Optimal deterrence with legal defense expenditure.
Gravelle, Hugh ; Garoupa, Nuno
I. INTRODUCTION
In this article we consider a justice system which makes both type
I errors (sometimes convicting the innocent) and type II errors
(sometimes acquitting the guilty) and in which legal defense expenditure
on behalf of the accused can reduce their probability of conviction.
Such expenditure has a private value, but its social value is less
clear. We address two sets of issues. First, do individuals accused of
crimes take socially optimal decisions about their expenditure on legal
defense and, if not, what are the implications for public policy in
terms of the regulation of defense expenditure or its provision by the
state? Second, what are the implications of legal defense expenditure
for optimal deterrence policy?
In much of the literature on optimal deterrence welfare is the
unweighted sum of the expected utilities of honest and dishonest
individuals (Becker, 1968; Polinsky and Shavell, 1979). With such an
efficiency-oriented welfare function, the only socially relevant aspects
of legal defense are its effect on deterrence and its cost.
Because defense expenditures reduce the probability of punishment
of dishonest individuals, they reduce the expected sanction on dishonest
individuals and thus reduce deterrence. However, when there are type I
errors, honest individuals face the risk of wrongful arrest and
conviction. (1) Defense expenditure by them increases the rewards for
honesty. What matters for deterrence are the effects of defense
expenditure on the difference between the expected utility of honest and
dishonest individuals. We show that permitting defense expenditures may
increase deterrence as compared with a system in which no such
expenditure is permitted.
We also show that the level of defense expenditure chosen by
accuseds is not efficient. The private value of legal defense
expenditure is the reduction in the probability of conviction. Both
honest and dishonest individuals choose their expenditure, when accused,
to maximize their expected utility. The marginal effect of defense
expenditure on the expected utility of honest and dishonest individuals
at the privately optimal levels is zero. Consequently marginal changes
in defense expenditure at the private optimum have no effect on
deterrence because they do not change the difference between the
expected utilities of honest and dishonest individuals. But defense
expenditures do have a positive marginal social cost, so that the
marginal private and social values of defense expenditure are different
and there is scope for regulation to improve on the market equilibrium.
There is a commonly held view that type I and type II errors have a
direct effect on social welfare, rather than an indirect one through
their effect on deterrence. The view is reflected in Blackstone's
remark that it is "better that ten guilty persons escape, than that
one innocent suffer" (Volokh, 1997, 174). (2) With a
justice-oriented welfare function reflecting concern with type I and II
error, as well as with individuals' expected utilities, increases
in defense expenditure by the honest reduce type I errors and thereby,
ceteris paribus, increase welfare. Increases in defense expenditure by
the dishonest increase type II errors and thereby directly reduce
welfare. With a justice oriented welfare function honest individuals
spend too little on defense if the social cost of a type I error is
greater than the fine imposed if the individual is convicted. The
marginal social value of defense expenditure by the dishonest is always
negative at their privately optimal level.
The canonical result in efficient deterrence policy is the Becker
(1968) demonstration that, because fines have a positive deterrent effect but a zero marginal social cost, the optimal policy is to
increase them to a level that leaves convicted accused with zero wealth.
There are few examples of deterrence regimes that use maximal fines, and
the Becker result has generated a large literature that suggest reasons
why the efficient fine should not bankrupt convicted accused (Garoupa,
1997; Polinsky and Shavell, 2000).
The effective fine is limited by the wealth, net of defense
expenditure, of those convicted. We show that if the nominal fine is
large enough, accused individuals will choose a high level of defense
expenditure such that they will be bankrupted and unable to pay all the
nominal fine if found guilty but which leaves them with positive wealth
if acquitted. With a lower nominal fine they spend less on defense and
are not bankrupt even if convicted. There is critical level of the fine
such that they are indifferent between the high level of defense
expenditure that bankrupts them if found guilty and a lower level that
does not.
Suppose that the critical fine is smaller for the dishonest than
the honest. Then it can never be efficient to set the fine above the
level that is critical for the dishonest. Raising the fine above this
level would have no effect on the dishonest, because they cannot pay it
in full. Their defense expenditure will, however, jump upward. The
honest do pay the fine in full if convicted. They are made worse off and
their defense expenditure is increased. Hence raising the fine above the
critical level for the dishonest simultaneously reduces deterrence and
increases socially costly defense expenditure. The optimal fine cannot
exceed this critical level and both dishonest and honest types are left
with positive wealth if convicted. Note that it is the fact that defense
expenditures are chosen by the accused that drives the conclusion that
the optimal fine leave those convicted with positive wealth, not the
presence of type I errors.
Alternatively, if less plausibly, suppose the critical fine for the
honest is smaller than for the dishonest, so that they are induced to
choose bankruptcy before the honest. The fine again should not be
greater than the critical level that induces the dishonest to choose
bankruptcy. At higher levels there is no effect on deterrence because
neither type of individual pays the fine in full, but the expenditure of
the dishonest jumps upward. Hence the fine should not exceed a level
that leaves the dishonest with positive wealth but that induces the
honest to prefer bankruptcy if convicted. We show that if defense
expenditures are sufficiently responsive to the fine it will be optimal
to set the fine below the critical level for the dishonest. Thus even in
this case where the honest are induced to choose bankruptcy before the
dishonest, the efficient deterrence policy can leave both the honest and
the dishonest with positive wealth if convicted. The result does not
require that there be a direct social harm fro m type I errors.
With a justice-oriented welfare function, in which the amount of
type I and II error has a direct impact on welfare, assessing the
marginal social value of the fine is more complicated. Greater
deterrence reduces the amount of type II error because there are fewer
dishonest individuals, but, because there are more honest individuals,
there is more type I error. A higher fine induces more defense
expenditure, which reduces the amount of type I error and increases type
II error. Overall a concern for type I and II errors can increase or
reduce the optimal fine.
We outline the model and consider the implications of defense
expenditure for deterrence in the next section. In the following
section, we consider the choice of the fine in the presence of type I
and II error and defense expenditure and show that it is never efficient
to have a fine that bankrupts all those convicted. At the end of the
third section, we consider the justice-oriented welfare function and its
implications for optimal fine. Next, policies to regulate the level of
legal defense expenditure are discussed. We show that the market
equilibrium level of legal defense expenditure is not optimal under
either welfare function. We further examine an upper limit on
individuals' legal defense expenditures and a tax-financed public
defender system in which all accused receive the same amount of defense.
In the remainder of this introduction we relate our analysis to the
previous literature. Type I and II errors are considered by Ehrlich (1982) and Miceli (1991), who show that such errors can lead to a less
than maximal sanction if there is direct social concern with the
wrongful punishment of the honest and the mistaken acquittal of the
dishonest. In Png (1986) individuals can decide to take part in an
activity that may produce more social benefit than harm if they exercise
sufficient care. Because those who do not exercise sufficient care may
escape punishment, the fine should exceed the harm caused to ensure that
expected punishment equals the harm. Such a fine reduces participation
in the activity below its efficient level because some of those who do
take sufficient care are wrongly punished. Thus there should also be a
subsidy for participation in the activity. In none of these papers are
individuals able to reduce their probability of punishment by legal
defense expenditure.
The relationship between punishment and legal defense is considered
in Lott (1987), where it is assumed there are only type II errors, that
punishment is fixed, and that potential criminals have different
opportunity costs of imprisonment. Lott (1987) argues that if punishment
does not vary by opportunity cost, those with high opportunity costs
will be overdeterred. Allowing individuals to choose their defense
expenditure leads to those with greater opportunity costs spending more
on defense and having lower probability of punishment, thus reducing the
extent of overdeterrence. But restrictions on defense expenditure can be
welfare-increasing in these circumstances because they also reduce the
rewards to dishonesty of individuals with low opportunity costs of
imprisonment who are underdeterred (Garoupa and Gravelle, 2000).
Kaplow and Shavell (1990) show that legal advice to those
contemplating potentially harmful acts may either raise or lower
welfare, though they do not consider the costs of providing the advice.
In Malik (1990) there are only type II errors, and individuals who
decide to commit a crime can engage in a costly "avoidance"
activity that reduces their probability of punishment. Consequently, it
is argued that the fine may be less than the wealth of the accused
because its beneficial deterrent effect is partially offset by its
inducement of costly avoidance activity. Any policy that reduced
avoidance activity would therefore be socially beneficial. Our model
allows for type I errors and thus avoidance activity (legal defense
expenditure) by honest individuals. In these circumstances the issue of
whether avoidance activities that raise the expected utilities of both
honest and dishonest individuals are socially beneficial is nontrivial.
Further, by correctly specifying the bankruptcy constraint on policy, we
show that the efficient fine always leaves the convicted dishonest
individuals with positive wealth.
II. THE MODEL
The basic model is standard (Polinsky and Shavell, 1979, 2000). All
individuals are risk neutral and endowed with an income of y. (3) Each
considers the possibility of committing a harmful act with a benefit of
b and a social cost of h. Individuals are identical except for their
benefit b [member of] [0, [infinity]) which has a distribution function
G(b) over individuals. Because h > 0 is finite and fixed, some crimes
have a positive net social benefit. This is not essential, though it is
of interest to show that an optimal deterrence policy will in general
not seek to deter all crimes with a negative net social value. One
example might be firms that can choose to abide by pollution control
standards or violate them and risk a fine. The social harm from
additional pollution may exceed or be less than the costs incurred by
the firm in reducing its emissions.
Choice of Defense Expenditure by Accused
Every individual, whether honest or dishonest, has a probability of
being arrested and tried for the offense. The arrest probability of the
dishonest [q.sub.1] exceeds that of the honest [q.sub.0] (see Table 1):
(i) 1 > [q.sub.1] > [q.sub.0] > 0.
The probability of conviction [p.sub.i] for an accused individual
of type i is a decreasing convex function [p.sub.i]([c.sub.i]) of legal
defense costs [c.sub.i]: [p'.sub.i] < 0, [p".sub.i] > 0
and satisfies [p.sub.i](0) < 1, [p.sub.i]([infinity]) > 0. There
are both type I errors, because the honest have a positive probability
of conviction: [q.sub.0][p.sub.0]([infinity]) > 0, and type II
errors, because the dishonest have a positive probability of escaping
punishment: [q.sub.1][1 - [p.sub.1](0)] > 0.
The nominal fine for the offense is f. If the fine is less than y -
[c.sub.0] it is paid in full by a wrongfully convicted honest
individual, who is left with y - [c.sub.0] - f. If the fine exceeds y -
[c.sub.0] he is left with nothing. The honest accused chooses [c.sub.0]
to maximize [u.sub.0]([c.sub.0]) = [1 - [p.sub.0]([c.sub.0])](y -
[c.sub.0]) + [p.sub.0]([c.sub.0]) max{y - [c.sub.0] - f, 0}.
The dishonest accused's problem is very similar. We assume
that the benefit b from the crime is not recoverable by a fine. (4) If
the nominal fine is less than (y - [c.sub.1]) it is paid in full and the
convicted dishonest individual is left with y + b - [c.sub.1] - f. If
the fine exceeds y - [c.sub.1] he is left with b. The dishonest accused
will choose [c.sub.1] to maximize
[u.sub.1]([c.sub.1]) + b = [1 - [p.sub.1]([c.sub.1])](y -
[c.sub.1])
+ [p.sub.1]([c.sub.1]) max{y - [c.sub.1] - f, 0} + b,
= [1 - [p.sub.1]([c.sub.1])](y + b - [c.sub.1])
+ [p.sub.1]([c.sub.1]) max{y + b - [c.sub.1] - f, b}.
We assume that [p'.sub.i](0) > -[infinity] so that there is
a small enough fine [f.sup.0.sub.i] such that the accused only chooses
to spend on defense if f > [f.sup.0.sub.i]. There are two possible
solutions with positive defense expenditure: [c.sup.*.sub.i] and
[c.sup.**.sub.i], i=0,1. The first holds when the accused chooses a
level of expenditure that leaves positive wealth if convicted:
[c.sub.i](f) = [c.sup.*.sub.i](f) = argmax{y - [c.sub.i] -
[p.sub.i][f.sub.i]}. The second holds when the fine is so large that the
individual chooses a level of expenditure that leads to bankruptcy if
convicted: [c.sub.i](f) = [c.sup.**.sub.i]=argmax{(y - [c.sub.i])(1 -
[p.sub.i])}. The two solutions are characterized by
(1) -[[p'.sub.i]([c.sup.*.sub.i])f + 1] = 0 and
(2) -[p'.sub.i]([c.sup.**.sub.i])[y -
[c.sup.**.sub.i]]-[1-[p.sub.i]([c.sup.**.sub.i])] = 0
and are shown in Figure 1.
When the individual is bankrupted if convicted, both the expected
marginal cost and the expected marginal gain from defense expenditure
are reduced. As we show in the Appendix (in the proof of Proposition 1),
the former effect outweighs the latter, so that expenditure when the
individual chooses to be bankrupt if convicted is greater than if he
does not: [c.sup.**.sub.i] > [c.sup.*.sub.i].
For low enough fines the accused chooses a level of defense
expenditure [c.sup.*.sub.i] that leaves positive income even if
convicted. His maximized expected utility conditional on being accused
is then [v.sup.n.sub.i](f) = y - [c.sup.*.sub.i](f) -
[p.sub.i]([c.sup.*.sub.i](f))f and is decreasing with the fine. For a
large enough fine the accused will prefer to choose a level of defense
expenditure [c.sup.**.sub.i] that bankrupts him if convicted. His
maximized expected utility in this case is [v.sup.b.sub.i] = [1 -
[p.sub.i]([c.sup.**.sub.i])](y - [c.sup.**.sub.i]), which does not vary
with the fine. As we show in the Appendix (in the proof of Proposition
1), there is a level of the fine [F.sub.i] at which the accused is
indifferent between [c.sup.*.sub.i]([F.sub.i]) and [c.sup.**.sub.i]. To
avoid needless complications we assume that indifferent individuals
choose [c.sup.*.sub.i]([F.sub.i]). Defense expenditure is at first
increasing in f, jumps upward at [F.sub.i], and is constant thereafter.
Expected utility is continuous in the fine, though defense expenditure
is not.
Although the accused is indifferent between [c.sup.*.sub.i](F) and
[c.sup.**.sub.i] when f = [F.sub.i] and would be bankrupt if convicted
if he chose [c.sup.**.sub.i], the accused is not bankrupt if he chooses
[c.sup.*.sub.i](F). Let [c.sub.i] be the defense expenditure that just
bankrupts him: [c.sub.i] = y - [F.sub.i]. Substituting [F.sub.i] =
[p.sub.i] ([c.sub.i])[F.sub.i] + [1 - [p.sub.i]([c.sub.i])][F.sub.i] and
rearranging, we see that if he chose this level of expenditure he would
have y - [c.sub.i] -[p.sub.i]([c.sub.i])[F.sub.i] = [1 -
[p.sub.i]([c.sub.i])] (y - [c.sub.i]). As inspection of Figure 1 shows,
this must occur where [c.sub.i] > [c.sup.*.sub.i] ([F.sub.i]).
Hence, if convicted he must have strictly positive wealth at
[c.sup.*.sub.i]([F.sub.i]): y - [c.sup.*.sub.i]([F.sub.i]) - [F.sub.i]
> 0.
Summarizing, we have the following (proofs of propositions not
given in the text are in the Appendix).
PROPOSITION 1. There is a level of the fine [F.sub.i] for each type
of individual such that if f [less than or equal to] [F.sub.i] the
accused chooses a level of defense expenditure [c.sup.*.sub.i](f) that
does not lead to bankruptcy if convicted and if f > [F.sub.i] the
accused chooses a level of defense expenditure [c.sup.**.sub.i] that
does lead to bankruptcy if convicted. Privately optimal defense
expenditure [c.sub.i] (f) is increasing in the fine in the nonbankruptcy
case, discontinuous upward in the fine at [F.sub.i], and unaffected by
the fine in the bankruptcy case:
[c.sub.i](f) = 0, f [member of] [0, [f.sup.o.sub.i]],
= [c.sup.*.sub.i](f), f [member of] ([f.sup.o.sub.i], [F.sub.i]],
= [c.sup.**.sub.i] > [c.sup.*.sub.i]([F.sub.i]), f [member of]
([F.sub.i], [infinity]).
[c.sub.if] = [c.sup.*.sub.if](f) > 0, f [member of]
([f.sup.o.sub.i], [F.sub.i])
= 0, f [member of] ([F.sub.i], [infinity])
We assume that the legal system is not perverse in the sense that
the honest are more likely to be convicted than the dishonest when they
spend the same amount on defense. The nonperversity assumption is
(ii) [p.sub.1](c) > [p.sub.0](c).
It is less obvious whether defense expenditure has a larger or
smaller marginal effect for the honest or the dishonest. We could argue
that a good (high-cost) lawyer will make more difference when the
evidence against the accused is stronger (because he is guilty) so that
(iii) [p'.sub.1](c) < [p'.sub.0](c) < 0.
However, defense expenditure could have a greater marginal effect
for the innocent: [p'.sub.0](c) < [p'.sub.1](c) < 0. For
example, searching for witnesses who will testify that the accused was
elsewhere when the crime was committed may be less costly if he is
innocent than if he is guilty.
Using the first-order conditions it is straightforward to establish
the following.
PROPOSITION 2. For f > [f.sup.o.sub.1] dishonest accuseds spend
more on legal defense than honest accused if their defense expenditure
has a greater marginal effect (iii holds). For f [member of]
([f.sup.o.sub.i], [F.sub.1]) and for f > [F.sub.0] dishonest accuseds
spend less on legal defense than honest accused if their defense
expenditure has a smaller marginal effect.
Part (a) of Figure 2 illustrates the case in which defense
expenditure is more productive for the dishonest than the honest. In
part (b) defense expenditure is more productive for the honest.
If the marginal effect of defense expenditure is larger for honest
accused, Proposition 2 and the nonperversity assumption (ii) imply that
the honest have a smaller probability of conviction than the dishonest.
However, if the marginal effect of defense expenditure is greater for
the dishonest, they could spend sufficiently more on defense to offset
their disadvantage in having a higher conviction probability at given
levels of defense expenditure. Hence there could be a p probability
reversal: [p.sub.1]([c.sub.1](f)) < [p.sub.0]([c.sub.0](f)).
If the dishonest accused have a smaller conviction probability than
the honest, it is also possible that they have a smaller unconditional probability of being convicted: [q.sub.1][p.sub.1]([c.sub.1](f)) <
[q.sub.0][p.sub.0]([c.sub.0](f)). As we will see shortly, such a qp
probability reversal implies that when both honest and dishonest prefer
a level of defense expenditure that enables them to pay the fine if
convicted, increases in the fine will increase the amount of crime. We
will restrict attention to the more plausible case in which there is no
qp probability reversal and the dishonest have a greater unconditional
conviction probability than the honest:
(iv) 1 > [q.sub.1][p.sub.1]([c.sub.1](f)) >
[q.sub.0][p.sub.0]([c.sub.0](f)) > 0.
Deterrence policy is considerably affected by whether the honest or
the dishonest are the first to choose bankruptcy as the fine increases.
Accuseds prefer the optimal nonbankrupting expenditure as long as
[v.sup.n.sub.i](f) exceeds [v.sup.b.sub.i]. Increases in the fine reduce
[v.sup.n.sub.i] at the rate [p.sub.i]([c.sup.*.sub.i](f)) and have no
effect on [v.sup.b.sub.i]. Honest and dishonest have the same expected
utility from nonbankruptcy with a zero fine. With no probability
reversal [v.sup.n.sub.1] will fall faster than [v.sup.n.sub.0] as f
increases. However, this does not imply that the dishonest will be the
first to choose bankruptcy as f increases: their expected utility from
bankruptcy is smaller than that of honest accuseds. Although
[v.sup.n.sub.1] falls faster than [v.sup.n.sub.0], it must fall further
before the dishonest prefer bankruptcy.
It there is probability reversal, so that [v.sup.n.sub.1] falls
more slowly than [v.sup.n.sub.0] as f increases, the honest will choose
bankruptcy before the dishonest: [F.sub.0] < [F.sub.1]. The converse does not hold, so that if there is no probability reversal we cannot
conclude that the dishonest will choose bankruptcy before the honest.
The case in which the dishonest choose bankruptcy before the honest
seems more plausible and we will often make this assumption:
(v) [F.sub.1] < [F.sub.0].
Honesty versus Dishonesty
If honest, an individual has expected utility [V.sub.0]([c.sub.0])
= (1 - [q.sub.0])y + [q.sub.0][u.sub.0]([c.sub.0]); whereas a dishonest
individual has expected utility [V.sub.1]([c.sub.1]) = (1 - [q.sub.1])y
+ [q.sub.1][u.sub.1]([c.sub.1]) + b. The individual commits a crime if
and only if [V.sub.1] > [V.sub.0] or equivalently
(3) b > z([c.sub.0], [c.sub.1], f, y)
= (1 - [q.sub.0])y + [q.sub.0][u.sub.0]([c.sub.0]) - (1 -
[q.sub.1])y
- [q.sub.1][u.sub.1]([c.sub.1]).
Because the proportion of individuals choosing honesty is G(z) we
can define z as the amount of deterrence produced by the criminal
justice system.
When the dishonest choose bankruptcy if convicted at a lower fine
than the honest ([F.sub.1] < [F.sub.0]), we have
(4) z = [q.sub.1][[p.sub.1]f + [c.sup.*.sub.1]] -
[q.sub.0][[p.sub.0]f + [c.sup.*.sub.0], f [less than or equal
to][F.sub.1];
(5) = [q.sub.1][[p.sub.1]y + (1 - [p.sub.1])[c.sup.**.sub.1]] -
[q.sup.0][[p.sub.0]f + [c.sup.*.sub.0]],
[F.sub.1] < f [less than or equal to] [F.sub.0]; and
(6) = [q.sub.1][[p.sub.1]y + (1 - [p.sub.1])[c.sup.**.sub.1]]
- [q.sub.0][[p.sub.0]y + (1 - [p.sub.1])[c.sup.**.sub.0]],
[F.sub.0] < f.
When [F.sub.0] < [F.sub.1] the deterrence function has the same
form as (4) for f [member of](0, [F.sub.0]) and as (6) for f [member of]
([F.sub.1], [infinity]), but
(7) z = [q.sub.1][[p.sub.1]f + [c.sup.*.sub.1]] -
[q.sub.0][[p.sub.0]y+(1 - [p.sub.0])[c.sup.**.sub.0]], [F.sub.0] < f
[less than or equal to] [F.sub.1].
Examination of the deterrence function establishes the following.
PROPOSITION 3. Deterrence is a continuous function of the fine. If
the dishonest have a greater unconditional probability of conviction
than the honest (iv holds), then (a) if [F.sub.1] < [F.sub.0],
deterrence is increasing in the fine up to [F.sub.1]: dz/df =
[q.sub.1][p.sub.1] - [q.sub.0][p.sub.0] > 0, decreasing over the
range ([F.sub.1], [F.sub.0]): dz/df = -[q.sub.0][p.sub.0] < 0, and
constant thereafter; (b) if [F.sub.0] < [F.sub.1], deterrence is
increasing in the fine up to [F.sub.1] and constant thereafter.
Figure 3 illustrates. In part (a), where [F.sub.1] < [F.sub.0],
increases in the fine to [F.sub.1] make crooks and honest individuals
worse off, even though they respond by increasing their defense
expenditure. The crooks suffer a larger fall in expected utility and so
more individuals choose to be honest. Over the range [[F.sub.1],
[F.sub.0]], crooks are unaffected by increases in the fine because they
are bankrupted if found guilty, whereas honest individuals are made
worse off. Hence the gain from crime compared to honesty increases. With
a fine large enough to make all types of convicted accused prefer
bankruptcy if convicted, further increases in the fine have no effect on
the expected utility of either crooks or honest individuals.
Figure 3(b) shows the case where [F.sub.0] < [F.sub.1]. The
expected utility of the dishonest falls faster than that of the honest
up to [F.sub.0], so deterrence increases. Once the honest have chosen to
be bankrupt if convicted, increases in the fine only affect the
dishonest, so that the fine has a greater marginal deterrence effect and
the deterrence function is kinked upward at [F.sub.0]. Once both groups
prefer bankruptcy when convicted, further increases in fine have no
additional deterrent effect.
Type I and II Errors and Deterrence
It is well known (Miceli, 1991) that the existence of type I and
type Illegal errors weakens deterrence because the possibility of
wrongful arrest and conviction reduces the expected utility from being
honest and the possibility of escaping punishment increases the expected
utility from dishonesty. The implications of type I and II errors are
less straightforward once legal defense expenditure is allowed for.
The accuseds' ability to spend money to reduce their
conviction probability when arrested increases their expected utility
compared with no expenditure: [V.sub.i]([c.sub.i](f)) > [V.sub.i](0).
What matters for deterrence is the difference between the expected
utilities of honest and dishonest individuals. The fact that
[V.sub.i]([c.sub.i](f)) > [V.sub.i](0) implies nothing about whether
[V.sub.0]([c.sub.0](f)) - [V.sub.1]([c.sub.1](f))is greater or less than
[V.sub.0] (0) - [V.sub.1] (0). However if there are no type I errors, so
that only the dishonest engage in defense expenditure that increases
their expected utility, defense expenditure must reduce deterrence. We
have the following.
PROPOSITION 4. In the presence of type I and II errors, permitting
defense expenditure by accused individuals may increase or reduce the
amount of crime: z([c.sub.0](f), [c.sub.1](f),f) may be less than or
greater than z(0, 0, f). If there are no type I errors
([q.sub.0][p.sub.0] = 0) permitting legal defense expenditure reduces
deterrence.
III. WELFARE MAXIMIZING DETERRENCE
Efficient Fine
The public sector cost of deterrence activities is the cost of
policing less the expected receipts from fines and is covered by lumpsum
taxes T imposed elsewhere in the economy. We assume in effect that we
are concerned with deterrence in a small area or sector whose
potentially dishonest population is small in relation to the total
population of the economy. Hence changes in T resulting from changes in
this sector have a negligible effect on the tax bills of the population
in the sector. The assumption enables us to ignore the potential
complications that would result from changes in T leading to changes in
the critical levels [F.sub.i] at which accused would prefer bankruptcy
if convicted.
To make our results comparable with the deterrence literature we
initially assume an efficiency-oriented welfare function that is the
unweighted sum of the expected utilities of honest and dishonest
individuals and the taxpayers:
(8) W = W([c.sub.0](f), [c.sub.1](f),
z([c.sub.0](f), [c.sub.1](f),f),f)
=[[integral].sup.z.sub.0] [V.sub.0]dG +
[[integral].sup.[infinity].sub.z][[V.sub.1] - h]dG - T
= y + [[integral].sup.[infinity].sub.z](b - h)dG - m -
G(z)[q.sub.0][c.sub.0]
- [1 - G(z)][q.sub.1][c.sub.1],
where z(*) is defined by (3) and m is the fixed level of policing
expenditures. Notice that the social consequences of legal defense, as
opposed to its private consequences, are solely determined by its impact
on deterrence and by its cost.
We assume that the planner cannot observe whether an individual is
honest or not, nor can she observe the level of any individual's
defense expenditure. We suppose initially that her only policy
instrument is the fine (5) and can establish (see the Appendix) the
following.
PROPOSITION 5. Assume that the dishonest have a greater probability
of conviction than the honest (iv). The efficient fine always leaves
dishonest individuals with positive wealth if convicted: [f.sup.*] [less
than or equal to] [F.sub.1]. If [F.sub.1] < [F.sub.0] both honest
individuals and dishonest individuals have positive wealth if convicted.
Although, as we noted, deterrence is a kinked function of the fine
at [F.sub.1] and [F.sub.0] and that defense expenditure jumps at these
points, the derivative of the welfare function with respect to the fine
exists and is continuous except at [F.sub.0] and [F.sub.1]. We can
therefore obtain some intuition about the result by
examining
(9) dW/df = [W.sub.z][z.sub.f] + [SIGMA][W.sub.ci][c.sub.if]
= [(h - z) + ([q.sub.1][c.sub.1] - [q.sub.0]
[c.sub.0])]g(z)[z.sub.f]
-[q.sub.0]G[c.sub.0f]-[q.sub.1](1 - G)[c.sub.1f].
Suppose that the dishonest choose bankruptcy before the honest
([F.sub.1] < [F.sub.0]). Increases in the fine have no effect on
defense expenditures for an individual of type i if the fine exceeds
[F.sub.i] (see Proposition 1). Hence for f > [F.sub.0] > [F.sub.1]
the last two terms in (9) are zero and so is the first term, because
deterrence is not affected. Consequently, the marginal value of the fine
is zero for f > [F.sub.0] > [F.sub.1].
For [F.sub.0] > f > [F.sub.1] the first term in (9) is
negative because deterrence is reduced in this range (Proposition 3).
Because [c.sub.0f] is positive and [c.sub.1f] is zero, the marginal
value of the fine is negative for this range.
For [F.sub.0] > [F.sub.1] > f increases in the fine do
increase deterrence so that the first term in (9) is positive. The
second and third terms are negative, so an interior efficient fine is
possible in this range.
In the perhaps less plausible case in which the honest are bankrupt
before the dishonest ([F.sub.0] < [F.sub.1]) deterrence is increasing
with the fine up to f = [F.sub.1] and constant thereafter. Because
defense costs increase with f it is again possible that the efficient
fine does not maximize deterrence and leaves either the dishonest or
both the honest and dishonest with positive wealth if convicted.
These arguments suggest that the welfare-maximizing fine cannot
exceed [F.sub.1] and that there are two types of efficient fine
depending on the relative marginal importance of the fine's impact
on deterrence and in reducing defense expenditure: (6)
* Critical fine: [f.sup.*] = [F.sub.1]. If deterrence has a high
marginal value relative to the marginal cost of defense expenditure,
then our assumption that all dishonest individuals choose
[c.sup.*.sub.1] at [F.sub.1] means deterrence can be increased to its
maximal extent without triggering a jump in defense expenditure.
Dishonest accuseds are not bankrupted if not convicted. Honest
individuals are also left with positive wealth or bankrupt if convicted
depending on whether [F.sub.1] < [F.sub.0] or [F.sub.1] >
[F.sub.0].
* Interior fine: [f.sup.*] < [F.sub.1]. If increases in the fine
lead to an increase in defense expenditure that is large relative to the
change in deterrence, there will be a interior solution in which the
efficient fine is less than the critical [F.sub.1] and the dishonest are
not bankrupted by the fine. If [F.sub.1] < [F.sub.0] the honest will
have positive wealth if convicted but may be bankrupt if [F.sub.1] >
[F.sub.0].
In models with type I and II errors but no defense expenditures the
bankruptcy constraint is just y [less than or equal to] f for both
honest and dishonest accuseds. Because there is no qp probability
reversal in such models, increases in the fine always increase
deterrence and do not increase socially costly defense expenditures.
Hence the efficient fine is as large as possible: [f.sup.*] = y. Thus it
is defense costs, rather than the presence of type I and type II errors,
that potentially overturn the Becker (1968) maximal fine result when
there are no direct costs of type I and II errors. Although the fine is
a deterrent, it is also a stimulus to socially wasteful expenditure by
the accused.
Does punishment fit the crime in the sense that the dishonest face
an expected penalty equal to the direct social harm they impose: z = h?
In the standard Becker (1968) model the punishment is less than the harm
because policing has a positive marginal cost. The marginal value of
deterrence is positive at the optimum because deterrence has a positive
marginal cost. In our model, where there are defense costs and legal
error, the marginal social benefit from deterring an additional criminal
will also be positive at the optimum. The marginal social benefit from
deterrence is the net social cost of the marginal crime (h - b) = (h -
z) plus the expected increase in expenditure of criminals compared to
honest individuals ([q.sub.1][c.sub.1] - [q.sub.0][c.sub.0]). When (iii)
holds, so that criminals spend more on defense than honest accused, the
latter term is positive. Hence a positive marginal social value of
deterrence does not necessarily imply that the benefit to the marginal
criminal (z) is less than the soci al harm from the crime. Criminals may
face expected penalties that exceed the direct harm they inflict.
Justice-Oriented Welfare Function
The unweighted utilitarian or efficiency orientated welfare
function (8) is standard but does not reflect the common view that there
are additional social costs from a justice system that fails to convict all dishonest accused and convicts some honest individuals.
Suppose that each case of wrongful conviction has a social cost of
[k.sub.0](f), where [k'.sub.0](f) > 0 reflects the judgment that
the social harm from wrongful conviction is greater the greater the
punishment imposed (Ehrlich, 1982; Miceli, 1991). Each dishonest person
who is not punished, either by not being tried or by wrongful acquitted,
has a social cost of [k.sub.1]. (7) The justice-oriented social welfare
function is
(10) W = W - G[q.sub.0][p.sub.0][k.sub.0] - (1 - G)
x (1 - [q.sub.1][p.sub.1])[k.sub.1].
The weights [k.sub.0], [k.sub.1] are the marginal social cost of a
single wrongful conviction and a single guilty person escaping
punishment. The judgment that it is better that n guilty persons go free
than that one innocent person be convicted can be interpreted as fixing
the relative weights [k.sub.0] = n[k.sub.1].
The effect of a marginal increase in deterrence on welfare is
[W.sub.z] [W.sub.z] - {[p.sub.0][q.sub.0][k.sub.0] - [(1 -
[q.sub.1])
+ [q.sub.1](1 - [p.sub.1])][k.sub.1]}g(z)
=[W.sub.z] - Kg(z).
The term K is the marginal injustice cost of increasing deterrence
and could be positive or negative. With increased deterrence more
individuals choose to be honest, so that the number of mistaken
convictions of the honest increases, thereby increasing the amount of
injustice. However, the number of dishonest individuals decreases, so
that there are fewer who escape punishment, thereby reducing injustice
from type II errors. The greater the relative weight [k.sub.0] on type I
errors the more likely is it that increasing deterrence has a positive
injustice cost.
The marginal social effect of an increase in the fine is
(11) [W.sub.f] = [W.sub.f] - K g [z.sub.f] -
G[q.sub.0][p.sub.0][k'.sub.0]
-G[q.sub.0][p'.sub.0][c.sub.0f][k.sub.0] + (1 -
G)[q.sub.1][p'.sub.1][c.sub.1f][k.sub.1].
A concern for injustice may tend to increase or decrease the
optimal fine. The second term in (11) is negative if the marginal
injustice cost of deterrence K is positive. The third effect tends to
reduce the optimal fine (Ehrlich, 1982; Miceli, 1991), because increases
in the fine raise the social cost of type I errors. The last two terms
reflect the impact of the fine in increasing accuseds' defense
expenditures and hence reducing their probability of conviction. The
fourth term is the social benefit from reduction in the probability of
conviction of the honest is a social benefit and works to increase the
optimal fine. The last term is the social cost from increasing the
probability of acquittal of the dishonest and works to reduce the
optimal fine.
A greater concern for type I errors, reflected in an increase in
[k.sub.0], has an ambiguous effect on the optimal fine. Increases in
[k.sub.0] increase the marginal injustice cost of deterrence K and
thereby tend to reduce the optimal fine because increases in the fine
increase the number of type I errors because there are more honest
individuals. But increases in [k.sub.0] mean that there is a greater
value in defense expenditure of accused innocents and increases in the
fine increase that expenditure. Hence [k.sub.0] has offsetting effects
on the second and fourth terms in (11).
IV. REGULATING DEFENSE COSTS
In this section we consider various policies that can be adopted to
affect the defense expenditure of accused. We start by temporarily
assuming that it is possible to identify crooks and honest individuals
and to control their defense expenditure. The aim of the assumption is
to further investigate the welfare implications of defense expenditure
as a background to choice of policy under more realistic circumstances.
Social Value of Legal Defense Expenditure
When the defense expenditures of honest and dishonest individuals
are directly controlled the welfare function is written as W ([c.sub.0],
[c.sub.1], z([c.sub.0], [c.sub.1], f), f). The marginal social values of
defense expenditure are
(12) dW / d[c.sub.0] = [W.sub.z] [z.sub.[c.sub.0]] -- K g
[z.sub.[c.sub.0]] + [W.sub.[c.sub.0]] --
G[q.sub.0][p'.sub.0][k.sub.0];
(13) dW / d[c.sub.1] = [W.sub.z][z.sub.[c.sub.1]] -- K g
[z.sub.[c.sub.1]] + [W.sub.[c.sub.1]] + (1 -
G)[q.sub.1][p'.sub.1][k.sub.1].
At the privately optimal defense expenditures the first and second
terms in both (12) and (13) are zero. z is the difference between
expected utilities that are maximized by private choice of defense
expenditures and so [z.sub.[c.sub.1]] = 0. The third term in both
expressions is negative and reflects the direct cost of defense
expenditure.
An increase in defense expenditure for honest individuals beyond
the private optimum has two offsetting effects on welfare: the cost of
defense expenditure and the reduction in the conviction probability of
honest individuals. If f [less than or equal to] [F.sub.0], the
first-order condition (1) on [c.sup.*.sub.i](f) implies that (12) is (f
- [k.sub.0])G[q.sub.0][p'.sub.0]. Hence the private choice of legal
expenditure when innocent will be too small from a social point of view
if the marginal social cost of convicting an innocent person is greater
than the marginal gain from the reduction in taxation implied by the
increased fine revenue: [k.sub.0] > f. This seems a plausible value
judgment.
The marginal social value of [c.sub.1] at [c.sub.1] =
[c.sup.*.sub.1](f) is negative because in addition to its cost,
additional defense expenditure increases the chance of wrongful
acquittal. But the first best socially optimal value of [c.sub.1] may
not be zero. It may be possible to set it at a high level, above
[c.sup.*.sub.1](f), such that the dishonest individual has a lower
expected utility than if [c.sub.1] was zero. For example, setting
[c.sub.1] = y leaves the dishonest individual with zero wealth whether
convicted or acquitted and a lower expected utility than if [c.sub.1] =
0. The resulting increase in deterrence may be worth the additional
defense costs.
PROPOSITION 6. The choices of defense expenditure by honest and
dishonest accused are not first-best socially optimal. If f [less than
or equal to] [F.sub.0] and there is a social cost of mistaken
convictions, the honest individual's choice of legal defense
expenditure is too small if and only if [k.sub.0] > f. The first-best
expenditure by dishonest accuseds is either zero or greater than the
privately optimal level.
Limit on Private Legal Defense Expenditure
The regulator's information is limited: she observes the
results of the trial, but she does not observe b, nor individual defense
expenditures, nor whether an individual committed a crime. The
regulator's feasible policies, in addition to the fine, include a
limit on private defense expenditure by accuseds, and a ban on private
defense expenditures coupled with a provision of the same level of
defense expenditure to all accused (a public defender system). (8)
When the regulator can fix the maximum amount c that accuseds can
spend on their defense, the marginal social value of c is
(14) dW / dc = [W.sub.z][z.sub.c] - K g [z.sub.c] +
[SIGMA][W.sub.[c.sub.i]]d[c.sub.i]/dc
-[k.sub.0]G[q.sub.0][p'.sub.0]d[c.sub.0]/dc + [k.sub.1](1 - G) x
[q.sub.1][p'.sub.1]d[c.sub.1]/dc.
Suppose that (iii) and (v) hold so that the honest spend less on
defense and choose bankruptcy at a higher fine than the dishonest.
Setting c [greater than or equal to] [c.sup.**.sub.1] does not constrain the choices of either type of accused. A reduction in c in the range c
[euro] ([c.sup.*.sub.1](f), [c.sup.**.sub.1]) does not affect the
expected utility of the honest or their defense expenditure. Reducing c
to [c.sup.*.sub.0](f) reduces the defense expenditure of the dishonest
and makes them worse off. Hence deterrence increases and defense
expenditure falls. If there is no social cost to type I and II errors,
(14) reduces to the first and third terms and welfare would be increased
by tightening the constraint on defense expenditure in this range.
With no cost to type I or II errors the regulator can restrict
attention to c [less than or equal to] [c.sup.*.sub.0] (f) and honest
and dishonest accused will choose [c.sub.0] = [c.sub.1] = c. Deterrence
in this range is
(15) z = [q.sub.1][[p.sub.1](c)f + c] - [q.sub.0][[p.sub.0](c)f +
c].
We have assumed (iii) that the defense expenditure of the dishonest
has a greater marginal product, so deterrence is decreasing in c
(16) [z.sub.c]=[q.sub.1][[p.sub.1](c)f + 1] -
[q.sub.0][[p'.sub.0](c)f + 1] < 0
by (i) and the fact that c [less than or equal to]
[c.sup.*.sub.0](f) < [c.sup.*.sub.1](f). Hence (14) is negative for c
[less than or equal to] [c.sup.*.sub.0](f) and the efficient value of c
is zero. Note also that deterrence is increasing in f: [z.sub.f] =
[q.sub.1][p.sub.1](c) - [q.sub.0][p.sub.0](c) > 0 by (i) and (ii),
and so with no social costs of type I and II errors the optimal fine
should be maximal.
If there is only a cost to type II errors the previous arguments
hold a fortiori because now increased deterrence is of even more value
and the third term in (14) is - K g [z.sub.c] = [k.sub.1] (1 -
[q.sub.1][p.sub.1])g[z.sub.c] < 0.
We saw in the previous section that the privately optimal defense
expenditure was not first-best efficient. We have now established that
the private, unregulated equilibrium expenditure is also not second-best efficient: a complete ban on private defense expenditure yields a higher
welfare than the unregulated market equilibrium. Indeed any binding
restriction on private legal defense expenditure increases welfare
compared with the market equilibrium when there are no costs of type I
errors.
When there is a cost to type I errors the optimal value of c may be
positive and could even be greater than [c.sup.*.sub.0](f). First, with
a cost to type I errors K may be positive, so that there is a cost to
increased deterrence because the number of honest individuals, who are
subjected to type I errors, is increased. Second, relaxing the
constraint on defense expenditures in the range c <
[c.sup.*.sub.0](f) reduces the probability of conviction of honest
accuseds. In the range c [euro] ([c.sup.*.sub.1](f), [c.sup.**.sub.1]),
the second factor does not operate but the first does. Hence it is
possible that a concern for type I errors could lead to a constraint on
defense expenditure that binds only for the dishonest. The same type of
argument we used in the previous section shows that optimal fine may
also be less than maximal when there is a cost to type I errors.
PROPOSITION 7. If defense is more productive for the dishonest
(iii), they choose bankruptcy before the honest and (v), and there is no
cost of type I error ([k.sub.0]=0), then the efficient limit on defense
expenditure is zero: [c.sup.*] = 0 and the efficient fine is maximal:
[f.sup.*] = y. When there is a cost of type I error ([k.sub.0] > 0),
the optimal limit on defense expenditure may be positive and may only
constrain the dishonest, and the optimal fine may be less than maximal.
Public Defender System
Under a public defender system all accused are provided with the
same amount of legal defense [c.sub.0] = [c.sub.1] = c, which is paid
for by taxation rather than by the accused. Accordingly we now constrain
policy by y - f [greater than or equal to] 0. Deterrence is
(17) z = [[q.sub.1][p.sub.1](c) - [q.sub.0][p.sub.0](c)]f,
and increases in c reduce deterrence: [z.sub.c] < 0.
The marginal welfare from public expenditure on legal defense is
[W.sub.z][z.sub.c] + [SIGMA] [W.sub.[c.sub.]] - K g [z.sub.c] -
[k.sub.0]G[q.sub.0][p'.sub.0] + [k.sub.1] (1 -
G)[q.sub.1][p'.sub.1],
which is very similar to (14). Analogous arguments to those in
previous sections establish the following.
PROPOSITION 8. If the cost of convicting the innocent is zero, the
efficient amount of publicly funded legal defense expenditure is zero,
and the efficient fine is maximal. When the cost of type I error is
positive ([k.sub.0] > 0) the optimal amount of publicly funded legal
defense expenditure may be positive and may be greater than the amount
chosen by honest defendants, and the optimal fine may be less than
maximal.
V. CONCLUSIONS
When legal defense expenditure reduces the probability of
conviction and there is no direct concern with the cost of legal errors,
policies are influenced by their implications for deterrence and the
level of defense costs. If the only policy variable is the fine, its
impact on defense expenditure means that it is never efficient to set it
high enough that convicted dishonest accused are bankrupt. If defense
expenditures can be directly regulated the efficient regime has no
defense expenditure and a fine that is maximal, just bankrupting all
accused, both the honest and the dishonest.
Some of these policies would likely be challenged as
unconstitutional or grossly unfair to the accused. One way of reflecting
such concerns is to suppose that there is a direct social cost of legal
errors. Because defense expenditure by the honest reduces the
probability that the innocent are wrongly convicted and punished, it can
be optimal to permit such expenditure. Direct error costs can also
justify the provision of defense from public funds. Furthermore, optimal
fines could be less than maximal when there is concern about the
conviction of innocent individuals.
APPENDIX
Proof of Proposition 1
We assume that the productivity of defense expenditure ensures that
there is an [f.sup.o.sub.i] such that when f > [f.sup.o.sub.i], the
optimal level of defense expenditure is positive and characterized by
the first-order conditions (1) and (2), depending on whether the accused
is bankrupted by the optimal defense expenditure or not.
a. Denote the maximized value of y - [c.sub.1], -
[p.sub.i]([c.sub.i])f by [v.sup.n.sub.i](f) and of [1 -
[p.sub.i]([c.sub.i])](y - [c.sub.i]) by [v.sup.b.sub.i].
[v.sup.n.sub.i](f) is monotonically decreasing in f and satisfies
[v.sup.n.sub.i](0) > [v.sup.b.sub.i] >
[v.sup.n.sub.i]([infinity]). Hence there exists a unique [F.sub.i]
satisfying [v.sup.n.sub.i]([F.sub.i]) = y - [c.sup.*.sub.i] ([F.sub.i])
- [p.sub.i]([c.sup.*.sub.i]([F.sub.i]))[F.sub.i] = (1 -
p([c.sup.**.sub.i]))(y - [c.sup.**.sub.i]) = [v.sup.b.sub.i].
b. Because (1) characterizes the choice of defense expenditure if
and only if the individual is not bankrupt at [c.sup.*.sub.i] we have -1
+ [p.sub.i]([c.sup.**.sub.i]) - [p'.sub.i]([c.sup.**.sub.i])[y -
[c.sup.**.sub.i]] = 0 = -1 - [p'.sub.i]([c.sup.*.sub.i])f [less
than or equal to] -1 - [p'.sub.i]([c.sup.*.sub.i])[y -
[c.sup.*.sub.i]], which implies 0 < -
[p'.sub.i]([c.sup.**.sub.i])[y - [c.sup.**.sub.i] < -
[p'.sub.i]([c.sup.*.sub.i])[y - [c.sup.*.sub.i]]. Suppose that
[c.sup.**.sub.i] [less than or equal to] [c.sup.*.sub.i]. Then
-[p'.sub.i]([c.sup.**.sub.i]). [greater than or equal to]
-[p'.sub.i]([c.sup.*]) from the convexity of [p.sub.i](c) and y -
[c.sup.**.sub.i] [greater than or equal to] y - [c.sup.*.sub.i]. Because
y - [c.sup.**.sub.i] [greater than or equal to] 0 we have a
contradiction and have established that [c.sup.*.sub.i](f) <
[c.sup.**.sub.i] for all f [member of] (0, [F.sub.i]].
c. From the implicit function theorem, we know that the sign of
[c.sup.*.sub.if](f) and [c.sup.**.sub.if](f) are given by
[[partial].sup.2][u.sub.i]/[partial][c.sub.i][partial]f. The comparative
static results are immediate from (1) and (2).
d. From the definition of [F.sub.i] and the fact that [1 -
[p.sub.i]([c.sub.i])](y-[c.sub.i]) is maximised at [c.sup.**.sub.i],
y-[c.sup.*.sub.i]-[p.sub.i]([c.sup.*.sub.i])[F.sub.i] = [1-
[p.sub.i]([c.sup.**.sub.i])](y-[c.sup.**.sub.i]) >
[1-[p.sub.i]([c.sup.*.sub.i])](y-[c.sup.*.sub.i]), and subtracting the
right-hand expression from the left-hand expression we get
[p.sub.i]([c.sup.*.sub.i]([F.sub.i]))[y-[c.sup.*.sub.i]([F.sub.i])-[F
.sub.i]] > 0 and so y-[c.sup.*.sub.i]([F.sub.i]) > [F.sub.i]. The
accused is not bankrupt if convicted when he chooses
[c.sup.*.sub.i]([F.sub.i]).
e. Similarly, [1-[p.sub.i]([c.sup.**.sub.i])](y-[c.sup.**.sub.i]) =
y - [c.sup.*.sub.i]-[p.sub.i]([c.sup.*.sub.i])[F.sub.i] > y -
[p.sub.i]([c.sup.**.sub.i])[F.sub.i] - [c.sup.**.sub.i] implies
[p.sub.i]([c.sup.*.sub.i])[F.sub.i] > [p.sub.i]([c.sup.**.sub.i])
[F.sub.i] > [p.sub.i]([c.sup.*.sub.i])(y-[c.sup.**.sub.i]) and so
[F.sub.i] > y - [c.sup.**.sub.i]. The dishonest accused is bankrupt
when convicted at f [greater than or equal to][F.sub.i] when he chooses
[c.sup.**.sub.i].
Proof of Proposition 3
Deterrence is continuous because up to a positive constant, it is
equal to the difference between the value of two maximized functions
[V.sub.0]([c.sub.0]), [V.sub.1]([c.sub.1]), each of which are continuous
in the fine. Using the envelope theorem, the expression [z.sub.f] is
immediate.
Proof of Proposition 5
The welfare function W(f) = Z(f)) = W([c.sub.0](f), [c.sub.1](f),
Z(f))=W([c.sub.0](f),[c.sub.1](f),z([c.sub.0](f),[c.sub.1](f),f)) has a
continuous total derivative with respect to f everywhere except at
[F.sub.1] and [F.sub.0]. The sign of dW/df is discussed in the text.
a. Consider the case in which [F.sub.1] < [F.sub.0]. Then for
[member of] > 0, W([F.sub.0]) - W([F.sub.0] + [epsilon]) = [1 -
G(Z([F.sub.0]))][[c.sup.**.sub.0] - [c.sup.*.sub.0]([F.sub.0])] > 0,
because Z([F.sub.0] = [epsilon]) = Z([F.sub.0]), [c.sub.1]([F.sub.0] +
[epsilon]) = [c.sub.1]([F.sub.0]), and [c.sub.0]([F.sub.0] + [epsilon])
= [c.sup.**.sub.0] > [c.sub.0]([F.sub.0]) =
[c.sup.*.sub.0]([F.sub.0]). For f [member of] ([F.sub.1],[F.sub.0]), W
(f) is decreasing in f because deterrence is decreasing, honest
individuals' defense costs are increasing, and dishonest
individuals' defense costs are constant. Because W([F.sub.1]) -
[lim.sub.z[right arrow]0] W([F.sub.1] + [epsilon]) = G(Z([F.sub.1]))
[[c.sup.**.sub.1] - [c.sup.*.sub.1] ([F.sub.1])] > 0, the optimal
fine cannot exceed [F.sub.1].
b. When [F.sub.1] > [F.sub.0] and [epsilon] > 0, W([F.sub.1])
- W ([F.sub.1] + [epsilon]) =
G(Z([F.sub.1]))[[c.sup.**.sub.1]-[c.sup.*.sub.1]([F.sub.1])] > 0,
because Z([F.sub.1] = [epsilon]) = Z([F.sub.1]), [c.sub.1]([F.sub.1] +
[epsilon]) = [c.sup.**.sub.1] > [c.sub.1] ([F.sub.1]) =
[c.sup.*.sub.1]([F.sub.1]), and [c.sub.0]([F.sub.0] + [epsilon]) =
[c.sup.**.sub.0]. Again, the optimal fine cannot exceed [F.sub.1].
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
[FIGURE 2 OMITTED]
[FIGURE 3 OMITTED]
TABLE 1
Notation
Variable Definition
h social harm from a crime
b private benefit from a crime
G(b) distribution function of benefits
from crime
y endowed income
[q.sub.0] probability that honest individuals
is arrested and charged
[q.sub.1] probability that dishonest individuals
is arrested and charged
[p.sub.0]([c.sub.0]) probability of conviction of honest
accused
[p.sub.1]([c.sub.1]) probability of conviction of honest
accused
[c.sub.i] legal defense expenditure of type
i = 0, 1 accused
f fine
[F.sub.i] fine that just induces type i accused
to choose [c.sub.i], which bankrupts
him if convicted
m policing costs
t tax rate on defense expenditure
[theta] compensation for acquitted accused
[k.sub.0] social cost per convicted honest person
[k.sub.1] social cost per acquitted dishonest
person
[lambda] social value of relaxing bankruptcy
constraint on effective fine
T lump-sum tax
(1.) Throughout the article we use the terms honest and dishonest
as synonyms for innocent and guilty, respectively.
(2.) It is just about possible to interpret the statement within
the standard efficiency framework as an empirical judgment about the
marginal rate of substitution between type I and II errors. Such an
interpretation does not seem compatible with the terms of the debate in
the voluminous literature discussing the number of guilty persons whose
wrongful acquittal is equivalent to a single wrongful conviction
(Volokh, 1997).
(3.) The assumption that individuals have the same income and that
all count equally in our welfare function means that we are not
concerned with distributional issues, such as the optimal means of
providing subsidies for legal defense expenditure to the poor (Dnes and
Rickman, 1998).
(4.) The offense may yield purely nonmonetary benefits.
Alternatively, it may yield monetary benefits that have been spent or
distributed to shareholders by the time the accused is convicted. A
similar assumption is made in Malik (1990) and Polinsky and Shavell
(2000).
(5.) Increasing policing expenditures m will increase the arrest
rates [q.sub.i]. Because type I and II errors and defense expenditures
have no new implications for efficient policing expenditure, we simplify
by assuming that m is fixed. The standard maximal fine result is driven
by the fact that the fine is a costless instrument that can be
substituted for costly policing expenditure. However, our demonstration
that the optimal fine does not bankrupt dishonest accused does not
depend on the fixity of m. If m was a policy variable it would be
efficiently chosen when [(h - z) + ([q.sub.1] [c.sub.1] -
[q.sub.0][c.sub.0])]g(z)[z.sub.m] - 1 = 0, implying dW/df =
-dm/[df\.sub.z] - [q.sub.0] G[c.sub.0f] - [q.sub.1] (1 - G)[c.sub.1f],
so that dW/df need not be positive even though increases in the fine
permit reductions in costly policing.
(6.) If any of the dishonest accused choose [c.sup.**.sub.1] rather
than [c.sup.*.sub.1]([F.sub.1]) when f = [F.sub.1] the welfare problem
may have no solution. Welfare would be always be greater at some fine
slightly less than [F.sub.1] than at [F.sub.1] because of the upward
jump in defense expenditure by accuseds who choose [c.sup.**.sub.1] at
[F.sub.1].
(7.) The social harm from failure to punish the dishonest could
plausibly depend on the cost of their crime, as in Miceli (1991), but
this is not relevant in the current model, where we assume that all
crimes impose the same direct social cost h.
(8.) In a longer version of the article we consider the possibility
of taxing defense costs and introducing compensation for acquitted
individuals and reach analogous results (Gravelle and Garoupa, 2000).
REFERENCES
Becker, G. "Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach."
Journal of Political Economy, 76, 1968, 169-217.
Dnes, A., and N. Rickman. "Contracts for Legal Aid: An
Economic Analysis of the UK Government's Proposals." European
Journal of Law and Economics, 6, 1998, 247-66.
Ehrlich, I. "The Optimum Enforcement of Laws and Concept of
Justice: A Positive Analysis." International Review of Law and
Economics, 2, 1982, 3-27.
Garoupa, N. "The Theory of Optimal Enforcement of Law."
Journal of Economic Surveys, 11, 1997, 267-95.
Garoupa, N., and H. Gravelle. "Does Efficient Deterrence
Require that the Wealthy Should Be Able to Buy Justice?" Discussion
Paper 00/07, Department of Economics and Related Studies, University of
York, 2000.
Gravelle, H., and N. Garoupa. "Crime, Punishment and the
Accused's Defence Expenditure." Discussion Paper 00/08,
Department of Economics and Related Studies, University of York, 2000.
Kaplow, L., and S. Shavell. "Legal Advice about Acts Already
Committed." International Review of Law and Economics, 10, 1990,
149-59.
Lott, J. R. "Should the Wealthy Be Able to Buy Justice?"
Journal of Political Economy, 95, 1987, 1307-16.
Malik, A. S. "Avoidance, Screening and Optimum
Enforcement." Rand Journal of Economics, 21, 1990, 341-63.
Miceli, T. J. "Optimal Criminal Procedure: Fairness and
Deterrence." International Review of Law and Economics, 11, 1991,
3-10.
Png, I. P. L. "Optimal Subsidies and Damages in the Presence
of Judicial Error." International Review of Law and Economics, 6,
1986, 101-5.
Polinsky, A. M., and S. Shavell. "The Optimal Trade-off
between the Probability and Magnitude of Fines." American Economic
Review, 69, 1979, 880-91.
-----. "A Note on Optimal Fines when Wealth Varies among
Individuals." American Economic Review, 81, 1991, 618-21.
-----. "The Economic Theory of Public Enforcement of
Law." Journal of Economic Literature, 38, 2000, 45-76.
Volokh, A. "n Guilty Men." University of Pennsylvania Law
Review, 146, 1997, 173-211.
Nuno Garoupa *
* We are grateful for helpful comments from the editor, two
referees, Mitch Polinsky, Jennifer Reinganum, Ricard Torres, and
participants in the 14th Annual meeting of the European Law and
Economics Association, Barcelona, September 1997.
Gravelle: Professor, Centre for Health Economics, University of
York, Heslington, York YO10 5DD, UK. Phone 44-1904-432663, Fax
44-1904-432700, E-mail
[email protected]
Garoupa: Associate Professor, Department d'Economia i Empresa,
Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Ramon Trias Fargas 25-27, 08005 Barcelona,
Spain. Phone 34-93-542 2639, Fax 34-93-542 1746, E-mail
[email protected]