliance on regional organizations (such as NATO),
transgovernmental networks, or nongovernmental organizations.
Maintaining the status quo in UN procedures is a recipe for a less
legitimate, and weaker, organization.
The legitimacy of the UN will be bolstered only if the organization
is able to act decisively against nonstate threats, as well as to solve
a variety of problems inherent in the unequal growth that characterizes
the world economy. But decisiveness without accountability is ultimately
arbitrary, and will not generate sustained support. An organization that
is decisive without being accountable would also not be legitimate.
Legitimacy requires both decisiveness and accountability, and
accountability may be a precondition, as we have just noted, for
decisiveness. Principled action against nonstate threats by the UN
therefore requires a bolstering of the organization's
accountability mechanisms.
(1) I am grateful to Professor Philip Cerny, who was in the
audience at the Carnegie Council Roundtable on December 13, 2005, for
clarifying this distinction in subsequent correspondence.
(2) Anne-Marie Slaughter, A New World Order (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 2004).
(3) Richard Stewart and Benedict Kingsbury at NYU Law School have a
very interesting project organized on this subject.
Robert O. Keohane, This article draws heavily, without further
citations, on my previously published work, including especially two
coauthored papers: Ruth W. Grant and Robert O. Keohane,
"Accountability and the Abuse of Power in World Politics,"
American Political Science Review 99, no. 1 (2005), pp. 29-44; and Allen
Buchanan and Robert O. Keohane, "The Preventive Use of Force: A
Cosmopolitan Institutional Proposal," Ethics & International
Affairs 18, no. 1 (2004), pp. 1-22.
Table 1. Seven Mechanisms of Accountability in World Politics
Accountability
Mechanism holder Power wielder
Hierarchical Leaders of Subordinate official
organization
Supervisory States Multilateral
organization
and executive head
Fiscal Funding agencies Funded agency
Legal Courts Individual official
or agency
Market Equity- and Firm
bondholders,
and consumers
Peer Peer organizations Organizations and
their leaders
Public Peers and Individual or agency
Reputational diffuse public
Mechanism Cost to power wielder Examples
Hierarchical Loss of career Authority of UN
opportunities secretary-general
Supervisory Restraints on ability World Bank and IMF
to act, loss of office governance by their
executive boards
Fiscal Budget restrictions Withholding of
UN dues
Legal From restriction of International
authority to Criminal Court
criminal penalties
Market Loss of access to, or Refusal of capital
higher cost of, capital markets to finance
developing-country
governments during
world financial crises
Peer Effects on network ties Independent marine
and therefore on certification body's
others' support evaluation of the
Greenpeace-Shell
controversy
Public Diffuse effects on Effects on U.S.
Reputational reputation, prestige, "soft power" of
self-esteem unilateralism
Source: Ruth Grant and Robert O. Keohane, "Accountability and Abuses
of Power in World Politics," American Political Science Review 99,
no. 1 (February 2005), pp. 29-44.