Precommitment regimes for intervention: supplementing the security council.
Buchanan, Allen ; Keohane, Robert O.
As global governance institutions proliferate and become more
powerful, their legitimacy is subject to ever sharper scrutiny. Yet what
legitimacy means in this context and how it is to be ascertained are
often unclear. In a previous paper in this journal, we offered a general
account of the legitimacy of such institutions and a set of standards
for determining when they are legitimate. (1) In this paper we focus on
the legitimacy of the UN Security Council as an institution for making
decisions concerning the use of military force across state borders. The
context for this topic has changed over the last decade as a result of
the ongoing development of the responsibility to protect (RtoP) doctrine
and extensive discussions about it in the United Nations. Yet the mostly
widely accepted proposals for RtoP still require Security Council
authorization for forceful intervention, and strictly limit the
conditions under which such intervention may take place.
The world currently lacks reliable multilateral arrangements both
to prevent humanitarian disasters and to protect fragile democratic
governments against coups and other violent attempts to overthrow them.
We are particularly interested in the protection of fragile democracies.
It is a valid question whether democratic publics should rely on the
Security Council, with its particular composition and permanent member
veto, to serve as their principal external guarantor. We argue that the
Security Council is a legitimate institution for making these decisions,
but that it does not possess unconditional exclusive legitimacy. That
is, under some conditions, multilateral coercive intervention to resolve
a humanitarian crisis or to counter the use of violence against
democratic governance could be legitimately authorized through other
means. Nevertheless, the dangers of unilateral intervention, or
intervention by a relatively small set of powerful states, are
sufficiently great that these other options should be quite carefully
restricted. In the final section of this paper we evaluate proposals for
institutions other than the Security Council to authorize the
multilateral use of force. We are skeptical about the authorization of
force by a democratic coalition, but we look with more sympathy on the
idea of establishing "precommitment regimes." Such regimes
would enable states to preselect groups of other states to intervene
legally, without Security Council authorization, in cases of
well-defined contingencies involving threats to struggling democracies
or major violations of human rights.
To begin, we set out a conceptual framework for assessing the
legitimacy of the Security Council. We distinguish between normative and
sociological legitimacy and between justice and legitimacy, and we
explain the distinctive practical function and value of legitimacy
assessments. We then proceed to discuss the legitimacy of Security
Council action, concluding that, despite some serious flaws, the
Security Council is arguably a legitimate institution for making
decisions regarding the use of force across borders.
Next we focus on the problem of Security Council inaction. This
problem became salient in the 1990s in the context of such humanitarian
emergencies as those in Somalia, Bosnia, and Rwanda. These concerns led
to a now famous report, The Responsibility to Protect, (2) and to almost
a decade of discussions in the United Nations about the principle of the
responsibility to protect and how it should be implemented. These
discussions culminated in a three-day debate in the UN General Assembly
in July 2009, which has provided a clear indication of the support of
most UN members for the principle of RtoP as interpreted by
Secretary-General Ban Ki-moon, as well as the range of concerns and
objections to its institutionalization. RtoP may ultimately lead to
broader international agreement on the conditions under which
humanitarian intervention is justified, but it does not resolve a
crucial issue: whether, if the Security Council refuses to act due to
the exercise of a Great Power veto, other means may legitimately be used
to authorize the use of armed force.
As mentioned above, in the final section we consider possible
reforms that would help to make RtoP more meaningful, including reforms
circumventing a Security Council veto. In our view, desirable reforms
must meet three criteria: (1) they must facilitate prompt action that
promises to be effective and not to worsen the situation; (2) they must
not undermine the near consensus formed, in the discussion of RtoP, on
the principle that under some conditions coercive multilateral
intervention is justifiable; and (3) they must not overlook the crucial
significance of building state capacity to prevent avoidable
humanitarian crises.
A CONCEPTUAL FRAMEWORK
Normative and Sociological Senses of "Legitimacy"
It is important at the outset to distinguish between the normative
and sociological sense of "legitimacy." An institution is
legitimate in the normative sense if and only if it has the right to
rule, broadly described. A legitimate institution is justified in
issuing rules and seeking to gain compliance with them by attaching
costs and benefits, and if those to whom it directs its rules have
content-independent reasons to comply. In other words, the fact that the
institution issues the rules itself counts as a reason for compliance,
irrespective of the substance of the rule. (3) In addition, legitimate
institutions are presumptively entitled to noninterference with their
proper activities. (4) Generally speaking, the proper response to the
defects of a legitimate institution is to try to reform it, rather than
to overthrow it.
Legitimacy in the normative sense is not to be confused with
legality. Agreement that the Security Council has exclusive legal
authority under international law does not settle whether it has
exclusive legitimacy; indeed, having legal authority may even be
compatible with its lacking legitimacy tout court. Similarly, whether
the NATO intervention in Kosovo was illegal is one question, and whether
it was legitimate is another, as the Goldstone report noted. (5)
In contrast to the normative conception, to say that an institution
is legitimate in the sociological sense is merely to say that it is
generally believed to have the right to rule. An institution might be
legitimate in the normative sense even if it was not legitimate in the
sociological sense--if, for example, there were a widespread erroneous
adverse belief about how it came to be or how it was currently
operating. Conversely, an institution might be widely believed to be
legitimate but lack legitimacy in the normative sense, if, for example,
it succeeded in hiding certain damaging information about itself.
Whether an institution is legitimate in the sociological sense can be
determined by surveys of opinion and observation of the behavior of
agents subject to its authority. Whether it is legitimate in the
normative sense is a moral question that can only be answered on the
basis of a defensible account of what characteristics an institution
must have in order to have the right to rule.
There is an important connection between the two senses of
legitimacy. To function effectively, an international institution
usually needs to be widely regarded as legitimate. This is particularly
true of international institutions that are not simple bargains for
mutual advantage and where free riding cannot be avoided by tit-for-tat
strategies. An institution that is not regarded as legitimate is more
likely, other things being equal, to provoke a backlash that may have
serious consequences. So designers of institutions should not simply aim
for ideally best arrangements, but must consider trade-offs between
moral desiderata and sociological legitimacy. In the remainder of this
essay we will first focus on normative legitimacy, but then go on to
consider its relationship to sociological legitimacy in our assessment
of proposals for alternatives to the Security Council.
A Standard of Legitimacy for Global Governance Institutions
Legitimacy is not the same as justice. An institution can fall
short of being fully just and yet be legitimate (although it is true
that severe injustices can rob it of legitimacy). When there is
pervasive disagreement and uncertainty about what justice requires, the
concept of legitimacy can play a uniquely valuable role by making
possible support for the institution that is based on moral reasons, not
merely on self-interest or the fear of coercion. People who disagree
about what justice requires may be able to agree in their judgments of
legitimacy. If there is considerable agreement on a standard of
legitimacy, or at least on some basic necessary conditions for
legitimacy, then legitimacy judgments can identify an effective
normative coordination point in the absence of agreement on justice.
There are two weighty reasons not to insist that global governance
institutions must be just if they are to be recognized as having the
right to rule. First, there is sufficient disagreement and uncertainty
about what global justice requires that demanding such a high and
ambiguous standard for legitimacy would frustrate the reasonable goal of
securing coordinated support for valuable institutions on the basis of
moral reasons. Second, even if there were much less disagreement and
uncertainty, withholding support from a valuable institution because it
fails to meet standards of justice would undermine progress toward
justice, which requires effective institutions. The concept of
legitimacy, then, can be seen as an expression of a realistic normative
stance: it reflects both an awareness that some institutions, though
morally flawed, are so beneficial that we need them despite their
imperfections, and a commitment to holding institutions to a higher
standard than their mere benefit relative to the non-institutional
status quo.
In our view, the legitimacy of global governance institutions,
including the Security Council, should be assessed according to what we
call the Complex Standard. (6) We advance the Complex Standard as a
proposal for criteria that individuals and groups can use to determine
whether particular global governance institutions ought to be regarded
as authoritative in their domains of operation. That is, should those to
whom they address their rules and policies work on the presumption that
they should be obeyed, or at most reformed, and that they should not be
interfered with or overthrown? The Complex Standard is not offered as a
discovery of the necessary and sufficient conditions for the legitimacy
of global governance institutions, but rather as a reasonable basis for
a valuable practice. It has three substantive criteria and three
epistemic criteria.
The first substantive criterion is minimal moral acceptability.
Global governance institutions, like other institutions, must not
persist in perpetrating serious injustices that involve violations of
basic human rights. This requirement seems especially appropriate for
the Security Council, since in recent times it has increasingly
portrayed the protection of basic human rights as one of its major
tasks.
The second substantive criterion is institutional integrity. If
there is a gross disparity between an institution's performance and
its self-proclaimed goals or procedures, its legitimacy is seriously
called into question. Similarly, it undermines an institution's
legitimacy if its constitution predictably thwarts the pursuit of the
very goals on which it bases its claims of authority.
The third substantive criterion, comparative benefit, is more
complex, but intuitive nonetheless. Because the chief justification for
having global governance institutions is that they supply important
goods that cannot be achieved without them, failure to supply these
benefits calls the legitimacy of these institutions into question.
Unless they do a reasonably good job of supplying the benefits invoked
to justify their creation, the constraints on sovereignty they impose
and the removal of decision-making to bodies remote from democratic
citizens would be unacceptable. Achieving the comparative benefit
criterion requires providing net benefits exceeding those that would be
possible without the institution in question. However, if an institution
provides only marginally better benefits than would be available in its
absence, and if there is good reason to believe that it should be able
to provide much more substantial benefits but persists in failing to do
so, its legitimacy will be questionable.
This is not to say that an institution loses legitimacy whenever
there is a feasible alternative that could be marginally more efficient
at delivering the benefits in question. Such a criterion for legitimacy
would be too demanding and would foster excessive instability, defeating
the practice's goal of achieving moral reason-based coordinated
support for valuable institutions. Yet if an institution persists in
seriously suboptimal performance, with little prospect for improvement,
and there is a morally acceptable alternative institution that would do
a significantly better job of securing the benefits in question and that
could be created without excessive transition costs, the
institution's legitimacy would be called into question.
The three substantive criteria are best conceived as what John
Rawls calls counting principles: the more of them an institution
satisfies and the higher the degree to which it satisfies them, the
stronger its claim to legitimacy. (7) In addition to the three
substantive criteria, there are three epistemic virtues that are
critical for the legitimacy of global governance institutions.
First, because their chief function is to achieve coordinated
action among states and other actors, institutions ought to generate
reliable information about coordination points and make it available to
relevant actors; otherwise they will not satisfy the criterion of
comparative benefit. Second, a degree of transparency concerning the
institution's operations is necessary in order to achieve
satisfactory terms of accountability. By "terms of
accountability" we mean the specification of who the accountability
holders are and of the standards to which they are to hold the
institution's operations. For the terms of accountability to be
met, the operations of the institution must be reasonably transparent to
the accountability holders and other relevant stakeholders. Third,
institutions must have the capacity to revise their goals and processes
over time as circumstances dictate, and this in turn requires the
capacity to revise the terms of accountability through a process of
principled deliberation.
Because there is considerable disagreement and uncertainty as to
what global justice requires and about the proper division of labor
between international and national institutions for achieving it, there
is continuing controversy about the appropriate terms of accountability
for global governance institutions. Epistemic virtues are therefore of
crucial importance. Institutions should facilitate principled, factually
informed deliberations about these matters and should help ensure that
they utilize input from all who properly have a stake in the outcomes.
ASSESSING THE LEGITIMACY OF SECURITY COUNCIL ACTION
In assessing the performance of the Security Council, we begin with
our three epistemic criteria.
On the criterion of transparency, the Security Council gets low
marks. Its most important negotiations take place in secret. (8) Despite
tall of transparency, the effectiveness of the Council, as essentially a
Great Power club, actually depends on its lack of transparency. It can
therefore be argued that to achieve the objectives of international
peace and security, the Security Council must be non-transparent: that
is, a transparent Security Council would fail on the criterion of
comparative benefit since it would simply become a forum for appealing
to outside audiences rather than reaching Great Power agreement to take
effective action. We do not dispute this argument, but note that
non-transparency can affect the sociological legitimacy of the Security
Council with states other than Great Powers, and with the publics of
democratic Great Powers.
From the standpoint of accountability, the Security Council also
falls short, in two respects. First, the UN Charter provides no checks
on the Security Council: there are no constitutional constraints on what
it can do. Indeed, when the Security Council acts, with the approval of
all Great Powers and sufficient other support, its legal powers are
essentially unlimited, and there is no provision for judicial review of
its decisions by the International Court of Justice or any other
judicial body. (9) Second, there is little in the way of incentives for
responsible use of the veto by the five permanent members. The permanent
members most likely to use the veto against humanitarian intervention
are extremely powerful and not likely to suffer severe political or
economic consequences for using it to thwart such interventions.
The Security Council scores better on our third epistemic
criterion--the capacity of an institution to revise its goals in light
of experience and changing values. The institutional goals of the
Security Council have changed somewhat over time, with the protection of
basic human rights coming to occupy a larger place in the
institution's mission. On the other hand, the permanent member veto
seems firmly entrenched, despite the lack of a compelling moral
justification for it.
We now turn to our three substantive criteria. When taking measures
under its own control, the Security Council has generally met the
minimal moral acceptability requirement. And although there have been
occasional reports of rape and killing by UN forces, forces under UN
command do not seem to exhibit a systematic pattern of serious human
rights violations. They have not, however, always been effective. For
example, as an international commission reported, "poorly armed and
ill-disciplined UN troops were an inadequate response in the face of
atrocities in Sierra Leone." (10) There have recently been much
more serious problems with operations carried out by forces nominally
under state control, working in cooperation with UN peacekeeping forces.
A recent report by Human Rights Watch has documented mass rapes and
murders by Congolese forces supported logistically by the United Nations
Peacekeeping Department. (11)
The Council's record is mixed and ambiguous on the criterion
of institutional integrity. Integrity requires a lack of "egregious
disparity" between the goals of an institution and its actual
practices. (12) Every complex organization engages in some form of
"organized hypocrisy," and the UN is no exception. (13) The
"Oil-for-Food" program, which was marred by corruption, is a
case in point. So weaknesses can be identified on this standard. But
unlike many national-level and local institutions in a variety of
countries, the Security Council does not seem to be consistently
corrupt. On the other hand, the failure to take serious steps toward
stopping the massive killing and other human rights abuses in Bosnia,
Rwanda, Darfur, and Congo, and perhaps somewhat more controversially in
Kosovo, reveals a marked discrepancy between the professed goals and the
behavior of the Security Council.
Finally, assessing how well the Security Council fares according to
the criterion of comparative benefit is probably most difficult because
it requires the assessment of a counterfactual--that is, what would have
been the case in the absence of the Security Council. It should not be
taken for granted, as if it were self-evident, that the use of force
across borders would be more common and more often wrongful if the
Council did not exist. Few informed observers would give the Council
major credit for the reduction in the scale and destructiveness of
warfare in the second, as compared to the first, half of the twentieth
century, since factors other than the existence of the Security Council
(such as the possession by states of nuclear weapons and changing views
of the acceptability of war as a means of national policy) could account
for the improvement. By all accounts, UN peacekeeping operations and
Security Council-authorized interventions have had much more modest
effects. Nevertheless, the most systematic recent studies of
peacekeeping conclude, after careful analysis that takes account of
these inferential difficulties, that the net effects are positive:
"peacekeeping works." (14)
Based on these empirical findings, we believe that the Security
Council provides significant benefits from the standpoint of
international security and the protection against human rights abuses
relative to the status quo ante, the condition in which there was no
supranational institution capable of exercising significant constraint
on the use of force. We conclude that the Security Council sufficiently
realizes the substantive criteria of the Complex Standard to be
considered legitimate (in the normative sense), although its performance
is in many respects highly flawed.
ASSESSING THE LEGITIMACY OF SECURITY COUNCIL INACTION: THE
RESPONSIBILITY TO PROTECT
During the 1990s the Security Council's failure to act
effectively, for years in the former Yugoslavia, and with devastating
consequences in Rwanda, drew much more criticism than its authorization
of peacekeeping actions in troubled societies ranging from Angola and
Mozambique to Guatemala. Responding to this concern, in 2001 the
International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty (ICISS),
initiated by the government of Canada, issued a report, The
Responsibility to Protect, which has resonated in the United Nations
system ever since. (15) As co-chair of the commission, Gareth Evans--the
former foreign minister of Australia--has played an active role in
explaining and promoting the concept of the "responsibility to
protect," and the World Summit of 2005 endorsed the report's
recommendation in the following terms:
The international community, through the United Nations, also has
the responsibility to use appropriate diplomatic, humanitarian, and
other peaceful means, in accordance with Chapters VI and VIII of
the Charter, to help to protect populations from genocide, war
crimes, ethnic cleansing and crimes against humanity. In this
context, we are prepared to take collective action, in a timely and
decisive manner, through the Security Council, in accordance with
the Charter, including Chapter VII, on a case-by-case basis and in
cooperation with relevant regional organizations as appropriate,
should peaceful means be inadequate and national authorities are
manifestly failing to protect their populations from genocide, war
crimes, ethnic cleansing and crimes against humanity. (16)
Building on this resolution, in January 2009 Secretary-General Ban
Ki-moon articulated three "pillars" of the responsibility to
protect: (1) state responsibility; (2) international assistance and
capacity building; and (3) timely and decisive response "when a
State is manifestly failing to provide such protection." (17) The
secretary-general emphasized that all three pillars had to be strong. A
subsequent General Assembly debate in July 2009 revealed some dissent to
the principle, but also an increasing convergence of views among many
countries. There was support for the secretary-general's view that
RtoP was not open for renegotiation, but needed to be implemented; for
his articulation of the three pillars strategy; and for his view that
the scope of RtoP should be narrowly confined to four crimes: genocide,
war crimes, ethnic cleansing, and crimes against humanity. Notably, it
should not extend to inadequate responses to natural disasters or civil
war. The Nicaraguan president of the General Assembly, joined by Cuba,
Venezuela, Sudan, and on some issues other delegations, tried to cast
doubt on the legitimacy of RtoP by linking it to unilateral
intervention, but without much success. In contrast, India, Indonesia,
Japan, Brazil, and South Africa came to its defense.
The secretary-general's report, and the subsequent debate, did
reveal some ambivalence about the role of the Security Council in
implementing the RtoP agenda. The secretary-general urged the five
permanent members "to refrain from employing or threatening to
employ the veto in situations of manifest failure to meet obligations
relating to the responsibility to protect." (18) To our mind, this
statement can be interpreted as an attempt to cast doubt on the
legitimacy of such a veto. In the General Assembly the caution about
RtoP expressed by many developing countries suggested that there would
be little support in that body for more expansive authorization for
humanitarian intervention. As noted above, a radical minority saw RtoP
as a license for unilateral intervention, but there was more general
caution about intervention without the consent of the state involved,
expressed by China, Pakistan, and Sri Lanka. On the other hand,
thirty-five states supported the secretary-general's recommendation
that the five permanent members refrain from employing the veto in
situations covered by RtoP. And, not surprisingly, a number of
delegations expressed (in varying degrees) skepticism about the Security
Council's ability to discharge its responsibilities and declared
the need for General Assembly oversight. (19)
Exclusive Versus Nonexclusive Legitimacy
We have argued that the Security Council is a legitimate
institution and that this implies that its actions are presumptively
legitimate. Nevertheless, as noted, in recent years the Council has been
criticized more severely for inaction than for action. Although no
interventions by the Security Council have led to large-scale human
rights abuses, its inaction in Rwanda in 1994 contributed to a death
toll estimated at between 500,000 and 800,000. (20) The central problem
with the Security Council is, therefore, not what it does, but what it
fails to do. So the most serious questions about Security Council
legitimacy are not those of nonexclusive but of exclusive legitimacy.
An institution has exclusive (normative) legitimacy with regard to
a domain of action if and only if it is legitimate with regard to that
domain and it is impermissible for any other agent to attempt to act in
that domain (without its authorization). Thus, if the Security Council
had exclusive legitimacy with regard to intervention decisions, every
other agent would be under a moral obligation not to make such
decisions. We argue that the Security Council does not have exclusive
legitimacy. It would be permissible, we argue--and in fact would be
highly desirable--to develop a superior (on the basis of the Complex
Standard) institution for the making of intervention decisions when the
Security Council fails to make them.
The core of our argument that the Security Council does not possess
exclusive legitimacy can be outlined as follows, in the form of four
premises and a conclusion.
Premise One: The Security Council has sometimes failed to authorize
justified humanitarian interventions against genocide, war crimes,
crimes against humanity, and ethnic cleansing; and there is no evidence
that this disposition toward inaction has been rectified. By claiming
exclusive authority, the Security Council not only fails to discharge
its avowed function of protecting basic human rights but also poses a
serious obstacle to states fulfilling the responsibility to protect.
Furthermore, there is no prospect of the Security Council reliably
protecting weak democratic governments from violent overthrow.
Premise Two: Because it lacks systematic procedures for
accountability and is recalcitrant to reform the permanent member veto,
the Security Council has little prospect for substantial improvement. If
the permanent members were to accept the secretary-general's advice
not to use the veto in situations covered by RtoP--and were somehow to
institutionalize this promise--this premise could be rendered invalid;
but such self-abnegation is highly unlikely.
Premise Three: If an institution repeatedly fails to discharge one
of its primary justifying functions (in this case, the protection of
basic human rights), acts as an obstacle to other parties fulfilling
that function, and has little prospect for substantial improvement in
these regards, then it is permissible to try to develop a superior
alternative, if there is a reasonable probability that the alternative
can be successfully created and sustained and the risk that the attempt
to create the alternative will have negative unintended consequences is
acceptably low.
Premise Four: There is a reasonable probability that at least one
alternative institution for making humanitarian intervention decisions
and decisions concerning the restoration of legitimate government that
would be superior to the Security Council could be created and
sustained, and the risk that the attempt will have bad unintended
consequences is acceptably low.
Conclusion: Therefore, the Security Council does not possess
exclusive legitimacy with regard to humanitarian intervention decisions,
and it is permissible to try to develop a superior institutional
alternative.
The first three of these premises enjoy considerable intuitive
plausibility, given our analysis of legitimacy and our account of the
distinctive function and practical value of legitimacy assessment.
Premise Four, however, requires more support, since we have not
discussed alternative institutions. Therefore, we will next explore two
candidates for alternative institutions that could perhaps be superior,
on the basis of the Complex Standard, to the status quo: a democratic
coalition and a precommitment regime.
ALTERNATIVES TO THE SECURITY COUNCIL
A Democratic Coalition
The first alternative that we consider is a coalition of democratic
states. "Democratic" here means liberal constitutional
democracies: states with constitutions that embed majoritarian voting
processes in a system of entrenched civil and political rights and that
have an independent judiciary. In addition, such states have strong
civil societies, with a variety of organizations, institutions, and
practices that provide sources of information that are relatively
independent of the state, that help create a political culture that is
willing to question the state's policies, and that exert
significant influence on state action. One prominent example of the idea
of a democratic coalition is the proposal for a "concert of
democracies" advanced by John Ikenberry and others. (21)
The key idea of this proposal is that democratic states are
relatively reliable decision-makers when it comes to decisions
concerning humanitarian intervention. Their relative reliability has two
main sources. First, if the coalition's membership is restricted to
well-established liberal constitutional democracies, the shared
commitment to human rights and to democratic government will be
relatively strong--entrenched in political cultures and empowered by
constitutional orders. Second, liberal democracies are epistemically
superior in ways that are relevant to making good decisions. They
feature free media, traditions of organized political activism, access
to accurate information, and powerful channels of accountability that
constrain state action.
The most plausible proposals for a democratic coalition to
authorize intervention share three features. (22) First, the coalition
could begin its formal deliberations only after a failure by the
Security Council to authorize an intervention and could act only after
advising the Security Council that it is about to do so, in order to
give that body a chance to reconsider its own inaction. Second, the
coalition's deliberations would be guided by a relatively
uncontroversial set of substantive criteria for intervention that set a
high threshold for what counts as a socially created humanitarian
emergency--namely, massive violation of the most basic human rights,
genocide being the clearest example. Third, the democratic coalition
would include provisions for ex ante and ex post accountability. Ex ante
accountability requires that all of the issues and options (including
nonmilitary options) be discussed, and that states that question the
necessity of the intervention have the opportunity to interrogate those
who support it. Provisions for ex post accountability are also
necessary. The intervenors must publicly commit in advance to allowing
an independent body to have free access to the state into which the
intervention is to occur and to facilitate the generation and
publicizing of the best available information about (1) the actual
effects of the intervention and (2) whether the pre-intervention
assessment of the humanitarian emergency on the basis of which the case
for intervention was made was credible. The independent body's ex
post evaluation of the intervention would focus on whether the behavior
of intervening states was consistent with the statements they made in
the ex ante accountability process.
There are two quite different types of objections to the democratic
coalition proposal. The first is that its combination of membership
criteria and substantive criteria is not adequate to ensure responsible
decisions. Although it is true that well-established democratic states
have a stronger commitment to human rights and democracy than other
states, this commitment is not a guarantee against flawed
decision-making in the case of humanitarian interventions. For example,
the democratic states willing to participate in an intervention
coalition may use such an opportunity to pursue their own geopolitical
interests under the guise of humanitarian concern, either in a
calculated fashion or through self-deceiving rationalizations. Also, the
channels of accountability provided by democratic political processes
are designed to make leaders accountable to their own fellow citizens,
not to foreigners. This implies a risk that when democratic states
deliberate about intervention, they may seriously underestimate or
unduly discount the costs of an intervention to the intended
beneficiaries or other "outsiders." Taken together, these
objections imply that a democratic coalition may lack adequate
provisions for responsible decision-making: the combination of
membership criteria and substantive criteria is insufficient, so
additional provisions for accountability are needed. The inclusion of ex
ante and ex post accountability provisions to simple democratic
coalition proposals is designed to address this first type of objection.
The second type of objection is from the standpoint of sociological
legitimacy, and it remains even if ex ante and ex post accountability
provisions are included. Unless the criteria for membership are so
undemanding as to undercut the claim that democracies are relatively
reliable decision-makers, many states, including some powerful ones,
such as China and Russia, will be excluded from participating.
Nondemocratic states tend to be especially adamant about the
inviolability of sovereignty, and may regard a democratic coalition as a
military alliance against them. Specifically, Russia and China are
likely to find the idea of such a coalition especially repugnant,
because it repudiates the exclusive legitimacy of the Security Council,
in which they both hold veto power. Indeed, the Chinese reaction to the
idea of a democratic intervention coalition has been extremely negative.
(23) A new institution for intervention that is greeted with hostility
by two or more major powers as well as by a number of less powerful
nondemocratic states would be lacking in sociological legitimacy. The
proposal for a "concert of democracies" by Ikenberry and
others is perhaps especially unlikely to enjoy broad sociological
legitimacy because of a provision of its draft enabling treaty, whereby
members of the coalition are obligated not to use force against each
other. Thus, the proposal for democracies to use force against states
controlled by nondemocratic governments at the same time exempts the
intervenors from possible intervention. (24)
The lack of sociological legitimacy is a serious matter for three
reasons. First, it may hamper the effectiveness of the coalition. States
that regard the coalition as illegitimate will not cooperate (by not
granting rights to traverse airspace, and so forth), and may exert
pressure on their allies and clients to refrain from cooperating as
well. Second, there is the risk of an adverse defensive reaction: the
perceived threat of a democratic coalition could strengthen militant
nationalism in powerful nondemocratic countries, and might even lead to
the forging of new alliances among them. Third, the institutionalization
of a democratic coalition could inhibit cooperation between democratic
and autocratic states on important issues other than humanitarian
intervention--such as global economic stability, orderly international
trade, and effective actions to limit climate change. The protection of
human rights through intervention is an important objective for policy,
but does not necessarily trump effective cooperation on other issues
that affect billions of people and, indeed, prospects for a healthy
atmosphere for human life. In brief, where sociological legitimacy is
lacking, institutionalizing a democratic coalition could have bad
consequences. On balance, the expected gain in the quality of decisions
relative to the Security Council does not seem great enough to justify
the risk that the lack of sociological legitimacy will undercut the
effectiveness of the coalition, provoke an unacceptable backlash, and
disrupt cooperation on other important issues.
A Precommitment Regime for Democracy-protecting Intervention
A precommitment regime is designed to achieve greater sociological
legitimacy than the democratic coalition proposal by explicitly
respecting state sovereignty while facilitating intervention when
necessary to protect democracy against violent overthrow. It is not
designed in the least to expand democracy to societies that have not
experienced it--certainly not by force--but only to help maintain it
where the people of a country have already managed to institute it
themselves. It is our hope that this respect for democratic sovereignty
would enable such a regime to go beyond the present RtoP mandate to
respond to sustained and widespread violence against civilians, as in
cases of genocide or ethnic cleansing, to achieve a further desirable
objective: helping to protect nascent democracies against violent
overthrow.
Under a precommitment regime for democracy protection, a set of
democratic states could enter into a contract by which a democratic
government would authorize intervention in its own territory in response
to violence that the government was unable to control, either due to
incapacity or to having been dislodged from power by force.
Conceptually, we think of this contract as between the guarantor states,
on the one hand, and the people, or demos, of the vulnerable state, on
the other. The existing democratic government would be regarded as the
agent of the demos. (25) Some would argue that in existing international
law states cannot consent to the use of armed force against themselves;
but the fact that this contract is with the demos gets around that
objection: armed force would not be used against the demos but only
against a regime that had violated democratic processes and disempowered
the public.
If the Security Council failed to authorize an intervention in
response to a grave humanitarian crisis involving massive violations of
human rights, as a result of a loss of effective control by the elected
government, its partners in the precommitment regime could intervene. If
the contract so provided, a precommitment regime could also be designed
for less extreme situations: for example, when the elected government is
violently overthrown in a military coup, or when a violent revolution
(with the violence not forced on the revolutionaries by state
repression) takes place, with or without aid from abroad. But
precommitment regimes could not be activated in the absence of violent
actions or threats. Claims of "creeping authoritarianism" on
the part of an elected government could not trigger intervention, since
in such circumstances the criteria for judgment on whether such actions
should be regarded as antidemocratic or as an implementation of
democracy are too unclear.
It is important to emphasize that pre-authorization for
intervention would be available only to democratically elected
governments that at the time of the precommitment contract held power
through means consistent with democratic legality. Authorization for
intervention would not be extended to situations in which a popular
movement had arisen to contest state power. The reason for these
conditions is to ensure that a precommitment regime did not become a
means for autocratic regimes to maintain themselves in power in spite of
popular opposition. We are not proposing a return to Count
Metternich's version of the Concert of Europe.
Furthermore, precommitment contracts would have to include
provisions to strengthen the capacity of those democratic states that
are to be protected to maintain order within their territories. Such
provisions would be in the interest of the potential intervenors by
reducing the likelihood that they would have to act, as well as in the
interests of the governments arranging to be protected. Such provisions
would also be sovereignty-reinforcing, and therefore consistent with the
emphasis that we observed in the RtoP debates on maintaining state
sovereignty and building state capacity.
Since we are not international legal specialists, we can only
sketch the legal arrangements we envisage, hoping that if international
lawyers find these ideas worthwhile, they could devise appropriate
modalities. As we envision, precommitment contracts would be reported to
the Security Council under Article 51 of the UN Charter and registered
with the Secretariat of the United Nations under Article 102. Each
precommitment regime would have a provision for designating which of its
guarantor members would undertake the intervention, should the
triggering conditions be fulfilled. And any valid precommitment contract
would have to incorporate ex ante and ex post accountability mechanisms,
as sketched above. Such precommitment regimes could be justified as
easily as defensive alliances, such as NATO. Article 51 of the Charter
says that "nothing in the present Charter shall impair the inherent
right of individual or collective self-defense if an armed attack occurs
against a Member of the United Nations, until the Security Council has
taken measures necessary to maintain international peace and
security."
Any contract would also have to include provisions for revoking the
authorization. Precommitment contracts should be revocable at will by
legitimate governments, since any other provision would be likely to be
seen by most states as inconsistent with an appropriate understanding of
sovereignty. However, if a precommitment regime had specified as a
triggering condition the violent overthrow of the democratically elected
government, then clearly an attempt to revoke the authorization for
intervention by those who had unlawfully seized control could not be
regarded as legitimate.
The Security Council could invalidate the precommitment agreement
through a procedural vote, requiring nine of the fifteen Council
members, with the veto not applying (Article 27.2). This provision is
designed to ensure that precommitment agreements regarded by the
Security Council as inconsistent with international peace and security
would not be valid. An agreement could be invalidated if in the judgment
of the Security Council the incumbent government did not permit fair
contestation for public office through free and fair elections, or if it
systematically repressed the ability of those outside the government to
speak, write, and organize politically. The Security Council could, in
making these judgments, rely on impartial measures of democracy, such as
those used by scholars. (26) The Security Council could take such action
at any time, taking into account the possibility that signatory
governments, even if democratic when the original contract was
concluded, could become nondemocratic over time.
There are at least four situations in which a state might find a
precommitment regime an attractive option: (1) a new democracy that had
not gained control of its own military could select a precommitment
regime as a way of deterring a military coup and, if unsuccessful at
deterrence, responding to it; (2) a state that had just made the
transition from authoritarian rule to democracy could opt for the
precommitment contract as an insurance policy against authoritarian
counterrevolutionaries forcing it back into its previous condition; (27)
(3) a state that has either recently emerged from a period of violent
ethnic conflict or has good reason to believe that it is likely to
suffer this great harm could engage in measures designed to prevent it
by signing the precommitment contract; (4) any state whose leaders
thought that it was likely to be a target of uninvited intervention in
the future could, by signing the precommitment contract, at least
control who the intervenors would be. This latter measure might be
critical in a situation in which there was reason to fear that a
neighboring state might be poised to invade one's country (to
secure resources or annex part of its territory, perhaps) under the
pretext of a humanitarian intervention or an intervention to restore
democracy. In the 1990s, for example, interventions in West Africa by
the Economic Community of West African States (ECOWAS) in Sierra Leone
and Liberia were both ineffective in dealing with resource-fueled civil
wars, and provided the opportunity for pillage by some ECOWAS units.
(28) The civil war in Rwanda spilled over into the Congo in 1994, and by
1998 several African countries had intervened, resulting in massive
human rights abuses. (29)
In certain situations, the incentives for opting for precommitment
could be increased by the actions of other states. For example, in cases
of new states emerging through secession from or dissolution of existing
states, where the risk of humanitarian crises or authoritarian takeovers
was high, other states could make the signing of a precommitment
contract a condition of recognition of the new state or of its
membership in valuable trade regimes or military alliances.
A precommitment regime would not require prior authorization of the
Security Council and would therefore sidestep the veto. But by providing
that the Council could invalidate agreements, this institutional
innovation--unlike a democratic coalition--would not directly challenge
the authority of the Council. Furthermore, it would be consistent with a
strong interpretation of the notion of sovereignty, because it would not
authorize intervention without prior state consent. To put the same
point differently, whereas the democratic coalition is in direct
competition with the Security Council in cases in which the Council
fails to authorize an intervention, the precommitment regime would
operate in a complementary way, without repudiating the Security
Council's decisions. Note that the Security Council could always
preempt action by the precommitment regime if it decided to take action
itself.
Scuh a precommitment regime does carry the potential danger that it
would become an oppressive alliance, enabling a protected state more
readily to repress domestic opposition or to threaten its neighbors.
Domestic repression would contradict the democracy-enhancing purpose of
a precommitment regime, and threats to neighbors could generate
protective reactions leading to a spiral of conflict. Precommitment
contracts would therefore remain valid only as long as their
beneficiaries continued to adhere to democratic standards, including an
absence of systematic bias against any internal ethnic group; and as
long as they maintained nonaggressive and nonexpansionary foreign
policies, firmly eschewing alliances that could be threatening to their
neighbors. Great care would have to be taken that pre-authorization
arrangements, within the spheres of military capacity of major states,
were clearly not threatening to those states, since such measures would
be a recipe for multilateral warfare rather than peacekeeping or
peacemaking. The provision that the Security Council could void a
dangerous contract is designed to mitigate the risk that states
protected by precommitment contracts could become internally repressive
or externally aggressive. (30)
We do not propose a precommitment regime as a panacea, since the
creation of this institutional option would not necessarily change state
behavior. Established democracies with the capacity to intervene on
behalf of threatened democracies are not always inclined to do so.
Indeed, there could be a problem of time inconsistency: even states that
had taken on the role of guarantor under a precommitment arrangement
might renege when the time came to fulfill their commitments. Shifts in
international alignments or domestic opinion could undermine even
genuine intentions to become engaged. (31) In response, we do not argue
that legal obligation automatically transfers into political action. But
a precommitment regime would remove one constraint, by providing a
clearly institutionalized path for pro-democratic intervention without
formal action by the Security Council. Furthermore, having joined a
precommitment regime as a guarantor, a state would have some
reputational stake in fulfilling its commitment. This consideration
would not necessarily be decisive, but it would generate an additional
reason to act. In view of the time inconsistency problem, however, it
would be important for the criteria for intervention to be very clear,
so that reputational costs of reneging would be higher and so that
democratic leaders in vulnerable states would not place confidence in
arrangements that turned out to be ephemeral. Indeed, one of the
advantages of a precommitment regime would be to enhance clarity about
whether, and under what conditions, democratic regimes could expect
external protection against threats of force against them.
On the side of vulnerable countries, there could also be
reservations: governments could be reluctant to signal weakness, or seem
to reduce their own sovereignty, by entering into precommitment
contracts. Yet if faced with real dangers from potential coups, they
would have the incentive to seek some guarantees, however uncertain, of
protection. Reluctance on the part of vulnerable countries (as well as
other countries) could be reduced, furthermore, by placing part of a
package of capacity-building measures under the responsibility to
protect. (32) The package as a whole would provide opportunities for
states to fulfill their responsibility to protect in a rule-governed,
responsible manner, taking sovereign consent very seriously, without
being hamstrung by the veto.
At present, precommitment regimes are likely to be most valuable in
Africa, a region far from the borders of any permanent member of the
Security Council, and in which democracy is fragile. Between 1960 and
2005 there were sixty-seven constitutional changes of leadership in
Africa, of which 21-31 percent were followed within four years by
attempted military coups. Furthermore, the proportion of constitutional
changes of leadership that are followed by military coups seems to be
fairly steady over time. (33) This reality suggests that there is a
major problem to which an international solution could be appropriate.
To some extent, coups have been inhibited by continuing ties with the
prior colonial powers; but a precommitment regime would regularize and
institutionalize such inhibitions, increasing accountability for such
protective actions through publicity and through the operation of the
Security Council.
In general, the incrementalist option of precommitment regimes is
likely to enjoy more sociological legitimacy than the status quo because
it makes it possible to fulfill better the responsibility to protect. It
is more a supplement than an alternative to existing arrangements for
joint military action. In addition, the precommitment proposal should be
less threatening to nondemocratic states, such as Russia and China,
because, unlike the democratic coalition proposal, it does not provide a
special exemption for democratic states to act contrary to existing UN
Charter-based international law. The execution of precommitment
contracts, as we have argued, is permissible under existing law.
The Risk of Unintended Consequences
Those who assume that the Security Council is not only legitimate
but also has exclusive legitimacy regarding humanitarian intervention
typically claim that any attempt to create an alternative institution
for these decisions would be too risky. Three different risks need to be
distinguished: (1) the risk that the new institution would make bad
decisions concerning intervention; (2) the risk that the existence of
the new institution would erode the sociological legitimacy of the
Security Council; and (3) the risk of other unintended consequences,
such as undermining efforts to institutionalize RtoP. Although one can
never provide guarantees against human error and self-interest, the
specifications that beneficiary governments must be democratic, and that
the Security Council can void such agreements, are designed to reduce
the first sort of risk. Compared to a veto-ridden Security Council,
unjustifiable inaction would be less likely.
With respect to the second issue, we have already noted that
because of provisions for Security Council preemption, arrangements for
precommitment regimes would not be likely to erode the Council's
perceived legitimacy. Indeed, they might reduce justifiable criticism of
the Council that results from its frequent inaction in the face of
humanitarian crises and the internal use of force. Finally, the risk
that a precommitment regime would generate other bad consequences is
potentially the most serious; and in comparing the proposal for a
democratic coalition with that of a precommitment regime, we have tried
to take this into account by specifying limiting conditions--in
particular, that the regime being protected must be democratic to
prevent the bad consequence of keeping authoritarian regimes in power,
and that the Security Council can void precommitment regimes by a
procedural majority of nine states. By contrast, the much more
open-ended proposal for a democratic coalition could provoke a serious
backlash from a coalition of post-imperialist countries and autocracies
that would wave the "anti-imperialist" banner to defeat its
efforts.
Nonetheless, we acknowledge that our preferred alternative might
have deleterious consequences that we have not anticipated. We hope, by
offering this paper, to elicit criticisms and suggestions to improve the
formulation presented here.
NOTES
(1) Alien Buchanan and Robert O. Keohane, "The Legitimacy of
Global Governance Institutions," Ethics & International Affairs
20, no. 4 (2006), pp. 405-38.
(2) International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty
(hereafter ICISS), The Responsibility to Protect (Ottawa: International
Development Research Center, 200l).
(3) This claim that legitimate institutions are generally
authoritative--that is, that those to whom they direct their rules have
content-independent reasons to comply with all of their rules or
policies--requires qualification. For it can be argued that if an
institution issued a policy that directly and unambiguously was at odds
with the very functions that are used to justify its existence or that
clearly violated the most basic human rights, then there would not even
be a prima facie duty to comply. In other words, in such extreme cases
the content of a policy could undercut authoritativeness. For example,
if we suppose that the European Court of Human Rights satisfies all
reasonable criteria for being a legitimate institution, and if we
further suppose that it has issued a ruling declaring that EU states may
deprive their Roma citizens of all civil and political rights, there
would be no content-independent reason for anyone to comply with this
ruling. It would be a mistake to say that in this case there was a
content-independent reason to comply but that it was outweighed by
considerations of content. Instead, the content of the policy is so
unacceptable that it negates any content-independent reasons for
complying. We rely here in part on an unpublished paper by Bas Van der
Vossen on legitimacy.
(4) This analysis of normative legitimacy as the right to rule is
elaborated and defended in Buchanan and Keohane, "Legitimacy."
(5) Independent International Commission on Kosovo, The Kosovo
Report (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000).
(6) Buchanan and Keohane, "Legitimacy."
(7) John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1971).
(8) For a recent comprehensive review of Security Council action on
issues of war and peace, see Vaughan Lowe et al., The United Nations
Security Council and War: The Evolution of Thought and Practice Since
1945 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008). In almost all important
situations, the most critical negotiations took place privately rather
than publicly.
(9) We are not suggesting that such a provision would be a good
idea, since the International Court of Justice (ICJ) is too weakly
institutionalized to take on such a burden; if it had this authority, it
would surely become even more politicized than it is, and there is
little reason to believe that the ICJ would dare to overrule a united
Security Council or that such an adverse ICJ decision would be heeded by
the Great Powers.
(10) ICISS, The Responsibility to Protect: Research, Bibliography,
Background (Ottawa: International Development Research Center, 2001), p.
109.
(11) See Human Rights Watch, "Eastern DR Congo: Surge in Army
Atrocities," November 2, 2009; available at
www.hrw.org/en/news/2009/11/02/eastern-dr-congo-surge-army-atrocities.
See also Jeffrey Gettleman, "U.N. Told Not to Join Congo Army in
Operation," New York Times, December 10, 2009. The moral status of
Security Council inaction is more questionable, as we will see, than
that of Security Council action.
(12) Buchanan and Keohane, "Legitimacy," p. 422.
(13) Stephen D. Krasner, Sovereignty: Organized Hypocrisy
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999).
(14) Virginia Page Fortna, Does Peacekeeping Work? Shaping
Belligerents' Choices after Civil War (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 2008); and Michael W. Doyle and Nicholas Sambanis,
Making War and Building Peace (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
2006). Both of these studies are impressive pieces of scholarship. It is
important to note, however, that efficacy at peacekeeping does not imply
overall effectiveness, particularly if an institution often fails to act
when human rights are at stake.
(15) ICISS, The Responsibility to Protect, n3.
(16) UN General Assembly, Sixtieth Session, "2005 World Summit
Outcome," A/RES/60/1, October 24, 2005, para. 139.
(17) UN General Assembly, Sixty-third Session, "Implementing
the Responsibility to Protect: Report of the Secretary-General,"
A/63/677, January 12, 2009, p. 9.
(18) Ibid., para. 61.
(19) We rely here on two valuable reports on the General Assembly
debate: Global Centre for the Responsibility to Protect,
"Implementing the Responsibility to Protect--The 2009 General
Assembly Debate: An Assessment" (August 2009); and International
Coalition for the Responsibility to Protect, "Report on the General
Assembly Plenary Debate on the Responsibility to Protect"
(September 15, 2009).
(20) For a gripping account by an academic who was at the United
Nations during these crucial times, see Michael Barnett, Eyewitness to a
Genocide: The United Nations and Rwanda (Ithaca: Cornell University
Press, 2002).
(21) G. John Ikenberry, Anne-Marie Slaughter, et al., "Forging
a World of Liberty Under Law: U.S. National Security in the 21st
Century," Final Report of the Princeton Project on National
Security (Princeton: Woodrow Wilson School of Public and International
Affairs, September 27, 2006).
(22) In our view the proposal for a concert of democracies by
Ikenberry et al. does not include sufficient provisions for
accountability. The provisions outlined here are drawn from Allen
Buchanan and Robert O. Keohane, "The Preventive Use of Force: A
Cosmopolitan Institutional Proposal," Ethics & International
Affairs 18, no. 1 (2004), pp. 1-22.
(23) One of the authors was present in Shanghai and Beijing in
January 2007, when the Princeton Project report was discussed in
meetings involving American and Chinese participants. The Chinese
participants were vociferous and sustained in their criticisms of the
idea of a democratic coalition that could authorize intervention. It was
clear that they viewed this proposal as entirely unacceptable.
(24) Ikenberry et al., "Forging a World of Liberty Under
Law," Appendix A, note 7.
(25) We thank an anonymous referee for raising the question of with
whom the contract should be made.
(26) The most common such measure is the Polity IV measure. See
"Polity IV Project: Political Regime Characteristics and
Transitions, 18o0-2009"; available at
www.systemicpeace.org/polity/polity4.htm.
(27) Andrew Moravcsik has made a similar argument about human
rights regimes: that "governments delegate self-interestedly to
combat future threats to domestic democratic governance." See
Andrew Moravcsik, "The Origins of Human Rights Regimes: Democratic
Delegation in Postwar Europe," International Organization 54, no. 2
(Spring 2000), pp. 217-53. The quote is from the abstract, which appears
in the unpaginated front material of the journal.
(28) See Adekeye Adebajo, Building Peace in West Africa: Liberia,
Sierra Leone, and Guinea-Bissau (Boulder, Colo.: Lynne Rienner
Publishers, 2002).
(29) Joe Bavier, "Congo War-Driven Crisis Kills 45,000 a
Month: Study," Reuters, January 22, 2008; available at
www.reuters.com/article/idUSL2280201220080122 (accessed July 7, 2010).
(30) See Inis L. Claude, Power and International Relations (New
York: Random House, 1962), esp. chap. 5, "A Critique of Collective
Security."
(31) We are grateful to three anonymous referees for emphasizing
this point in their comments on a draft of this paper.
(32) We are indebted to Laurence Helfer of Duke Law School for this
suggestion.
(33) Kristen A. Harkness, "Dangers to Democratization:
Military Responses to Constitutional Changes of Leadership in
Africa" (paper presented at the Midwest Political Science
Association conference, Chicago, April 2010), esp. Table 2, p. 12.
doi: 10.1017/So892679410000018
Allen Buchanan and Robert O. Keohane *
* We are grateful for comments on earlier versions of this paper by
Charles Beitz, Curtis Bradley, Michael Doyle, Laurence Heifer, Andrew
Hurrell, Richard Steinberg, and Laura Valentini, and to three anonymous
referees. Edward Luck was especially helpful at an early stage in the
development of our ideas.