The ordination of women: tradition and meaning.
Ferrara, Dennis Michael
In a recent issue of this journal, I essayed a retrieval of St.
Thomas's interpretation of the theological axiom that the priest,
in consecrating the Eucharist, acts in the person of Christ (in persona
Christi), arguing that Thomas assigns the axiom a primarily
ministerial-apophatic rather than representational sense.(1) Although
the main burden of the article was to combat the hierarchical
interpretation of in persona Christi that dominates recent magisterial teaching, it was perforce related to the question which has triggered
this interpretation, namely, the question whether women may be ordained
to the priesthood.
Even as my article was going to press, Pope John Paul II issued a
terse reaffirmation of the traditional ban against women priests,
declaring that his judgment "that the church has no authority
whatsoever to confer priestly ordination on women . . . is to be
definitively held by all the church's faithful."(2) If the
precise binding force of this declaration remains somewhat unclear, the
pope clearly does not rule out scholarly discussion of the arguments on
which it is based, as even Joseph Ratzinger has insisted.(3) The present
note is intended as a contribution to this ongoing discussion, with
specific reference to the distinction, and the importance thereof,
between the external fact of the Church's traditional ban on the
ordination of women and the inner theological meaning of this tradition.
Contemporary statements of the magisterium on this question have
argued on both fronts. First and foremost, they have argued on the basis
of the Church's constant and universal tradition of reserving the
apostolic ministry to men. According to the magisterium, this tradition
cannot be explained by the social and cultural vagaries of human
history, specifically, by the historical prejudices against women, but
stems from the will and institution of Christ himself, in such wise that
the Church is powerless to change it: "The Church, in fidelity to
the example of the Lord, does not consider herself authorized to admit
women to priestly ordination";(4) "the Church has no authority
whatsoever to confer priestly ordination on women."(5)
There is, however, a second and complementary argument advanced by
the magisterium against the ordination of women, namely, the argument
from theological meaningfulness, what Inter insigniores calls the
consonance of an all-male priesthood with God's plan of
salvation,(6) the light which this doctrine sheds, within the analogy of
faith, on the mystery of Christ(7) and the Church.(8) Pope John Paul Il
himself argues along these lines. In Ordinatio sacerdotalis, he speaks
of the "appropriateness of the divine provision,"(9) makes
repeated mention of God's "plan,"(10) specifically
ascribes the choice of men alone to "the wisdom of the Lord of the
universe",(11) and cites approvingly Paul VI's statement that
in choosing only men Christ gave the Church a "theological
anthropology" thereafter ever followed by the Church.(12) The
anthropological argument had been specified in Mulieris dignitatem(13)
13 in terms of the nuptial mystery between Christ and the Church in a
way that rehearses the central theoretical argument advanced in Section
5 of Inter insigniores, i.e. that the priest in celebrating the
Eucharist represents Christ the bridegroom and acts in persona Christi.
Nonetheless, despite this affirmation in principle of the existence
of intrinsic arguments, Ordinatio sacerdotalis makes no attempt to
specify what these might be. In particular, the pope virtually bypasses
the notion, so central to both Inter insigniores and Mulieris
dignitatem, of the priest's "representation of Christ,"
being content with a generalized and passing reference, supported by a
citation not of Inter insigniores but of Lumen gentium, to priests as
"carry[ing] on the apostles' mission of representing Christ
the Lord and Redeemer,"(14) relying instead on a forceful appeal to
the will of Christ in choosing twelve men as Apostles.(15) The present
note addresses what I believe to be the two main points raised by this
new, almost voluntaristic approach of the magisterium to the question of
women's ordination: (1) the inherently intelligible character of
the question itself; and (2) the actual understanding of this question
in the concrete tradition of the Church.
The Intelligible Nature of the Question
In the classic teaching of St. Thomas, the act of faith, though
performed under the "imperium" of the will, formally resides
in the intellect, since its object is the true, the verum.(16) It iS for
this reason precisely that theology, as fides in statu scientiae, has as
its proper aim the understanding of revealed truth. Implied in this
characteristically Catholic view of faith and theology is the
intelligibility of revealed truth itself. Nor is this view belied by the
abiding mysteriousness and supernaturality of those truths which
constitute the formal and normative objects of faith: the Trinity, the
Incarnation, and our divinization through grace. However opaque our
intellects in the presence of the pure refulgence of divine light--like
the eyes of the bat in the presence of the sun, says Thomas--however
meager and halting the insights achieved by our piecemeal forays into
the infinite, open country of divine being, it remains ever true that
God is truth and that our search aims at the understanding of that
truth, at the meaning of what is believed.
Now if this Catholic affirmation of the intelligibility of divine
truth and of our ability, though scant, to grasp that intelligibility
obtains in regard to even the most strictly supernatural of mysteries,
it obtains even more in regard to the question of the ordination of
women. For this question formally and directly concerns a constitutive element of the natural order, viz. the division of the sexes, insofar as
that division is "presupposed and perfected" in the order of
grace. It pertains, then, as Pope John Paul II himself states in
Ordinatio sacerdotalis, to the divine wisdom, that wisdom which, as St.
Thomas further explains, constitutes the intelligible and intelligent
basis, the "first principle," of the natural order based on
the "distinction of things."(17) More precisely, the
priesthood is a sacrament and so involves, as Inter insigniores insists,
a natural sign,(18) as do the other sacraments, e.g. washing for
baptism, a meal for the Eucharist. In the case of priesthood, moreover,
the sacramental sign pertains directly to the Church's public and
social nature, that is, its character as a "differentiated
body" and a "supernatural society,"(19) with its own
immanent and permanent structures. Now the doctrine that the priest must
be male expressly ties this sacramental sign to the natural
differentiation of the sexes and by that very fact posits the existence
of an intelligible link between the two in terms of what Paul VI, as
noted above, rightly called "theological anthropology."
Correlatively, to admit that the question of women priests pertains
directly to the divine intellect is by that very fact to admit that it
does not pertain directly, and hence cannot be resolved by appeals to,
the divine will. For while God does many things which leave us entirely
baffled, the placing of women in Church and world is not one of them. We
are not dealing here with an object of the divine election, not with
God's choice of individuals (Abraham, Mary) or nations (Israel, the
Persians) as instruments of the divine purpose, nor with God's
permissive unleashing of the devil upon the innocent (Job, Christ,
perhaps, at times, ourselves). Such choices are indeed inscrutable,
their "meaning," as Job 38-41 makes painfully clear, lost in
the mystery of the divine counsel. Faced with them we can only, if we
have the heart and grace for it, repeat with St. Paul: "How deep
are the riches and the wisdom and the knowledge of God! How inscrutable
his judgements, how unsearchable his ways!" (Rom 11:33). But the
relation between the priesthood and the natural differentiation of the
sexes does not and cannot pertain to God's will in this sense,
unless, of course, we wish to say that the traditional Catholic axiom on
the relation between nature and grace has here, in this one instance and
quite arbitrarily, been abrogated by the First Truth.
Once we grasp the inherently intelligible nature of the question of
women's ordination--if God has willed to exclude women from
priesthood, there must be a reason for it, one in some way meaningful to
the inquiring Christian mind--we are forced to limit the import of the
magisterium's appeal to the will and example of Christ. Inter
insigniores, for example, stresses Christ's enlightened and
antiprejudicial attitude to argue that his reservation of the apostolic
ministry to men was consciously willed and not the product of
"sociocultural conditioning."(20) Pope John Paul Il makes the
point even more strongly, emphasizing Christ's sovereign freedom in
calling the Twelve,(21) a freedom exercised in union with the Father and
his eternal plan.(22) However, this line of argument, which stresses the
historical Jesus' transcendence of cultural conditioning, besides
curiously taking its stand in the no-man's land of historical
reconstruction, begs the basic and underlying issue: if Christ indeed
consciously willed to restrict the apostolic ministry to men for all
time, what was his reason for doing so? For some reason must be assigned
to the Lord's alleged decision:(23) the subjective freedom of an
act is one thing, its objective content quite another. To vindicate
Christ's freedom in choosing only men thus tells us nothing
whatsoever about the divinely intended reason for the alleged choice.
Nor is the notion of divine vocation, which the magisterium invokes by
citing texts such as Mark 3:13--"he summoned the men he himself had
decided on"(24) --pertinent in this context; for God's call,
as an intervention in the historical order of grace, is addressed to
individuals, to unique historical persons, not to a natural class.
The question, then, concerns not the Lord's will but the
Lord's mind in this matter and, no less, the means available to us
for discerning it. Here, traditional Catholics will surely find Pope
John Paul II's argument from Christ's call of the Twelve
unsettling; first, because the link between the scriptural texts cited
by the pope and the question of women's ordination seems tenuous at
best; second, because in the Catholic tradition, the privileged means
for discerning the meaning of Scripture is not private interpretation
(even by a pope), but interpretation by the living tradition of the
Church.(25)
The Concrete Tradition of the Church
The primary argument advanced by the contemporary magisterium
against the ordination of women is the constant and universal tradition
of the Church. In itself, of course, an appeal to merely factual
tradition cannot be decisive, for then the distinction between
authoritatively binding tradition and purely historical and changeable
traditions would collapse. The magisterium itself acknowledges this by
arguing that the historical tradition has its ground and authority in
the will and institution of Christ. Omitted from the argument is the
theological rationale for the factual tradition evidenced in tradition
itself How, in other words, has the theological tradition explained the
Church's factual exclusion of women from the priesthood, and thus,
by implication, the will and institution of Christ himself? Since it is
impossible in the scope of a brief note to review all the pertinent
texts, I will limit myself in what follows to the witness of medieval
scholasticism.
Two features of scholasticism indicate the particular value of this
focus. The first is the scholarly, compendious nature of the scholastic
corpus, as evidenced, for example, in the Sentences of Peter Lombard and
the numerous commentaries thereon, yielding at least a working
presumption that we will find resumed in that corpus whatever of
significance the Fathers had to say on our subject. The second point
goes to the heart of the matter. For it was the unique characteristic of
scholasticism, and its lasting contribution to the Church, to insist on
the unity of faith and reason, to seek the intelligibility inherent in
what is believed, and in so doing lay a conscious and characteristically
Catholic foundation for a faith that, however transcendent its object,
does not bypass the exigencies of the human mind.
Since Pope John Paul 11 bypasses historical witnesses in his two
pronouncements on our subject, my approach here will take the form of a
commentary on the appeal made to scholastic thought by Inter
insigniores.
The Scholastic Witness
According to Inter insigniores, although "the Scholastic
doctors, in their desire to clarify by reason the data of faith, often
present arguments that modern thought would have difficulty in accepting
or would even rightly reject," their refusal to admit the
ordination of women was inspired by the "same conviction" of
fidelity to Christ as was that of the Apostles.(26) This interpretation
of the scholastic witness raises, as the scholastics themselves would
say, questions both of fact and of meaning.
The questions of fact are two. The first concerns the frequency
with which the intrinsic arguments presented by the scholastics are
"faulty" and objectionable to the modern mind. According to
Inter insigniores, this was "often" the case, although no
texts are cited to explain or support this contention. The second and
correlative question is whether and to what extent the scholastics,
despite these "sometimes" faulty intrinsic arguments,
ultimately based their rejection of women priests on the extrinsic argument, namely, fidelity to the mind and will of Christ. Four
scholastics are cited in support of this latter assertion: St.
Bonaventure, Duns Scotus, Richard of Middleton, and Durandus of
Saint-Pourcain. Noticeably absent from this list is the Church's
Common Doctor, Thomas Aquinas.
The significance of the omission of Thomas begins to become
apparent when we note that all four of the scholastics cited as
affirming the extrinsic argument explain the meaningfulness thereof by
way of what the Declaration calls a "faulty" intrinsic
argument -- a veiled reference to woman's traditionally alleged
inferior status, an argument based on the priest's hierarchical
role as leader of the community (eminentia gradus) and not on his
sacramental role.(27) Thus Bonaventure:
Our position is this: it is due not so much to a decision by the
Church as to the fact that the sacrament of Order is not for them. In
this sacrament the person ordained is a sign of Christ the Mediator. He
who rules bears the type of Christ the Head; thus, since a woman cannot
be the head of a man, she cannot be ordained.... There is a perfection
in regard to sanctifying grace, and this can be received equally by
women and men; and there is a perfection of status in regard to a
charism; and this can benefit one sex and not another, since it relates
not only to what is internal, but also to what is external. Such is the
perfection of Order, in which there is a conferral of power, which can
be shown on multiple grounds evidently not to befit women.(28)
Scotus presents the same argument even more forcefully. While
indeed contending that the exclusion of women from orders is due neither
to "a determination by the Church," nor even "a decision
by the Apostle [Paul]," but "derives from Christ" who, he
adds, "did not even place his mother in any grade of Order in the
Church,"(29) Scotus argues as follows for the meaningfulness of
Christ's alleged institution:
Order ... is a certain grade of eminence over others in the Church
and is for a certain act of superiority which must somehow be signified
by natural eminence of condition and rank. But woman is naturally in a
state of subjection in relation to man, and therefore cannot possess a
rank of eminence over any man, because in reference to nature, state,
and nobility, women are less noble than any man; hence, after the fall,
the Lord subjected her to man's dominion and power. If then she
could receive Order in the Church, she could preside and rule, which is
against her condition. Thus, a bishop conferring orders on a woman not
only does evil by transgressing the precept of Christ--he does nothing
at all, nor does the woman receive anything, since she is not a matter
capable of receiving this sacrament.(30)
The same basic arguments had been rehearsed by Richard of
Middleton, earlier Franciscan doctor, who, while asserting that
"Christ instituted this sacrament for conferral on men only, not
women," argues the reasonability of this institution as follows:
(1) public teaching does not befit women on account of the weakness of
their intellect and the mutability of their affections; and (2)
woman's state of subjection and natural inferiority make her by
nature incapable of representing the eminence of rank in which one is
constituted by Order.(31)
We come, finally, to Durandus of Saint-Pourcain, an independent
(i.e. non-Thomist) Dominican of the early 14th century. Women, according
to Durandus, are indeed barred from priestly ordination by the
institution and precept of Christ, who, both at the Last Supper and in
his postresurrection bestowal of the power to forgive sins, ordained
only men, to the exclusion of even his mother, the holiest of women. At
the same time, Christ's will is based on a sound reason for
Durandus, and what this is, is not surprising. Order, he says, places
one in a rank of superiority over the nonordained, a rank which it does
not befit women to have over men, since women are in a state of
subjection on account of their bodily weakness and intellectual
imperfection.(32)
In sum, all four of the scholastics cited by Inter insigniores as
basing the rejection of women priests on the extrinsic argument defend
the reasonableness of this argument by intrinsic arguments labeled
"faulty" by the Declaration itself, i.e. the commonly accepted
view of women's natural "state of subordination." Nor
does the Declaration cite any "non-faulty" intrinsic arguments
by the scholastics. That this belies the implication of the
Declaration's statement that the scholastics "often"
invoke intrinsic arguments--the implication, namely, that some
scholastics presented intrinsic arguments that were cogent--is confirmed
when we examine St. Thomas's position on the matter.
Like Scotus, Thomas argues that the male sex is so required for the
validity of orders that even if a woman were otherwise qualified her
reception of the sacrament would be invalid. The reason for this is that
the sacrament is a sign and hence requires not only the reality
signified (res), but also the signification of that reality
(significatio rei); for example, since Extreme Unction signifies the
healing of the sick, only a sick person can validly receive it. Now
since woman's state of subjection makes it impossible for the
female sex to signify any eminence of rank, women are incapable of
receiving the sacrament of Order.(33) Of particular note is
Thomas's exclusive reliance on the intrinsic argument, on the
argument from theological meaning. Despite his explicit recognition of
the fundamentality of Christ's institution of the sacraments, (34)
Thomas foregoes the appeal to that institution made by the later
scholastics cited by Inter insigniores and, of course, both by Inter
insigniores itself and Ordinatio sacerdotalis. And the same must be said
of Bonaventure, who, in the very text cited by Inter insigniores itself
(see above), makes no appeal to Christ's institution.
This brings us to the second question of fact raised by the
Declaration's interpretation of scholasticism: the extent to which
the scholastic authors based their rejection of women's ordination
on fidelity to the mind and will of Christ. According to Inter
insigniores, the appeal to the institution of Christ is normative for
the entire scholastic period: "The same conviction ... animates
medieval theology."(35) The texts reviewed above, however, reveal
two distinct groups of scholastics with two distinct approaches: a first
group, represented by Thomas and Bonaventure, which relies solely on the
intrinsic argument; a second group, represented by Scotus, Richard of
Middleton, and Durandus, which employs both intrinsic and extrinsic
arguments. There is, moreover, a plausible historical reason for this
difference: the caesura in scholastic thought brought about by the
condemnations of 1277.
As is well known, the rapid introduction of Aristotle into
Christian intellectual life in the 13th century brought sharp and
not-altogether-uncalled-for criticism from traditionalist quarters. This
criticism gathered force in response to what Josef Pieper has called the
"dynamic rationalism" that began to emerge at the University
of Paris around 1265 under the aegis of Siger of Brabant, whose
Averroist reading of Aristotle provided the basis for what later came to
be known as the "double truth" theory. The matter came to a
climax in 1277, when the bishops of Paris and Canterbury, in whose
respective jurisdictions lay the universities of Paris and Oxford, the
intellectual centers of Christendom, condemned, virtually simultaneously
and seemingly in prearranged concert, a variety of propositions (many of
them Thomist) allegedly derived from pagan philosophy and inimical to
the faith.(36) Of specific importance is that underlying many of these
propositions (in their condemned form, at any rate) was a subjection of
faith to reason or, more precisely, a restriction of divine activity to
what is rationally possible and even necessary. Gilson speaks in this
connection of "Greek necessitarianism": the "Aristotelian
identification of reality, intelligibility, and necessity, not only in
things, but first and above all in God."(37) The condemnations had
a profound and chilling effect on Christian intellectual life. The free
play of ideas was checked, and the University of Paris paralyzed for
half a century. Gilson even thinks that in certain cases one can tell
simply by examining a teaching whether it was conceived before or after
1277.(38)
The anti-intellectual milieu created by the condemnations, a
climate in which reason became suspect by faith, makes historically
intelligible, if admittedly it does not demonstrate, the relative
emphasis placed on the extrinsic argument against women priests--the
argument from Christ's institution--by Richard of Middleton (who
came to Paris in 1278), Scotus, and Durandus in contrast to the simple
intrinsicism of Thomas and Bonaventure. At the same time, the post-1277
emphasis on the extrinsic argument is only relative: all five of the
scholastics in question defend the reasonableness of the Church's
refusal to ordain women with the same "faulty" intrinsic
argument from women's "natural inferiority." Nor does the
marginality of two of the Declaration's four witnesses enhance the
credibility of its interpretation of the scholastic period.(39)
To sum up, the Declaration's assessment of the scholastics is
at best highly misleading and at worst erroneous on both of the matters
pertinent to the present discussion. First, a review of the
Declaration's own witnesses points to the conclusion that the
scholastics do not offer "faulty" intrinsic arguments merely
"often," but always: no other intrinsic argument appears to be
forthcoming. Second, the appeal to Christ's institution is not a
constant but a late phenomenon within scholasticism, unknown to its two
greatest and most typical exponents and quite plausible in the
anti-intellectual milieu obtaining after 1277.
If the direct effect of the Declaration's skewed
interpretation is to emphasize the importance of the extrinsic argument
far beyond what is historically warranted, its ultimate effect is so to
separate the extrinsic and intrinsic arguments as to propose the former
in an historical and intellectual vacuum. Specifically telling in this
regard is the Declaration's "scissors and paste" approach
to the scholastic material, its citation of textual snippets on the
extrinsic argument to the exclusion of the intrinsic arguments, often
present in those very same texts. This studied separation of fact and
meaning is unmistakably clear in the official commentary on Inter
insigniores:
As for the theologians, the following are some significant texts:
Saint Bonaventure: "Our position is this: it is due not so much to
a decision by the Church as to the fact that the sacrament of Order is
not for them. In this sacrament the person ordained is a sign of Christ
the Mediator." John Duns Scotus: "It must not be considered to
have been determined by the Church. It comes from Christ. The Church
would not have presumed to deprive the female sex, for no fault of its
own, of an act that might licitly have pertained to it." Durandus
of Saint-Pourcain: . . . "the male sex is of necessity for the
sacrament. The principal cause of this is Christ's institution. . .
. Christ ordained only men ... not even his Mother. . . . It must
therefore be held that women cannot be ordained because of Christ's
institution."(40)
The separation is heightened by the Declaration's treatment of
St. Thomas, who as noted above, knows only the "faulty"
intrinsic argument. Inter insigniores deals with this embarrassing truth
about the Church's Common Doctor in two ways: first by excluding
Thomas in its rehearsal in Section 1 of the scholastic witnesses to the
extrinsic argument; second, by its citation, in the notorious
"natural resemblance" passage of Section 5, of Thomas's
intrinsic argument in a form so completely bowdlerized as to be
virtually indistinguishable from Bonaventure's symbolic argument
that the ordained person is "a sign of Christ the Mediator."
Citing Thomas, Section 5 argues that "the sacraments represent
what they signify by natural resemblance" and hence that the priest
must be male, "for otherwise there would not be this `natural
resemblance' which must exist between Christ and his
minister." What Thomas himself meant by "natural
resemblance" is clear. In response to the objection that slaves,
being, like women, in a state of subjection, are likewise barred from
orders, Thomas writes: "The sacramental signs are representative by
reason of natural resemblance. Now woman is in a state of subjection by
nature, which is not the case with a slave. Hence the two cases
differ."(41) This argument merely specifies the preceding argument
from sacramental signification. Just as a healthy person cannot receive
the sacrament of the sick, so woman, who is in a state of subjection
vis-a-vis man, cannot receive the sacrament of order, which signifies a
position of eminence in the ecclesial community, a position within the
ruling hierarchy. And while this argument from a "state of
subjection" is true for Thomas of both slaves and women, it is true
of them differently: for a slave is in subjection only factually and
hence is capable of being freed, whereas women is in a state of
subjection by nature and hence irreparably. It hardly seems necessary to
add that none of this has to do in any way, shape, for form with a
"natural resemblance" to Christ himself.
Conclusion
The contemporary magisterium rejects the possibility of ordaining
women on two bases: tradition and theology, external fact and intrinsic
meaning. Of these, the appeal to tradition is primary and normative,
only, however, insofar as this tradition is seen as reflecting the will
and institution of Christ, thereby reducing the arguments from
theological meaning to secondary importance, an emphasis which reaches
its apogee in Ordinatio sacerdotalis, the recent apostolic letter of
Pope John Paul II. I have argued that this approach is incommensurate with the nature of the doctrine in question, with the traditional
practice of Catholic theology, and with the historical facts themselves.
It is incommensurate with the doctrine, because the doctrine
involves the structural relation between nature and grace and hence has
its ultimate formal basis not in the divine will, and hence not in the
will of Christ, but in the divine intellect, what Pope John Paul II
himself calls "the wisdom of the Lord of the universe."
It is incommensurate with the traditional practice of Catholic
theology, which, even in regard to the highest and most mysterious of
revealed truths--the Trinity, the Incarnation, and our divinization in
grace--has consistently aimed at understanding divine truth, at moving
beyond mere fact, even divine fact, to the intelligibility of the fact,
to the meaningfulness of what is believed.
It is incommensurate with the historical facts of tradition,
insofar as the tradition makes only sporadic appeals to Christ's
institution and always joins this appeal, where it occurs, with an
intrinsic argument showing the meaningfulness of this institution.
Finally, the theological tradition prior to Vatican Il knows only
one intrinsic argument against the ordination of women: the
"faulty" argument from women's inferior status, an
argument linked, as I have said, to the priest's hierarchical
rather than sacramental role. While the present note has limited its
argument on this point to the scholastic era, a review of the patristic texts cited by Inter insigniores will reveal the argument to be valid
more universally.(42) Particularly unknown prior to Vatican II are
attempts, as in both Inter insigniores and Mulieris dignitatem, to
justify the maleness of the priest via the notion of
"representation" of Christ, whether by way of nuptial imagery
or, more technically, by invoking the in persona Christi axiom. And the
same must be said, I believe, of attempts to justify the maleness of the
priest by appealing to the normativeness of Christ's call of the
Twelve. Ironically, such arguments represent what the magisterium itself
might call a novelty: far from restating the older theological
tradition, they inaugurate as it were a new tradition.
The critically tenable conclusion of all this is not that the
magisterium's position on the ordination of women is wrong. The
critically tenable conclusion is that unless the magisterium wishes to
inculcate a form of fideism on this question, it will have to explain
its position, and the mind of Christ himself, with reasons other than
have appeared in the tradition of the Church thus far. Any such
rationale, as has been noted, will have to address the central
theological issue: the alleged link between the sexual difference and
the nature of the priesthood,(43) a link which comes to intelligible
expression in the essential functions and operations of the
priesthood,(44) traditionally summed up as the threefold "office
entrusted by Christ to his apostles of teaching, sanctifying, and
governing the faithful."(45) However faithful to the magisterium,
then, theologians may strive to be, they must, precisely as theologians,
continue to ask: What is it in these priestly functions that requires
that they be exercised by a man? What, that forbids them from being
exercised by a woman?
(1) Dennis Michael Ferrara, "Representation or Self-Effacement?
The Axiom In Persona Christi in St. Thomas and the Magisterium," TS
55 (1994) 195-224. (2) "Priestly Ordination" (Ordinatio
sacerdotalis), Apostolic Letter on Ordination and Women of Pope John
Paul II of May 30, 1994 (Origins, 24/4 [9 June 1994! 50-52). (3) Joseph
Ratzinger, "La Lettre Ordinatio sacerdotalis confirme ce que
I'Eglise a tou-jours vecu dans la foi" (La Documentation
Catholique no. 2094 [3 Juillet 1994] 611-615, at 612). (4) "On the
Question of the Admission of Women to the Ministerial Priesthood"
(Inter insigniores), Declaration of Oct. 15, 1976 of the Sacred
Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith (U.S. Catholic Conference
Edition with Commentary [Washington, D.C., 1977] Introduction; Acta
Apostolicae Sedis 69 [1977] 98-116, at 100). (5) Ordinatio sacerdotalis
no. 4. (6) Inter insigniores no. 4, end. (7) Ibid. no. 5. (8) Ibid. no.
6. (9) Ordinatio sacerdotalis no. 2. (10) Ibid. nos. 2, 3. (11) Ibid.
no. 3. (12) Paul VI, Address on the Role of Women in the Plan of
Salvation, Jan. 30, 1977 (Insegnamenti 15 [1977] 111) as cited in
Ordinatio sacerdotatis no. 2. (13) "On the Dignity and Vocation of
Women" (Mulieris dignitatem), Apostolic Letter of Aug. 15, 1988 of
Pope John Paul II (Origins 18/17 [6 Oct. 1988] no. 26; AAS 80/2 [1988]
1653-1729 at 1715-16). (14) Ordinatio sacerdotalis no. 2. (15) Ibid.
(16) Summa theologiae (ST) 2-2 q. 4, a. 2 c and ad 1. (17) ST 1, q. 44,
a. 3 c. (18) Inter insigniores nos. 4-5. (19) Ibid. no. 6. (20) Ibid.
no. 2. (21) Mulieris dignitatem no. 26. (22) Ordinatio sacerdotalis no.
2. (23) In Ratzinger's excellent formulation, the will of Christ is
neither "positivist" nor arbitrary," since it is
precisely "the will of the Logos and thus a will which has a
meaning" ("La Lettre Ordinatio sacerdotalis" 612). (24)
Inter insigniores no. 6; Ordinatio sacerdotalis no. 2. (25) Of
considerable pertinence here is the traditional teaching that the grace
of the teaching office (magisterium) in no way bestows on the
officeholder a special private access to the meaning of revealed truth
and hence does not dispense him from taking the ordinary means--serious
and objective study, wide consultation with clergy and laity,
prayer--for determining the truth in difficult and disputed matters. It
is, I would add, precisely by its willingness to take such ordinary
means that the magisterium best exhibits fidelity to its own essential
nature as a ministry of the revealed truth delivered once for all to the
Apostles. (26) Inter insigniores no. 1. (27) This point is elaborated at
greater length in my article "Representation or
Self-Effacement?" 216-23. (28) Bonaventure, In IV Sent. d. 25, a.
2, q. 1, ad 1 and ad 4. Scholastic discussions of the question of
women's ordination are found in commentaries on Book 4, dist. 25 of
Peter Lombard's Sentences, written around the middle of the 12th
century. That the Lombard did not himself raise the question of the
ordination of women indicates that the time frame in which the pertinent
scholastic texts occur begins in the 13th century. (29) Scotus, In IV
Sent. d. 25, Scholion (Opus Oxoniense). (30) Ibid. d. 25, q. 2 (Report.
Paris. (31) Richard of Middleton, In IV Sent., d. 25, art. 4, n. 1. (32)
Durandus of Saint Pourcain, In IV Sent., d. 25, q. 2. (33) ST Suppl. q.
39, a. 1 c. (34) ST 3 q. 64, a. 2 ad 1. (35) Inter insigniores no. 1.
(36) My account of the condemnations of 1277 and their significance is
based primarily on Josef Pieper, Scholasticism: Personalities and
Problems in Medieval Philosophy (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1956) 118-51,
whose sources include Gilson's History of Christian Philosophy in
the Middle Ages and van Steenberghen's The Thirteenth Century. For
a generally confirming view, see James Weisheipl, Friar Thomas Daquino:
His Life, Thought, and Work (New York: Doubleday, 1974) 331-50. (37) As
cited by Pieper, Scholasticism 138. Similarly, Weisheipl writes that
"The main thrust of the Parisian condemnation was to preserve the
omnipotence of God" (Friar Thomas 339). (38) See Pieper,
Scholasticism 127, 144. (39) So arcane did I find the references to
Richard of Middleton and Durandus of Saint Pourcain that I had to go
outside the Washington, D.C. area to find copies of their works. (40)
U.S. Catholic Conference Commentary 23 (41) ST Suppl. q. 39, a. 2 ad 4.
(42) For a fuller examination of the patristic literature, van der
Meer's pioneering study remains indispensable (Haye van der Meer,
S.J., Women Priests in the Catholic Church? A Theological-Historical
Investigation, trans. Arlene and Leonard Swidler [Philadelphia: Temple
University, 1973]); chap. 3 provides a critical review of many of the
patristic authors cited by Inter insigniores. Even a cursory reading of
van der Meer reveals the essential sameness, if not downright
repetitiousness, of the views expressed on our subject throughout the
patristic era, as well as the validity of the author's summary
remark that underlying the various views is "the conviction that
women cannot have any leadership role" (106). (43) In the end, the
question of women's ordination turns on the question of theological
anthropology, as implied by both Paul VI (see note 12 above) and John
Paul Il himself (see notes 9-11 and 13 above). It is, for example, only
in terms of the anthropology of the sexes that the argument from
Christ's will in calling the Twelve, which plays such a central
role in Ordinatio sacerdotalis, can take on theological meaningfulness.
And here it is of note that Ratzinger, who places repeated emphasis on
the significance of this call ("La Lettre Ordinatio
sacerdotalis" 611, 612, 613), makes no attempt whatever to
interpret this significance anthropologically, even while implying that
it is precisely the anthropological reasons that make it meaningful
rather than arbitrary (612). (44) Ratzinger rightly rejects a
"purely functional" and "pragmatic" view of the
priesthood, insisting on its "Christological criterion,"
namely, the priest's self-renouncing service of and obedience to
Christ, who was himself the archetype of service, washing the feet of
the disciples and preaching not his own word but that of the Father
("La Lettre Ordinatio sacerdotalis" 614). However, not only
does Ratzinger make no attempt to think this Christological criterion in
terms of the duality of the sexes, his argument actually reinforces the
apophatic-ministerial interpretation of the priesthood which I developed
in my article on in persona Christi, and which concluded that precisely
because of its ministerial essence, the priesthood transcends the sexual
difference. (45) Ordinatio sacerdotalis no. 1. In this opening sentence,
Pope John Paul Il himself invites us to think the relation between
priesthood and the distinction of the sexes "functionally" or,
as the scholastics would say, in terms of those fundamental operations
that actuate and express the inner