Development in moral doctrine.
Noonan, John T., Jr.
THAT THE MORAL teachings of the Catholic Church have changed over
time will, I suppose, be denied by almost no one today. To refresh
memories and confirm the point, I will describe four large examples of
such change in the areas of usury, marriage, slavery, and religious
freedom,and then analyze how Catholic theology has dealt with them.
Usury
The first is the teaching of the Church on usury. Once upon a time,
certainly from at least 1150 to 1550, seeking, receiving, or hoping for
anything beyond one's principal--in other words, looking for
profit--on a loan constituted the mortal sin of usury. The doctrine was
enunciated by popes, expressed by three ecumenical councils, proclaimed
by bishops, and taught unanimously by theologians. The doctrine was not
some obscure, hole-in-the-corner affectation, but stood astride the
European credit markets, at least as much as the parallel Islamic ban of
usury governs Moslem countries today. There were ways of profiting from
the extension of credit, ways that were lawful; but these ways had been
carefully constructed to respect the basic prohibition; and it was a
debated question at what point they crossed the line and were themselves
sinfully usurious. The great central moral fact was that usury,
understood as profit on a loan, was forbidden as contrary to the natural
law, as contrary to the law of the Church, and as contrary to the law of
the gospel.(1)
All that, we know, has changed. The change can be exaggerated.
Even at the height of the prohibition of usury not every form of
credit transaction was classified as a loan from which no profit might
be sought. The idea of legitimate interest was also not absent. Formally
it can be argued that the old usury rule, narrowly construed, still
stands: namely, that no profit on a loan may be taken without a just
title to that profit. But in terms of emphasis, of perspective, of
practice, the old usury rule has disappeared: the just title to profit
is assumed to exist. The centrality of "Lend freely, hoping nothing
thereby," construed as a command, has disappeared. We take interest
as profit on our banking accounts. We expect our banks to profit from
their lending business. Our entire financial world is built on
profitable charges for credit. The idea that it is against nature for
money to breed money, or that it is contrary to church law to deposit in
a savings institution with the hope of a profit, or that hoping for
profit at all from a loan breaks a command of Christ--all these ideas,
once unanimously inculcated with the utmost seriousness by the teaching
authority of the Church, are now so obsolete that one invites
incredulity by reciting them.
Marriage
Usury was a moral doctrine dependent on economic conditions that
could change. Let us now consider, as something related to fundamental
unchanging human nature, moral doctrine on adultery, bigamy, and
marriage. Monogamy without divorce is the law of the gospel, established
by words attributed to Jesus himself and related by him to the
primordial order established by God (Matt 19:2-9). Within the New
Testament, however, a perceptible change occurs. If, of two married
unbelievers, one converts and the other does not but deserts the
convert, St. Paul teaches that the convert is free: "Neither a
brother nor a sister is a slave in these matters" (1 Cor 7:10-16).
The implication, teased out in patristic times, is that the convert can
commit what otherwise would be adultery and bigamy and enter a second
marriage in the Lord.(2)
Until the 16th century, this so-called Pauline privilege remained
the solitary exception to Christian monogamy. Then, on behalf of African
slaves torn from their African spouses and shipped to South America, the
privilege was radically extended. The slave who wanted to convert could
not know whether his absent spouse would abandon him or not. No matter,
Gregory XIII ruled in 1585, it was important that such converts be free
to remarry "lest they not persist in their faith." On their
behalf, the pope dissolved their old marriages and declared them free to
enter a second marriage that would otherwise have been adulterous and
bigamous.(3)
The next step in this direction was taken under the impetus of the
great canonist Cardinal Pietro Gasparri in the 1920s. In a case from
Helena, Montana, Gerard G. Marsh, unbaptized, had married Frances F.
Groom, an Anglican. They divorced; Groom remarried. Two years later
Marsh sought to marry a Catholic, Lulu La Hood; Pius XI dissolved
Marsh's marriage to Groom "in favor of the faith" of Miss
La Hood. Apparently exercising jurisdiction over the marriage of two
nonCatholics (Groom and Marsh), the Pope authorized Marsh to marry a
Catholic under circumstances that but for the papal action would
(morally, not civilly) have constituted bigamy for Marsh and adultery
for La Hood.(4) Prior to 1924 the teaching of the Church, expressly
grounded on both the commandment of the Lord and on the natural law, was
that marriage was indissoluble except in the special case of conversion
of an unbeliever. The teaching was unanimously expressed by papal
encyclicals and by the body of bishops in their universal ordinary
teaching. Then, in 1924, by the exercise of papal authority, the meaning
of the commandment against adultery was altered; what was bigamy was
revised; and a substantial gloss was written on the Lord's words,
"What God has joined together let no man put asunder."
Slavery
Let us now examine two examples taken from an area more fundamental
than justice in lending, more fundamental than rectitude in sexual
relations--examples that bear on the basic conditions of moral autonomy.
I mean moral doctrine on human liberty. And first, moral doctrine on a
human being's right to be free from ownership by another human
being.
Once upon a time, certainly as late as 1860, the Church taught that
it was no sin for a Catholic to own another human being; to command the
labor of that other human being without paying compensation; to
determine where he or she lived and how much he or she was fed and
clothed; to restrict his or her education; to pledge him or her for a
loan, forfeit him or her for a default, sell him or her for cash; to do
the same as to his or her offspring; and to discipline him or her by
physical punishments if he or she were rude or boisterous or slack in
service. I refer, of course, to some of the features of chattel slavery
as it existed in the United States, as it was upheld by American law,
and as it was applied by Catholic laymen, bishops, and religious orders
with the approval of ecclesiastical authority. No qualm of conscience
troubled that leading Catholic jurist, Chief Justice Roger Taney, as he
wrote Dred Scott, or disturbed the slaveholding Maryland Province of the
Society of Jesus.(5) That loving one's neighbor as one's self
was observed only in a Pickwickian way by holding one's neighbor in
bondage was not a commonplace of Catholic moral thought.
It was Catholic moral doctrine that slaves should be treated
humanely, and that it was good to give slaves freedom. With some
qualifications it was Catholic moral doctrine that slaves should be
allowed to marry.(6) But Catholic moral doctrine considered the
institution of slavery acceptable. St. Paul had accepted it, returning
Onesimus to his master (Phlm 11-19) and instructing the Christian slaves
of Corinth to obey their masters (1 Cor 7:21).
The premier moralist of the West, St. Augustine, said succinctly
that Christ "did not make men free from being slaves." The
greatest of reforming popes, Gregory I, accepted a young boy as a slave
and gave him as a gift to another bishop; his famous decision to send
missionaries to England is said to have arisen from his musings as he
browsed in a slave market in Rome.(7)
The greatest of Catholic jurisprudents, Henri de Bracton, thought
slavery was contrary to natural law, but accepted it as an institution
of the law of nations; he merely copied the great Catholic lawgiver,
Justinian. St. Antoninus of Florence followed St. Thomas in acquiescing
in the civil law permitting slave status to follow birth to a slave
woman. Paul III praised the benevolent effects of slavery on agriculture
while approving the traffic in slaves in Rome. The eminent Jesuit
moralist Cardinal Juan De Lugo was in harmony with the moralists'
tradition when he found slavery "beyond the intention of
nature," but "introduced to prevent greater evils." Near
the end of the seventeenth century, the master French theologian, Bishop
Bossuet, declared that to condemn slavery would be "to condemn the
Holy Spirit, who by the mouth of St. Paul orders slaves to remain in
their state."(8)
In 1839 Gregory XVI condemned the slave trade, but not so
explicitly that the condemnation covered occasional sales by owners of
surplus stock.(9) In the first treatise on moral theology written for
Americans, Bishop Francis Kenrick in 1841 declared it no sin against
nature to own slaves treated in a humane way and added that, even if
Africans had been brought to America unjustly, long lapse of time had
cured any defect in title on the part of those who had inherited
them.(10) Up until actual abolition occurred, the Church was mute on the
institution. Or, rather, the Church endorsed the institution as
compatible with Christianity, indeed as Bossuet observed, expressly
approved in Christian Scripture.
Again, all that has changed. In the face of the repeated teachings
of modern popes, beginning with Leo XIII, on the rights of labor,
uncompensated slave labor is seen as a moral outrage. In the light of
the teachings of the modern popes and the Second Vatican Council on the
dignity of the human person, it is morally unthinkable that one person
be allowed to buy, sell, hypothecate, or lease another or dispose of
that person's children.(11) And all the usual and inevitable
corollaries of chattel slavery (the denial of education, the denial of
vocational opportunity, the destruction of the family) have been so long
and so vigorously denounced by bishops and moral theologians that today
there is a rampart of authority condemning the conditions without which
such slavery could not exist. Slavery has disappeared from most of the
world. The Catholic Church stands as one of the great modern teachers
excoriating it as evil.
Religious Freedom
Finally, I turn to moral doctrine on the freedom that should attend
religious belief. Once upon a time, no later than the time of St.
Augustine, it was considered virtuous for bishops to invoke imperial
force to compel heretics to return to the Church. Augustine's
position was expressly grounded in the Gospels.(12) At a later point in
time (the rule is well-established in St. Thomas Aquinas) it is doctrine
that a relapsed heretic will be judged by the ecclesiastical authorities
and remanded to the secular authorities for execution. Forgers are put
to death for debasing the currency. Why should not those disloyal to the
faith be killed for falsifying it? God may pardon them; the Church and
the State should not.(13)
For a period of over 1,200 years, during much of which the Catholic
Church was dominant in Europe, popes, bishops, theologians regularly and
unanimously denied the religious liberty of heretics; no theologian
taught that faith may be freely repudiated without physical
consequences, no pope extended the mantle of charitable tolerance to
those who departed from orthodox belief. On the contrary, it was
universally taught that the duty of a good ruler was to extirpate not
only heresy but heretics.(14) The vast institutional apparatus of the
Church was put at the service of detecting heretics, who, if they
persevered in their heresy or relapsed into it, would be executed at the
stake. Hand and glove, Church and State collaborated in the terror by
which the heretics were purged.
Nor did doctrine change markedly as the Protestant Reformation led
to the acceptance not of religious liberty but of religious toleration
in parts of Europe. Tolerance is permission of what is frankly described
as an evil, but a lesser evil. Eventually, as religious peace became the
norm in 18th- and 19th-century Europe, the hypothesis was advanced and
accepted that in such circumstances it was for the common good to
refrain from religious persecution.(15) The thesis required that in
ideal circumstances the state be the physical guarantor of orthodoxy.
All that changed quite recently--only 28 years ago. Then the Second
Vatican Council taught that freedom to believe was a sacred human right;
that this freedom was founded on the requirements of the human person;
that this freedom was at the same time conveyed by Christian revelation;
and that the kind of respect that must be shown for human freedom of
belief had been taught from the beginning by Jesus and his Apostles, who
sought not to coerce any human will but to persuade it. No distinction
was now drawn between the religious freedom of infidels (in theory
always respected) and the religious freedom of heretics, once trampled
on in theory and practice. Now each human being was seen as the
possessor of a precious right to believe and to practice in accordance
with belief. Religious liberty was established. The state's
interference with conscience was denounced.(16)
The minority in opposition strenuously maintained that the teaching
of the magisterium was being abandoned; they cited express texts and
hitherto unchallenged papal statements. Archbishop Marcel Lefebvre, a
leader of the minority, debating the document at the council, said
sarcastically that what was proposed was "a new law," which
had been condemned many times by the Church. What was being taught did
not come from the tradition of the Church, but from "Hobbes, Locke
and Rousseau," followed by rejected Catholic liberals such as
Lamennais. Pius IX had rejected it. Leo XIII had "solemnly
condemned it" as contrary "to Sacred Scripture and
Tradition."(17) A commentator after the fact calmly observed that
the Council had "reversed the teaching of the ordinary papal
magisterium."(18) The doctrine regnant from 350 to 1964 was, in a
cryptic phrase, reclassified as conduct occurring through "the
vicissitudes of history."(19)
Enough has been said, I trust, to suggest the nature of the
problem. Wide shifts in the teaching of moral duties, once presented as
part of Christian doctrine by the magisterium, have occurred. In each
case one can see the displacement of a principle or principles that had
been taken as dispositive--in the case of usury, that a loan confers no
right to profit; in the case of marriage, that all marriages are
indissoluble; in the case of slavery, that war gives a right to enslave and that ownership of a slave gives title to the slave's offspring;
in the case of religious liberty, that error has no rights and that
fidelity to the Christian faith may be physically enforced. These
principles were replaced by principles already part of Christian
teaching: in the case of usury, that the person of the lender, not the
loan, should be the focus of evaluation; in the case of marriage, that
preservation of faith is more important than preservation of a human
relationship; in the case of slavery, that in Christ there is
"neither free nor slave" (Gal 3:28); and in the case of
religious liberty, that faith must be free. In the course of this
displacement of one set of principles, what was forbidden became lawful
(the cases of usury and marriage); what was permissible became unlawful
(the case of slavery); and what was required became forbidden (the
persecution of heretics).
It is true that the moral doctrine of the Catholic Church can be
seen as sui generic; it belongs to no type and so yields no laws. Change
depends on two free agencies: human will and the Holy Spirit. No
a-priori rules can bind or predict their course.(20) Nonetheless, when a
palpable change has taken place (and surely usury, slavery, religious
liberty, and divorce are cases in point) it should be possible to look
back and determine what the conditions of change were; to observe the
extent of the change that was possible; and to construct a provisional
theory as to the limits to change. At least, in Newman's words, one
might propose "an hypothesis to account for a difficulty."(21)
While a large literature exists on the development of doctrine,
examination reveals that this literature is focused on changes in
theological propositions as to the Trinity, the nature of Christ, the
Petrine office, or Marian dogma. I have found no well-known writer on
development who has addressed the kinds of change I have described
above; no great theologians have immersed themselves deeply in these
mutations of morals. One exception, as will be noted below, is Bernard
Haring, but he does not theorize at length. But perhaps we can profit by
analogy if we look at what theologians have had to say about changes in
propositions of faith.(22)
One approach, of which Bishop Bossuet and Orestes Brownson are
representative, has been to deny that any real change has ever occurred;
there has only been an improvement in expression. For Bossuet and
Brownson the invariance of Catholic teaching was a mark of the true
Church, to be triumphantly contrasted with "the variations"
found among Protestants. A second approach, of which Spanish
17th-century theology affords an example, took the position that it is
possible for the Church to work out the logical implications of
Scripture and so reach, and declare as true, propositions not contained
in Scripture; real advances occur.(23)
A third, and highly influential theory, was put forward in 1843 by
John Henry Newman. Writing still as an Anglican, yet as one about to
become a Catholic, Newman produced a work that is part detective story
(what is the true Church?) and part apologia (all the apparent defects
of the true Church are defensible). His mind, teeming with images,
offered a variety of ways of understanding how the Church's
doctrine of today was not literally the same as the Church's
doctrine of yesterday, but yet the Church was faithful to her Founder.
Doctrine, he declared, developed. In the later Apologia pro vita sua,
development became one of the "principles" of Catholic
Christianity.(24) What was meant by development was illustrated in the
Essay on Development by analogy: by analogy to the beliefs of a child as
these beliefs matured in the mind of the child become adult; by analogy
with the thought of a poet, whose verse contained more than was explicit
in his mind as he composed; by analogy with any organic life as it grows
from bud to flower; and by analogy to the course of an idea embraced by
a society, an idea whose detailed consequences can be grasped only as
the idea is lived out in the society. By all these comparisons Newman
confessed that changes had occurred in the doctrine of the Church but
maintained that the changes had been rooted in the original revelation
and were a perfection, not a distortion, of it. True development, he
wrote, "corroborates, not corrects, the body of the thought from
which it proceeds."(25)
The Modernists took the idea of development and ran away with it.
Doctrine became the projection of human needs, changing in response to
those needs. Control of doctrine by the objective content of revelation
disappeared.(26) The Church rejected Modernism and retained
Newman's conclusion that there was genuine growth in doctrine from
unchanged foundations. Vatican II put it tersely: "Insight grows
both into the words and the realities that have been handed
on."(27) Change, that was in fact doctrinal progress, was
celebrated. The central reality, in relation to which insight grew, was
Jesus Christ, himself "both the mediator and the plenitude of the
whole revelation."(28)
How would any of these approaches work if applied to moral
doctrine? To deny that real change had occurred, as Bossuet and Brownson
did, would be an apologetic tactic incapable of execution and unworthy
of belief. To say, as did the 17th-century Spanish, that the unfolding
had been by logical implication would be equally incredible: the
acceptance of slavery did not imply freedom, the endorsement of
religious persecution did not entail respect for religious freedom. The
method might indeed be used if the most basic principles, such as
"Love your neighbor as yourself," were the starting point. But
would logic alone suffice?
Newman's complex set of analogies is different. At one level
of doctrine, of course, one cannot maintain that the Church's
present championing of freedom, personal and religious,
"corroborates" an earlier stage in which the Church defended
chattel slavery and religious persecution. At another level,
Newman's notion of an idea maturing can be criticized by taking his
analogy with organic life literally; he can then be caricatured as
supposing that spiritual growth is similar to vegetative growth.(29) But
Newman's rich range of arguments and metaphors cannot be so neatly
written off. In a passage dealing with the nature of development in
general that I read as decisive, he declares:
The development then of an idea is not like an investigation worked
out on paper, in which each successive advance is a pure evolution from
a foregoing, but it is carried on through and by means of communities of
men and their leaders and guides; and it employs their minds as its
instruments and depends upon them while it uses them.... It is the
warfare of ideas under their varying aspects striving for the
mastery....(30)
This passage acknowledges an objectivity in the idea or ideas at
issue; at the same time it fully recognizes that development occurs by
conflict, in which the leading idea will effect the "throwing
off" of earlier views now found to be incompatible with the leading
idea more fully realized.(31) Principles, broadly understood, underlie
and control specific changes.(32) Newman's approach is adaptable to
the development of moral doctrine.
The Modernist position that human needs will shape doctrine carries
the cost of eliminating any objective content; it is, as Pius X put it,
"the synthesis of all the heresies."(33)
Finally, there is the position of Vatican II: there can be and is a
growth in insight into a reality that is Jesus Christ. It comes from
"the contemplation of believers, the experience of spiritual
realities, and the preaching of the Church."(34) As Bernard Haring
has amplified the words of Dei verbum: "Christ does not become
greater through ongoing history, but our knowledge of the plan of
salvation which is revealed in the world in Christ does become more
complete and close to life in our hearts through the working of the
Spirit in the history of the Church and above all in the
saints."(35)
To hold that moral doctrine changes with increased insight into
Christ is an attractive proposition. It entails one obvious danger. When
one sees more deeply into Christ, is one looking into a mirror merely
reflecting one's own deepest feeling? The answer must be that the
Church has the mission of determining what is only the projection of
subjective feelings and what is an authentic response to Christ as
revealed.
If insight into Christ is taken from the realm of faith to that of
morals and applied to our four examples, it will be found to afford at
least partial explanation of what has happened. On the great question of
religious liberty, a stronger appreciation of Christ's own methods
has led to repudiation of all violence in the enforcement of belief. On
the great question of human slavery, a better grasp of the fellowship
effected by Christ has made the holding of any person in bondage
intolerable.
In the other cases one factor facilitating change was a deeper,
less literal reading of the words of Christ. Where "Lend freely,
hoping nothing thereby," had been understood as a peremptory command, it came to be understood as an exemplary exhortation.(36) Where
"What God has joined together, let no man put asunder" was
read as absolute, the possibility of exception has been eventually
envisaged and expanded. In these cases, too, one could say that the
reality of Christ was better reached by the abandonment of the letter.
Yet it would be preposterous to imagine that all these profound
changes occurred simply by the acquiring of deeper insights into Christ.
Human beings do not reach moral conclusions in a vacuum apart from the
whole web of language, custom, and social structure surrounding them. A
society composed entirely of free human beings was unknown in the
Mediterranean world of the first centuries; a society where the state
did not support religion was equally unknown. Only as social structures
changed did moral mutation become possible, even if the change in social
structures, as it might reasonably be argued, was owed at least in part
to the perception that structures fostering liberty were more congruent
with deeper insight into Christ.(37)
Those structures could not have shifted without experience. The
central European experience leading first to religious tolerance and
then to religious liberty was the experience of the evil of religious
persecution. The experience was long and bloody and sufficient to
demonstrate how demoralizing the enforcement of religion by force was.
Equally, I would argue, it was the centuries-old experience of slavery
that led to the conclusion that slavery was destructive both for the
slaves and for the masters.(38)
Experience as such, taken as "raw experience," the mere
participation in this or that phenomenon, is, however, not the key. Raw
experience carries with it no evaluation. But experience, suffered or
perceived in the light of human nature and of the gospel, can be judged
good or bad. It was the experience of unfreedom, in the gospel's
light, that made the contrary shine clear.(39)
The negative experience of religious persecution was reinforced by
the American experience of religious freedom, for America launched the
great experiment of a nation committed to the nonestablishment of any
national religion and the free exercise of religion. The American
experiment had blemishes, such as the persecution of the Mormons and of
the Jehovah's Witnesses, and the denial of constitutional freedom
to conscientious objectors to unjust war. But the American ideal, and
its relative success, were clear, and taught to Europe by Tocqueville,
Lamennais, and Lacordaire. In the end, the theologians built on the
American experience, guided in no small part by an American theologian,
John Courtney Murray. Finally, sealing all by fire, was the experience
of religious unfreedom under the terrible dictatorships of the 20th
century. Without those experiences, negative and positive, and without
the elaboration of the ideal by Tocqueville and Murray, the changes made
by Vatican II could not have occurred.(40)
The advance on slavery also depended on articulation by individuals
who were ahead of the theologians and the Church. In Catholic France,
Montesquieu challenged the morality of slavery, writing with fine irony
of blacks: "It is impossible that we should suppose those people to
be men, because if we should suppose them to be men, we would begin to
believe that we ourselves are not Christians."(41) It was
18th-century Quakers and Baptists and Methodists and 19th-century
Congregationalists who led the fight against slavery in the
English-speaking world, and it was the French Revolution that led to its
abolition in the French empire. The gospel, as interpreted by
Protestants and as mediated by Rousseau and the revolutionaries of 1789,
achieved much.(42) Only after the cultures of Europe and America changed
through the abolitionists' agency and only after the laws of every
civilized land eliminated the practice, did Catholic moral doctrine
decisively repudiate slavery as immoral. Only in 1890 did Pope Leo XIII
attack the institution itself, noting that slavery was incompatible
"with the brotherhood that unites all men."(43) At the end of
the argument and articulation and legal upheaval that had gone on for
two centuries, the requirement of Christ was clear.
In contrast, the change regarding divorce and remarriage, adultery
and bigamy, appears to have been almost entirely an internal process.
But was it? St. Paul's original modification of monogamy responded
to conditions he encountered affecting conversion. His rule worked well
enough until the extreme conditions of African slavery in South America
suggested the need for radical expansion. And that change was not
improved upon until, in modern religiously mixed societies, it became
common for unbaptized persons and Catholics to fall in love and want to
be married. Then a new expansion was made. Canonistic ingenuity and
exaltation of papal power played a dominant part. The canonists
responded to changed external conditions as they discovered the true
meaning of Christ's command.
The change with regard to usury, basically effected in the course
of the 16th century although formally acknowledged only in the 19th,
came from the convergence of several factors. Europe moved from an
agricultural to a commercial economy. Moral theologians began to give
weight to the experience of otherwise decent Christians who were bankers
and who claimed banking was compatible with Christianity. The morality
of certain types of credit transactions (the so-called triple contract
and the personal annuity and the foreign exchange contract) were all
re-examined and re-evaluated in the light of credit transactions already
accepted as legitimate. Perhaps above all, the perspective of moral
analysis shifted, from focus on the loan in itself to focus on the
lender and the investment opportunity the lender lost by lending. All
these factors--commercial developments, attention to experience, new
analyses, shift in perspective--produced a moral doctrine on usury that
was substantially different from that taught throughout the Middle Ages
and substantially similar in practice to what is accepted today. All
these factors, plus re-evaluation of the words of Christ, created the
new moral doctrine.(44)
CONCLUSION
Where morals are at issue, the process of change requires a complex
constellation of elements. Every society, including the Church, lives by
rules that keep its vital balance. Change one, and the balance is
jeopardized. Hence there is a conservative tendency to keep the rules as
they are, there is fear when they are given up, and sometimes nostalgia
for the loss.
Change is also resisted for other reasons. There is a praiseworthy desire to maintain intellectual consistency. There is a longing in the
human mind for repose, for fixed points of reference, for absolute
certainty. There is alarm about the future: What else can change? There
is the theological conviction that as God is unchanging, divine demands
must also be unchanging. How could one have gone to hell yesterday for
what today one would be held virtuous in doing? How could one have done
virtuously yesterday what one would be damned for doing today? How could
one once have been bound to a high and demanding standard that later is
said to be unnecessary? How could one once have been permitted to engage
in conduct that is later condemned as uncharitable? A mutation in morals
bewilders. Hence there is a presumption of rightness attending the
present rules, and authority is rightly vigilant to preserve them. Not
every proposed mutation is good; the majority, it could be guessed,
might be harmful.
But a new balance can be struck. The consistency sought should not
be verbal nor literal; nor can conformity to every past rule be
required. The consistency to be sought is consistency with Christ. The
human desire for mental repose is not to be satisfied in this life. One
cannot predict future changes; one can only follow present light and in
that light be morally certain that some moral obligations will never
alter. The great commandments of love of God and of neighbor, the great
principles of justice and charity continue to govern all development.
God is unchanging, but the demands of the New Testament are different
from those of the Old, and while no other revelation supplements the
New, it is evident from the case of slavery alone that it has taken time
to ascertain what the demands of the New really are. All will be judged
by the demands of the day in which they live. It is not within human
competence to say with certainty who was or will be saved; all will be
judged as they have conscientiously acted. In new conditions, with new
insight, an old rule need not be preserved in order to honor a past
discipline.
Another response to change is to ignore it, to deny explicitly or
implicitly that it has occurred, to be aware of the mutations described
here and find them without significance--just so many well established
and well-known historical facts. Denial of that sort also betrays fear
of change, fear that change is simply chance. Mutations are muted. But
why should believers in Christ have such a fear? The Spirit guides the
Church. The acts of development have a significance beyond themselves.
"The idea of development was the most important single idea Newman
contributed to the thought of the Christian Church."(45) The idea
of development had this importance because it contained an explanation
of the passage from the past and a Delphic prophecy of the future.
In the Church there can always be fresh appeal to Christ, there is
always the possibility of probing new depths of insight. To grow is to
change, and the gospel parable of the mustard seed promises growth (Matt
13:31-32). The kingdom of "heaven, we are told, is like a
householder who from his storeroom brings forth things old and new (Matt
13:52). Our world has grown by mutation, should not our morals,
especially when the direction and the goal are provided by the Lord?
"[H]ere below to live is to change. And to be perfect is to have
changed often."(46) Must we not, then, frankly admit that change is
something that plays a role in Catholic moral teaching? Must not the
traditional motto semper idem be modified, however unsettling that might
be, in the direction of plus ca change, plus c'est la meme chose?
Yes, if the principle of change is the person of Christ. (*) A more
developed form of the Thomas Verner Moore Lecture sponsored by St.
Anselm's Abbey, September 29, 1990, at the Catholic University of
America. (1) On the whole topic, see John T. Noonan, Jr.,
"Authority on Usury and on Contraception," Tijdschrift voor
Theologie 6 (1966) 26-50, republished in Cross Currents 16 (1966) 55-79
and The Wiseman Review (Summer, 1966) 201-29. The standard definition of
usury was given by Gratian, Decretum, Corpus iuris canonici, ed. E.
Friedberg (Leipzig, 1879-1881) 2.14.3.1. The Second Council of the
Lateran condemned usury (G. D. Mansi, Sacrorum conciliorum nova et
amplissima collectio [Paris, 1901-1920] 21.529-30); the Third Council of
the Lateran declared usury to be condemned "by the pages of both
Testaments" (Mans 22.231). The Council of Vienne declared that
anyone "pertinaciously affirming that to practice usury is no sin
should be punished as a heretic" (Clement, Constitutiones 5.5,
Corpus iuris canonici, ed. E. Friedberg). (2) See John T. Noonan, Jr.
Power to Dissolve (Cambridge: Harvard Univ., 1972) 343. (3) Ibid. 356,
citing Gregory III, Populis et nationibus, reprinted as Document VII in
the appendix to Codex iuris canonici (Rome: Vatican, 1917). (4) Power to
Dissolve 370-371. (5) According to Ambrose Marechal, Archbishop of
Baltimore the province in 1826 owned as personal property "about
500 African men" (Marechal to Cardinal Della Somaglia, January 15,
1826, in Thomas Hughes, S.J., History of the Society of Jesus in North
America: Documents [New York: Longmans, Green, 1908] 1.1.544). Anthony
Kohlmann, S.J., commenting on this assertion, put the number of slaves
at half this figure; he added that their value was less than Marechal
supposed because "those over 45 cannot be alienated," the
clear inference being that those under 45 could be sold (ibid. 545). (6)
Gratian, Decretum 2.29.2.8 upheld the validity of slave marriages but
required the consent of the slaves' owners. In the U.S., Bishop
Francis Kenrick thought that "the majority" of slave
agreements did not have "the force of marriage" since
"the intention of contracting a perpetual bond is lacking to
them" (Francis P. Kenrick, Theologia moralis [Philadelphia, 1843]
3.373). (7) Augustine, On Psalm 125 no. 7 (J. P. Migne, Patrologiae
cursus completus. Series latina [hereafter PL] (Paris, 1844-1891)
37.1653; Gregory, Epist. 7.30 (PL 77.887 [accepts slave]). For the story
of the slave market, see Bede, Historia ecclesiastica gentis anglorum,
ed. George H. Moberley (Oxford: Clarendon, 1869) 2.1; cf. Anon., The
Earliest Life of Gregory the Great, ed. and trans. Bertram Colgrave
(Cambridge: Cambridge Univ., 1968) 91. (8) Henri de Bracton, De legibus
et consuetudinibus Angliae, ed. S. E. Thorne (Cambridge: Harvard Univ.,
1970-77) 2.30, following Justinian, Digesta 50.17.32; Antonius, Summa
sacrae theologiae (Venice, 1581-82) 3.36; Paul III, Motu proprio,
November 9, 1548, trans. in John F. Maxwell, Slavery and the Catholic
Church (Chichester: Ross, 1975) 75; Lugo, De iustitia et lure 6.2,
Disputationes scholasticae et morales (paris, 1899) vol. 8; Jacques B.
Bossuet, Avertissement sur les lettres du Ministre Jurieu, in Bossuet,
Oeuvres completes (Lyons, 1877) 3.542. (9) Gregory XVI, In supremo
apostolatus, Acta ed. Antonio Maria Bernasconi (Rome: Vatican, 1901)
2.388. Bishop John England was at pains to explain to Secretary of State
John Forsyth that none of the bishops at the Provincial Council of
Baltimore thought that Gregory XVI's condemnation affected the
American institution of slavery; see John England, Works, ed. Ignatius
A. Reynolds (Baltimore J. Murphy, 1849) 3.115-119. The Holy Office in
1866 ruled that the buying and selling of slaves was not contrary to
natural law (Holy Office to the Vicar Apostolic of the Galle tribe in
Ethiopia, June 20, 1866 Collectanea S. C. de Propaganda Fide [Rome,
1907] I n. 1293). (10) Kenrick, Theologia moralis, vol. 2, tract (11)
E.g. Vatican II, Gaudium et spes no. 67, in Decreta, Declarationes, ed.
secretaria generali concilii oecumenici Vaticani II [Rome: Typis
polyglottis Vaticanis, 1966] 790 (Constitutiones 790). (12) Augustine to
Boniface, Epistula 185, PL 33.803. (13) Thomas Aquinas, Summa
theologiae, ed. Pietro Caramello (Turin: Marietti, 1952), 2-2, q. 11, a.
3 (death penalty; comparison to ,forgery); q. 11, a. 4 ad 1 (Church
"cannot imitate" God in reading hearts and so does not keep
relapsed heretics "from peril of death" imposed by the state).
(14) Lucius III, Ad abolendam (Decretale Gregorii IX, 5.7.9). (15) John
A. Ryan and Francis J. Boland, Catholic Principles of Politics (New
York: Macmillan, 1940) 317-21. The same aching appears in John A. Ryan
and Moorhouse F. X. Millar, S.J., The State and the Church (New York:
Macmillan, 1924) 35-39. (16) Vatican II, Dignitatis humanae personae no.
2, Second Vatican Council, Constitutiones 55. (17) Lefebvre,
Intervention, Sept. 20, 1965 (Acta Synodalia Sancti Concilii Oecurnenici
Vaticani 11 [Rome, 1976] 4.1, p. 409). (18) J. Robert Dionne, The Papacy
and the Church (New York: Philosophical Library, 1987) 193.
(19)Dignitatis humane personae 11. (20) See Karl Rahner, S.J.
Theological Investigations I, trans. C. Ernst (Baltimore: Helicon, 1961)
41. (21) John Henry Newman, An Essay on the Development of Christian
Doctrine, ed. Charles Frederick Harrold (New York: Longmans, Green,
1949) 28. (22) Consider as representative of recent work, Jan Hendrik
Walgrave's Unfolding Revelation: The Nature of Doctrinal
Development (London: Huntchinson, 1972). It has no discussion of moral
doctrine. Jaroslav Pelikan's massive work, The Christian Tradition:
A History of the Development of Doctrine (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago,
1971-1989) does not deal with any of the four changes used as examples
here; in other words, the development of moral doctrine is no part of
his comprehensive treatment of "the development of doctrine."
A recent sensitive account of the history of moral theology offers no
theory of development; see John A. Gallagher, Time Past, Time future: A
Historical Study of Catholic Moral Theology (New York: Paulist, 1990).
But John Mahoney, The Making of Moral Theology (New York:
Oxford/Clarendon, 1987) 320 observers that "the church has a great
difficulty . . . in handling the subject of change as such."
Mahoney goes on to note that change is "an unavoidable element of
human existence" and to suggest that change in moral doctrine is
sometimes the right response to changed conditions (326-27). (23) See
Owen Chadwick, From Bossuet to Newman: The Idea of Doctrinal Development
(Cambridge: Cambridge Univ., 1957) 20 (Bossuet); 171 (Brownson); 25-44
(Spanish). (24) Newman, Apologia pro vita sua, ed. Charles Frederick
Harrold (new York: Longmans, Green, 1947) 79. (25) Newman, Essay on
Development 2.5.6, p. 186. Newman wrote as an Anglican but did not amend
the quoted passages when he revised the Essay as a Catholic. On the
analogies, see Chadwick 151, 155. Aidan Nichols sees Newman's
fundamental metaphor as that of a seal cutting a design of we, (From
Newman to Congar: The Idea of Doctrinal Development from the Victorian
,to the Second Vatican Council [Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1990] 44).
(26) See John T. Noonan, Jr., "The Philosophical Postulates of
Alfred Loisy" (M.A. thesis. Catholic University of America, 1948).
(27) Vatican II, Dei verbum 8, Second Vatican Council, Constitutiones
430. (28) Ibid. 8, p. 494. (29) Compare the criticism of Newman's
metaphor by Ambroise Gardeil, Le Donne reuele et la theologie (Paris: J.
Gabalda, 1910) 156, noting the difference between "la vie d'un
vegetal et la vie d'un esprit." (30) Newman, Essay on
Development 1.1.6, p. 74. (31) Ibid. (32) Ibid. 2.5.2, p. 167. (33) Pius
X, Pascendi dominici gregis, Sept. 8, 1907 (Acta sanctae sedis 40.632;
Eng. trans. in All Things in Christ, ed. Vincent A. Yzermansi,
[Westminster, Md: Newman, 1954] 117). (34) Vatican II, Dei verbum no. 8,
Second Vatican Council, Constitutiones 430. (35) Bernard Haring, My
Witness for the Church, trans. Leonard Swidler (New York: Paulist, 1992)
122. (36) Urban III treated the words of Christ on lending as mandatory
(Urban III, Consuluit, Decretalia Gregorii IX 5.19.10, Corpus iuris
canonici, ed. E. Friedberg). Domingo de Soto is the first major
scholastic theologian to challenge this interpretation (De iustitia et
lure libri decem [Lyons, 1569] 6.1.1). (37) Cf. Louis Vereecke, Storia
della teologia morale moderna (Rome: Lateran, 1979) 1.4-5 (moral
theology is where the unchanged gospel encounters changing cultures).
(38) See Thomas Jefferson, Notes on the State of Virginia, ed. William
Peden (Chapel Hill: North Carolina, 1955) Query 18. (39) See Roger
Williams, The BLOUDY TENENT, of Persecution, for Cause of Conscience,
discussed, in A Conference between TRUTH and PEACE (1644), reprinted and
ed. Samuel L. Caldwell, The Complete Writings of Roger Williams (New
York: Russell & Russell, 1963) 3.3-4. (40) See Alexis de Toqueville,
Democracy in America, trans. Henry Reeve, rev. Francis Bowen (New York:
Alfred A. Knopf, 1945) 308-9; John Courtney Murray, "Governmental
Repression of Heresy," Proceedings of the Catholic Theological
Society of America 3 (Washington: Catholic Theological Society, 1948)
161. (41) Charles de Secondat, Baron de Montesquieu, L'Esprit des
lois, in his Oeuores completes (Paris, 1843) 5.309. (42) See David Brion
Davis, The Problem of Slavery in Western Culture (Ithaca: Cornell Univ.,
1966) 291, 333, 401. (43) Leo XIII, Catholicae ecclesiae, November 20,
1890 (Acta sanctae sedis 23.257). (44) See John .T. Noonan, Jr., The
Scholastic Analysis of Usury (Cambridge: Harvard Univ., 1956) 199-201.
(45) Owen Chadwick, Newman (Oxford: Oxford Univ., 1983) 47. (46) Newman,
Essay on Development 1.1.7, p. 38.