Supply, demand & kidney transplants.
Satel, Sally
IN MAY 2002, Clois Guthrie, an 85-year-old retired osteopathic surgeon, got the phone call he was waiting for: A suitable kidney had
just become available for him. A renal transplant would mean liberation
from the dialysis machine to which he had been tethered for two
miserable years. Elated, Guthrie and his wife raced to the Porter
Adventist Medical Center from their home in North Denver one hundred
miles away. (1) Yet mere hours before the operation was to take place,
the center's transplant surgeons were engaged in anguished
deliberation over whether Guthrie was actually the right person to get
that kidney. He was, after all, 85 years old. How much longer would he
live with a new kidney? Shouldn't the organ, taken from a healthy
30-year-old motorcyclist who had died from head trauma, be given to a
younger person who would get many more years of life from it?
The doctors decided to proceed, but in the end, there was a
technical glitch and the operation did not take place. Guthrie went back
on dialysis. Two-and-a-half years later he was dead of a heart attack at
age 88. The ethical dilemma sparked by his case, however, did not die
with him. Indeed, the question of "how old is too old for a
transplant?" is being asked with increasing urgency by transplant
professionals as the chasm between supply and demand widens inexorably.
Uneasy questions of allocation arise in environments of scarcity.
Who will get to stay on the crowded lifeboat and who will be tossed
overboard? This age-old tension between utility to society--the maximum
good for the maximum number--and fairness to the individual is
notoriously hard to resolve. In the case of the shortage of
transplantable kidneys, it is made gratuitously more difficult by a
"transplant community" that resists experimenting with bold
ideas to increase the supply.
Dire shortage, modest remedies
ORGAN TRANSPLANTATION IS one of the crowning achievements of
medical science. Yet from 1954--the year of the first renal
transplant--to the present, there have never been enough organs to meet
demand. The dearth includes all transplantable organs--hearts, livers,
lungs, pancreases--but because dialysis can keep patients with renal
failure alive, the shortage of kidneys is most acute in terms of volume.
Indeed, over three-quarters of the national wait-list population
comprises those waiting for a kidney.
In January 2007, roughly 70,000 people were waiting for a kidney,
according to the United Network for Organ Sharing (UNOS), which
maintains the national registry of transplant candidates under monopoly
contract with the Department of Health and Human Services. In big
cities, where the ratio of needy patients to available organs is
highest, the wait for a kidney ranges from five to eight years. This
time is spent undergoing dialysis, a procedure that circulates the
patient's blood through a machine (once called an "artificial
kidney") that purifies it, siphons off accumulated water, and
returns it to the body. Patients typically visit a dialysis center for
treatment three times a week, for four hours each time. Many patients
are deeply ambivalent about dialysis. They acknowledge its
life-preserving role yet resent it as a vast intrusion into daily life
that is often uncomfortable and debilitating.
Commitment to dialysis ends when a patient receives a transplant or
dies. In 2006, only 17,804 people--or about one-quarter of the
population waiting at the beginning of the year--received kidneys.
Meanwhile, over 3,813 died waiting and 1,190 became too sick to
transplant. It is a grim picture that is guaranteed to worsen. By 2010,
the median waiting time is projected to be at least ten years long,
extending well beyond the length of time that most adults, especially
those over 65, are able to survive on dialysis.
Despite decades of public education about the virtues of donating
organs at death, the supply of cadaver organs has remained
disappointingly steady over the years. Half of all Americans have
designated themselves as donors on their driver's licenses or on
state-run donor registries, yet if family members are unaware of a loved
one's preference, they are just as likely as not to grant
permission for the organs to be taken. This is understandable
considering that the request generally comes at the worst possible time.
Not only is their relative dead, but he may well have met a sudden and
violent end. It is just this kind of victim--a young, healthy individual
with severe head trauma (think helmetless motorcycle accident)--who is
the optimal deceased donor.
In response to the crying demand, transplant centers have been
rethinking the definition of a transplantable organ. Consequently,
kidneys from so-called expanded-criteria donors have become an important
new source. These are deceased donors, over 60 years of age, or those
between 50 and 59 years who had hypertension in life or died of a
stroke. The retrieval of organs from moribund patients who may never
meet the criteria for brain death is also being advanced. Such potential
donors are called "non-heart-beating" because they died of
cardiac arrest. Finally, there is an effort to boost the numbers of
transplants using kidneys from living donors through so-called kidney
exchanges. In such an arrangement, two or more prospective
donor-recipient couples who are incompatible with each other match with
a member of the other pair.
Zero-sum game
MUCH AS THESE procurement innovations are welcome, they are likely
to make only a modest contribution to supply. (2) The burden on
transplant bureaucrats at UNOS, then, is how to allocate the limited
reserve of cadaver kidneys in order to make optimal use of them. It is a
problem UNOS has been working on for some time, and last winter the
agency sponsored its Public Forum to Discuss Kidney Allocation Policy to
unveil its new proposal. Central to the new allocation model was the
concept of "Life Years from Transplant"--that is, how much
longer a patient would likely survive after a transplant compared to how
long he would live if he continued on dialysis instead.
The agency was seeking to maximize the number of additional years
lived. In comparison with the first come, first served rule that
currently guides kidney allocation, a scheme that prioritizes on the
basis of life-years gained is more utilitarian. Starkly put, it views a
healthy organ as wasted if it outlives its recipient--and the goal of
optimizing longevity is to avoid a Clois Guthrie situation, in which a
young kidney, able to prolong by decades the life of a 40-year-old,
instead goes to an 85-year-old who dies a few years later, taking the
organ with him.
In addition to penalizing older candidates, justifiable though this
may be, the new UNOS proposal also disfavors candidates who have waited
the longest. Indeed, it is the very fact of having waited years that
weakens a candidate's prospect for receiving a kidney. This is
because the more time he spends on dialysis, the more medical
deterioration he suffers and, as a result, the fewer years of added life
a new kidney will confer.
Proponents of the new UNOS scheme denied that a rigid age cut-off
would be applied. Yet they acknowledged that older candidates, as a
class, would indeed be disadvantaged. This was a flash-point. A number
of physicians and transplant recipients took the microphone during the
comment period to object. A few predicted the American Association of
Retired Persons would lobby strongly against the proposal, as the new
plan appeared to "discriminate" against older people. Others
speculated that the thriving international black market in kidneys would
get a further boost from well-to-do elderly who would become
"transplant tourists"--the term used to describe patients who
go overseas to purchase a transplant on the black market.
One transplant recipient in the audience expressed worry that
patients who had logged years on the list already would become
demoralized if waiting time became a minor factor in assignment.
"It will destroy hope," she said; knowing you will get a
kidney "is what keeps you going." Another recipient wondered:
"Who's to say an older person's five years of life are
any less important than a younger person's nine years?...
That's playing God and people aren't going to like it."
(3)
That is not playing God; that is playing man--the all-too-human
affair of people deliberating strenuously and in good faith to determine
what is right. The UNOS meeting dramatized the timeless "tragic
choice" dilemma. The phrase comes from a classic 1978 book called
Tragic Choices (W.W. Norton & Co.) by esteemed legal theorists Guido
Calabresi and Philip Bobbitt. The authors delineate the conflicts
society faces when it is compelled to distribute limited resources. Most
wrenching for citizens and policymakers are choices among fundamental
values. A transplant surgeon who cares for patients in a milieu of
scarcity is no less a healer. He still wants his patients--young and
old--to receive kidneys. Without question, a transplant will afford them
a better quality and quantity of life--irrespective of age--not only in
terms of liberation from dialysis but because they will be spared its
cardiovascular complications. Yet, on the other hand, the surgeon is
torn between his duty to the patient before him and the utilitarian
imperative of enhancing survival benefit across the population of
patients needing transplants.
It is the eternal tradeoff that comes with medical rationing:
individual versus societal benefit. Who will be saved? This question
recalls the classic quandary of lifeboat ethics that famously confronted
the physicians who developed chronic dialysis in the early 1960s.
Rationing and its discontents
EFFECTIVE DIALYSIS BEGAN during World War 11, but the technology
could be used only in patients with temporary damage to their kidneys.
Ongoing dialysis was not possible because of the difficulty of
maintaining a connection between patients' veins and arteries and
the artificial kidney, as the dialysis machine was once called. Glass
tubing was used as the conduit for blood as it flowed into and out of
the machine, but it would get blocked with clots from the vessel in
which it was embedded. Doctors rotated the tubes after each dialysis
session, but within a few weeks all viable vasculature would clot off.
Unless the patient's renal failure reversed before then, he would
die.
A breakthrough came on March 9, 1960, when a nephrologist at the
University of Washington experimented with tubes made of a relatively
new substance called Teflon. The non-stick surface of the Teflon allowed
the tubes to remain in the patient's arm for months without
clotting. "Suddenly, we took something that was 100 percent fatal
and overnight turned it into 90 percent survival," said Dr. Belding
Scribner, who pioneered the technique. And just as suddenly, the
University of Washington Hospital was inundated with referrals for
dialysis from physicians and patients across the country. Scribner
secured private funding to underwrite an experimental dialysis program,
the Seattle Artificial Kidney Center. It opened in January 1962 with a
total of three treatment slots. But who among the dying should get them?
Scribner argued that the job of choosing among medically eligible
candidates ought to be shared by society.
Thus, a lay committee, known as the Admissions and Policy Committee
of the Seattle Artificial Kidney Center at Swedish Hospital, was formed
to decide nothing less than who would be allowed to live. The committee
comprised seven volunteers--a lawyer, minister, housewife, state
government official, labor leader, banker, and surgeon--and was among
the earliest instances, if not the first, of physicians bringing
nonprofessionals into the realm of clinical decision-making. Committee
members insisted on remaining anonymous so that the medical staff, the
public, and especially the applicant-patients would never know their
identities.
The lay committee took its Solomonic charge seriously. "As
human beings ourselves," the lawyer told a reporter, "we
rejected the idea, instinctively, of classifying other human beings in
pigeonholes, but we realized we had to narrow the field somehow."
The committee did this by considering many factors, among them the
applicant's income, sex, marital status, net worth, nature of
occupation, extent of education, church attendance, number of dependents
(more dependents conferred a better chance of being chosen), and
potential for rehabilitation.
Within five months of its founding, the lay committee was thrust
into the public eye. The New York Times ran a front page story in May
1962: "Panel Holds Life-or-Death Vote in Allocating Artificial
Kidney." In November, Life, the 1960s' most influential
popular weekly magazine, ran a story by journalist Shana Alexander
called "They Decide Who Lives, Who Dies: Medical Miracle Puts Moral
Burden on a Small Community." The expose drew national attention to
what was happening in Seattle. Alexander dubbed it the "Life or
Death Committee," and the accompanying photo spread depicted the
members in silhouette, as if sitting in harsh judgment. In 1965, Edwin
Newman narrated an NBC documentary about Seattle called "Who Shall
Live?" Vocal physicians, social scientists, theologians, and legal
scholars felt that the selection of dialysis recipients based upon
determinations of human worth was an affront to the ideal of equality.
The moral claim of each patient to treatment was equivalent, they
argued. One much-cited essay in the UCLA Law Review bitingly observed
that "The Pacific Northwest is no place for a Henry David Thoreau
with bad kidneys," chiding the committee for ruling out creative
nonconformists.
Allocation of dialysis was among the first tragic choices to arise
in the modern era of medical innovation. Only on the battlefield had
case-by-case triage ever been performed so explicitly. The scarcity of
dialysis treatment generated layer upon layer of vexing questions. Who
should receive life-saving care, who should choose, and on what
principle? Some medical centers employed a first come, first served
policy; a few shuttered their programs altogether so they would not have
to choose. Most medical centers favored the utilitarian principle of
maximizing outcome--in other words, choosing patients who would get more
productive years out of dialysis. Inevitably, this ended up favoring the
same patients who impressed selection committees as more conscientious,
better educated, and more likely to be beneficiaries of the emotional
and instrumental support that comes along with stable families.
Thus, throughout the 1960s and early '70s, the tragic choice
posed by dialysis was uneasily resolved in favor of handpicking
patients. By 1972, however, pressure from advocates and physicians had
become strong enough to move Congress to establish universal funding for
dialysis. The Medicare End-Stage Renal Disease (ESRD) program, the new
federal entitlement, offered virtually unfettered access to dialysis.
Once the gate had swung open--admitting not only more patients who were
good dialysis candidates (i.e., otherwise fairly healthy and
cooperative) but also those with other medical and behavioral
problems--enrollment and costs skyrocketed. More and more patients were
kept alive on dialysis, and as advances in anti-rejection medication
came about in the early 1980s, more people wanted kidney transplants,
viewing dialysis as a bridge to surgery. With each passing year, the
volume of candidates burgeoned and the amount of time spent waiting for
a cadaver kidney increased. These dynamics were soon compounded by the
aging of the U.S. population and the surge of diabetes (the most common
single cause of renal failure). In 2004, the most recent year for which
there are data, the ESRD enrolled about 340,000 patients and cost over
$18 billion. Less than 1 percent of the Medicare population consumed
more than 6 percent of Medicare expenditures that year.
Today, 35 years after the establishment of ESRD, we have come full
circle. Once we were rationing dialysis, and now we are rationing
kidneys. The details have changed, but the basic challenge of assigning
scarce resources has not.
A shortage of altruism
UNDER THE 1984 National Organ Transplant Act, anyone who offers or
receives something of material value in exchange for an organ can be
charged with a felony. The ban's rationale was twofold: to prevent
lurid scenarios in which desperately poor people auctioned off their
spare parts to the wealthy and to ensure that citizens had equal access
to the organs collected. "The prisoner in California gets the heart
transplant because he needs it and is first on the list. It's blind
to whether you're a saint or a sinner or a celebrity. That's
key to maintaining the public trust," said Mark Fox, former head of
the UNOS ethics committee.
But the trust is already damaged because of the death toll over
which UNOS presides. The equity that UNOS seeks to preserve is
"degenerating into an equal opportunity to die waiting,"
nephrologist Benjamin Hippen told the President's Council on
Bioethics last year. The dire shortage of organs today is striking
evidence of the fact that altruism is not sufficient to produce enough
organs. In 2006, there were 7,180 deceased donors (yielding an average
of 1.5 kidneys each) and 6,242 living donors (mainly family and
friends). At the end of that year, the 67,000 candidates remaining
dwarfed the number of available organs.
A cohort of physicians and economists has sought for at least two
decades to persuade the transplant establishment to apply incentives to
increase the organ supply. Many creative arrangements--from tax credits
to tuition vouchers for children to charitable contributions in the
donor's name--should be given a trial, they urge, to see whether
new practices could compensate for the limits of altruism. Over the past
few years, their voices have grown more insistent. In 2003, the American
Medical Association testified in favor of a House bill that proposed
pilot studies of incentives for harvesting the organs of deceased
donors. At the 2006 World Transplant Congress in Boston, Dr. Richard
Fine, president of the American Society of Transplantation, asked his
colleagues: "Is it wrong for an individual who wishes to utilize
part of his body for the benefit of another [to] be provided with
financial compensation that could obliterate a life of destitution for
the individual and his family?"
At the 2007 annual meeting of the American Society of Transplant
Surgeons in January, a straw poll revealed that 80 to 85 percent of
participants were in favor of studying incentives for living and
deceased donors, according to society president Dr. Arthur Matas of the
University of Minnesota. The public is receptive as well. A 2007
national Gallup Poll on attitudes toward donation of organs after death
found that incentives would encourage more respondents to donate than
would be discouraged from doing so, though the majority said their
decision would remain unchanged. Most striking, among the 18- to
34-year-old age group, 34 percent said they would be more likely to
donate, 6 percent said they would be less likely to do so; the rest were
unchanged.
The moral imperative to innovate
PARADOXICALLY, THE CURRENT system, which is based on an
altruism-or-else policy, undermines respect for individual autonomy, one
of the most dearly held values in bioethics. Why shouldn't donors
be able to receive some form of reward for giving up a kidney to save a
life, especially if the act of compensating them encourages others to do
the same? To be sure, the idea of combining organ donation with material
gain can make people queasy. Yet the mix of financial and humanitarian
motives is commonplace. No one objects, for example, to a tax credit for
charitable contributions--a financial incentive to complement the
"pure" motive of giving to others. The great teachers who
enlighten us and the doctors who heal us inspire no less gratitude
because they are paid. A salaried firefighter who saves a child trapped
in a burning building is no less heroic in our eyes. Motives for giving
an organ should not be the issue. More important than whether a kidney
is given freely or for material gain is that it will increase the supply
of kidneys to ameliorate suffering.
How could incentives work? A plan first offered in the late 1980s
proposed to register a would-be donor today in return for the
possibility of a much larger payment to his estate should his organ be
used at his death. A major advantage of such a forward-looking approach
is that the decision-making burden is taken off family members at a
painful time--when they are sitting in the emergency room learning that
someone they love is now brain-dead. The drawback to this plan, however,
is that deceased donors alone cannot meet the need for kidneys because
very few Americans who die, perhaps 13,000 a year (or less than 1
percent of all deaths), possess organs healthy enough for transplanting.
Thus, even if every American participated in a futures arrangement, the
need for thousands of kidneys would go unmet.
Of course, the organs from deceased donors obtained through a
futures mechanism would be a most welcome contribution to the pool, but
in order to enhance supply more quickly and more robustly, living donors
need to be recruited as well. Not only can a person live a healthy life
with one kidney, but the long-term risk to the donor is negligible, and
short-term risks are comparable to surgical intervention in general
(about 3 deaths in 10,000). Moreover, a kidney from a living donor lasts
longer than one from a cadaver, thereby keeping young and middle-aged
recipients from getting back in the queue for a second organ sooner than
they otherwise might have to.
What kinds of incentives could be offered to individuals amenable
to relinquishing a kidney while living? Perhaps the federal government
could offer lifetime Medicare coverage. Not only would this be medically
responsible; it could serve as an inducement to donate--not to mention
saving taxpayer dollars by liberating patients from costly dialysis. If
the promise of health insurance did not attract a sufficient pool of
donors, other incentives could be offered as well. For example, the
donor could choose from a menu of options including a deposit to a
401(k) retirement plan, tax credits, tuition vouchers for the
donor's children, long-term nursing care, family health coverage,
life and nonfatal injury insurance, a charitable contribution in the
donor's name, or cash payments stretched over time. Under this
scheme, Medicare would underwrite the incentives in light of the fact
that it already pays for dialysis treatment, which costs about $66,650
per patient annually according to the United States Renal Data Service.
Compare these expenses with the cost of a transplant
operation--approximately $75,000 in all for the one-time cost of the
surgeries and hospital stays of the donor and recipient, plus the first
year of follow-up medical care including medication. Thereafter, the
cost of immunosuppressive drugs is about $12,000 per year. (4)
An important concern accompanying any enrichment plan is the
potential for exploiting donors--especially low-income donors who, as
the critics reasonably claim, will be the most likely to find incentives
attractive. This is why donor protection is the linchpin of any
compensation model. Standard guidelines for physical and psychological
screening, donor education, and informed consent could be formulated by
a medical organization, such as the American Society of Transplant
Surgeons, or another entity designated by the federal Department of
Health and Human Services (HHS). A "waiting period" of three
to six months could be built in to ensure that the prospective donor has
ample time to think through his commitment. Monitoring donor health
post-transplant is important as well and should include annual physicals
and laboratory tests for one to two years after donation.
Incentive arrangements could be overseen by HHS or an entity it
designates. As is currently the case with cadaver organs, kidneys
obtained from compensated donors would be matched with the next best
candidate waiting on the national list. This would require revising the
National Organ Transplant Act to lift the ban on valuable consideration
so that experimental trials could be conducted. Alternatively, Congress
might permit individual states to apply for a waiver from the ban in
order to devise their own incentive systems.
Within such a framework, altruistic donation would proceed in
parallel with a system that offers compensation. Any medical center or
physician that objects to the practice of compensating donors can simply
opt out of performing transplants that use such organs. Recipients on
the list are free to turn down a paid-for organ and wait for one given
altruistically. Choice for all--donors, recipients, and physicians--is
enhanced, while lives are saved.
A reprieve
THESE BROAD PROPOSALS and variants on them need considerable
elaboration. There is no denying the political and practical challenges
that come with introducing payment into a 20-year-old scheme built on
the premise that generosity is the only legitimate motive for
relinquishing an organ. Yet as death and suffering mount, constructing
an incentive program to increase the supply of transplantable organs
becomes a moral imperative.
We see again in 2007 how remarkable advances in transplant medicine
have reintroduced the classic dilemma of equity versus utilitarianism that beset the medical profession in 1962 after the advent of dialysis
therapy. To be sure, the world of health care is no stranger to
rationing--simply determining what pharmaceuticals are to be covered by
health plans is a form of rationing. But rarely has case-by-case access
to treatment been as overt as it was in the early days of dialysis and
is now in transplantation, though these days it is perhaps somewhat less
dramatic, as choices are not based explicitly upon patients' social
characteristics.
Would incentives work? There is good reason to be optimistic, but
pilot studies are required to test various models. Architects of any new
plan must give serious consideration to principled reservations and
practical concerns; but they must act nonetheless, taking small,
cautious steps. One thing is certain: A larger pool of kidneys would
offer a reprieve, at least a partial one, to those patients languishing on dialysis and to those given the tragic charge of deciding which lives
will be saved.
Sally Satel is a resident scholar at the American Enterprise
Institute. She is editing a book on the use of incentives to expand the
supply of kidneys for transplantation.
(1) Dr. Guthrie's story was reported in Alan Zarembo,
"How old is too old for a transplant? Kidneys are scarce. Elderly
patients may get fewer if rules change," Los Angeles Times (November 5, 2006).
(2) Paired exchanges are estimated to yield about 1,000 new kidneys
per year, according to Dorry Segev, MD, Johns Hopkins School of Medecine
(personal communication, May 16, 2007). Non-heart-beating decedents may
yield as many as 7,000 new donors per year (at 1.5 kidneys per donor,
plus other vital organs) from deaths that occur in hospitals, according
to Jim Warren, editor of Transplant News (personal communication, April
12, 2007).
(3) Judith Graham, "Should age determine who gets a kidney
transplant? Controversial proposal would put younger patients higher on
waiting list," Chicago Tribune (February 9, 2007).
(4) Arthur J. Matas and Mark Schnitzler, "Payment for Living
Donor (Vendor) Kidneys: A Cost-Effectiveness Analysis," American
Journal of Transplantation 4 (February 2004).