On the internal contradictions of the law of one price.
McChesney, Fred S. ; Shughart, William F. II ; Haddock, David D. 等
As stated originally, the venerable law of one price succinctly
describes long-run equilibrium in a perfectly competitive market. The
law was later amended, defining a market as the geographic area within
which the same thing sells for the same price at the same time,
allowance being made for transportation costs. Modified in that way, the
law has two plausible interpretations. By one interpretation, every
production site is a market. By the other, prices in fact do not differ
by transportation costs. The transportation-cost amendment thus
introduces internal contradictions that render the revised law of one
price either useless or wrong. (JEL D40, L10)
A market, according to the masters, is the
area within which the price of a commodity tends
to uniformity, allowance being made for
transportation costs. That is, two places are in
the same market for a good if the prices at the two
places differ by transportation costs. (Stigler,
1987, 77)
Economic terms seem to pass in their historical
development through a series of stages which,
without pretension to rigidness, may be described
as follows: first, no definition is given, but it is
assumed that every one has a sufficiently clear idea
of the subject to make a formal definition
unnecessary; second, a definition is attempted
and a number of exceptional forms are noted;
third, with the further increase of data, the relative
importance of the various forms changes, confusion
in discussion is introduced, logomachy takes
the place of constructive investigation; fourth, a
complete classification of the forms embraced
under the original term is made, and problems are
investigated with reference to these classes. The
bewildering vagueness of economic theory is
largely due to the fact that the terms used are
in all of these stages of development. (Moore
1906, 211)
I. INTRODUCTION
Delineating the boundaries of markets engaged economists'
attention early on. Many product attributes are important to consumers,
but price is an objectively measurable margin along which rivalry is
sharply engaged. Market prices transmit information about changing
demand and supply conditions to buyers and sellers, and widening
price--cost margins signal profit opportunities to which alert
entrepreneurs respond. Price consequently has held center stage in
economists' attempts to define markets.
Augustin Cournot (1927, 51), for instance, wrote that a market is
"the entire territory of which the parts are so united by the
relations of unrestricted commerce that prices take the same level
throughout with ease and rapidity." Alfred Marshall (1930, 325)
supplied a similar definition in his celebrated declaration that
"the more nearly perfect a market is, the stronger is the tendency
for the same price to be paid for the same thing at the same time in all
parts of the market." More recently, Joseph Stiglitz (1993, 19)
summarized what he called the law of the single price, stating that,
"under this law, there is a uniform price in the market, and price
differences are quickly eliminated by arbitrage." (1)
Marshall (1930, 325) introduced an important qualification,
however, when he observed that, "but of course, if the market is
large, allowance must be made for the expense of delivering the goods to
different purchasers; each of whom must be supposed to pay in addition
to the market price a special charge on account of delivery." That
qualification subsequently found its way into Stigler's price
theory textbook, quoted in the epigraph. Intentionally or not, the law
of one price was thereby converted into a law of different prices. Other
economists subsequently added transaction costs and information costs to
the list of caveats, culminating in a multiplicity of prices
nevertheless claimed to be consistent with the law of one price.
Economics has few laws. Perhaps the most famous is the (first) law
of demand. It truly is a law, because price and quantity demanded are
inversely related, ceteris paribus, at all times and in all places. But
the amended law of one price is different. It holds--except (more often)
when it doesn't.
The modern empirical literature abounds with apparent violations of
the law. Elzinga and Hogarty (1978), for example, report that in 1975
the f.o.b. (free on board) price of bituminous coal was $27.03 per ton
in eastern Kentucky, but $13.75 per ton in western Kentucky. That same
year, the nationwide average charge for shipping coal via rail was $5
per ton. Inclusive of freight charges a ton of comparable coal sold two
years later for $18 in New York, $38 in New Jersey, $23 in Illinois, and
$34 in Wisconsin. Shrives (1978) was able to explain less than
two-thirds of the observed variation in bituminous coal prices with a
model containing 25 independent variables. Baye and Morgan (2001)
document sizable and persistent differences in the prices quoted over
the Internet for a seemingly homogeneous product (a 0-point, 30-year,
conventional fixed-rate mortgage for a hypothetical New Jersey
homebuyer). Asplund and Friberg (2001) likewise find that a given good
in a given duty-free shop often sells at different prices quoted in
different currencies, contrary to what the law of one price would have
predicted.
This article argues that the numerous pricing anomalies interpreted
by some economists as evidence that the law of one price does not
hold--and by others as reason for adding new ceteris paribus conditions
to save the law from accumulating empirical contradiction--reveal two
basic problems: Modified to include transportation costs, the law is
internally contradictory, and, furthermore, economists have tended to
apply it overbroadly in attempts to force actual markets to conform to abstract models of pure competition. Stated in its received
Marshall-Stigler form wherein transportation cost is the only
complication allowed in the market for an otherwise homogeneous good,
the very concept of a law of one price is fatally flawed. If the amended
law is incoherent even in this simplest case, it remains incoherent in
more complicated situations where additional market frictions are taken
into account. Introducing other complications merely contributes
auxiliary reasons why the law fails to hold in the original,
transportation-cost-only case.
The next section supplies analytical background by discussing the
assumptions under which there is a strong "tendency for the same
price to be paid for the same thing at the same time in all parts of the
market." Section III then notes that the amended law of one price
actually has two plausible interpretations. Does the law mean that a
market can be defined endogenously as the territory wherein prices
differ only by transportation costs? Or does it mean that a market, once
exogenously defined by some other criterion, will exhibit prices that
differ only by transportation costs?
Under the first interpretation of the law every production site is
a market. Construing the law of one price that way adds more confusion
than clarity to the definition of economic markets. Under the second
interpretation, the amended law is simply wrong: Prices in fact do not
differ by transportation costs. Wherever located, all sellers in a
market must charge the same price for the same product. The owners of
favorably positioned firms may enjoy Ricardian rents in this case, but
they are not thereby able to charge different prices.
It is useful to emphasize at the outset what this article is not
about. The connection to the practice of defining markets for antitrust
purposes is tangential at best. It is true, of course, that the
antitrust laws require enforcers and courts to determine the set of
products--and the extent of the geographic area in which the sellers of
those products compete--that will be deemed relevant when assessing the
impact of mergers and other business practices on economic performance.
Depending on how narrowly or broadly a market is defined, a firm does or
does not have market power, or a proposed business consolidation does or
does not go beyond the market-share thresholds that trigger antitrust
concerns. Market definition gradually has become an art (if not a
science) because of its role in the enforcement of competition law. But
the law of one price evolved separately from--indeed, was stated well
before--the rise of modern antitrust. Nor is the article primarily an
exercise in the history of economic thought. Although the law of one
price surely originated in the work of the "masters,"
including Cournot, Jevons, and Marshall, it remains a standard part of
the canon of price theory today. (2)
In the end, the law of one price has become for modern economists
an analog of the Ptolemaic system of the universe for medieval
astronomers. Rather than abandon the notion that the sun moved around
Earth, astronomers such as Tycho Brahe invented new and increasingly
fabulous theories to account for inconveniently inconsistent
observations, in that way hoping to shore up the model of a geocentric universe. All else equal, however, science prefers simpler explanations
to complex ones, and in time Ptolemaic notions were abandoned altogether
in favor of the Copernican heliocentric model. Increasingly encumbered with addenda and asterisks to make it seem to work, the law of one
price, meant originally as a description of the tendency for prices in a
market to equilibrate, likewise has been gutted of analytical content.
Stripped of interpretative errors and irrelevant complications, the
law of one price, properly understood, is seen to be neither more nor
less useful than the abstract competitive model on which it was founded.
Being a direct implication of that model, the law of one price states
that, once a market has been defined, prices will tend to converge so
that, in the long run, the same price will prevail in all parts of the
market. Plainly, however, at any point in time a tendency toward price
equilibration and a single price are not the same thing.
II. THE EXTENT OF THE MARKET
In the textbook model of pure competition, with all its simplifying
assumptions (including product homogeneity, perfect information, and
perfect resource mobility) all sellers necessarily charge the same
price. All production and consumption decisions implicitly take place at
a single point in economic space-time. There are no locational
advantages or any other differences across products or firms that matter
to buyers and that would cause the demand curves perceived by sellers to
slope downward. Under these conditions, any price differences that
emerge are quickly eliminated by arbitrage as the market moves toward
long-run equilibrium.
Clearly, a useful economic model does not conclude that the
products making up a naturally occurring market must sell at the same
price. The goods and services that consumers treat as substitutes
frequently are different physically. Even if this is not the case,
sellers differ as to location, promptness of delivery, their willingness
to extend credit, offering and honoring warranties, repairing or
replacing defective items, and so on. Buyers likewise differ as to
location, willingness to accept delivery, promptness of payment,
creditworthiness, penchant for returning items, desire for pre-and
postsale services, and so on. Prices will adjust to reflect differences
in the many nonprice attributes of transactions and, indeed, as
emphasized by Stigler (1968), variations in these nonprice attributes
are competitive substitutes for variations in price. (3)
However, as modified to incorporate transportation costs, the law
of one price is a simpler proposition. The theory received from those
masters to whom Stigler refers abstracts from the myriad strategies
sellers employ to distinguish their products from those offered by
rivals. (4) In eschewing realism for tractability, and by downplaying
the dynamic forces that in Marshall's (1930, 333) colorful language
cause prices to be "tossed hither and thither like a shuttlecock,
as one side or the other gets the better in the 'higgling and
bargaining' of the market," the amended law of one price is a
statement about the boundaries of markets wherein products are
differentiated along a single dimension, namely, the locations of
sellers. All other complicating factors possibly influencing prices
implicitly are held constant.
In this stylized world of static, long-run competitive equilibrium,
two sellers are said to be in the same market if the prices they charge
differ only by the cost of transportation between their separate
locations. In that world, sellers quote prices f.o.b.: The price paid by
any buyer is equal to the price at the seller's plant (the
"mill price") plus the cost of shipping the product to him or
her. Buyers are free to make their own transportation arrangements (and
pay for them). Alternatively, if the seller offers the option of
delivering the product to the buyer's location, the cost of
shipping is invoiced separately. Under these assumptions, Stigler (1987,
77) writes, "the price of a commodity 'tends to
uniformity' for one reason: the buyers at point B refuse to pay
more than the price at point A plus the cost of transportation, and the
buyers at point A act similarly. Or the sellers act in this
manner."
In other words, according to Stigler, the market price is p + t,
the mill price plus the unit cost of transportation, and locations A and
B supposedly are both "in" the same market because the prices
at the two points differ only by the cost of transportation between
them. Marshall (1930, 325) supplies a particularly apt example of the
logic underlying the law of one price:
The whole of the Western World may, in a
sense, be regarded as one market for many kinds
of stock exchange securities, for the more valuable
metals, and to a less[er] extent for wool and cotton
and even wheat; proper allowance being made for
the expenses of transport, in which may be
included taxes levied by any customs houses
through which the goods have to pass. (emphasis
added)
The amended law of one price, although usually expressed in terms
of sellers' transportation costs, does have one other
embellishment: "mobility of customers [is] ... sufficient to ensure
the tendency to uniformity in price, allowance being made for
transportation costs of consumers." Buyers, as Stigler (1987, 78)
observed, sometimes face lower transportation costs than sellers:
"A cotton farmer will have a relatively small area in which he will
sell his crop; the buyers may deal in every cotton-picking state."
Fundamentally, however, recognizing that buyers are sometimes cheaper
transporters than sellers are does not alter the thrust of the analysis.
Two places are in the same market if the prices at the two places differ
only by the cost of transportation between them, regardless of the
identity of the low-cost shipper.
But is that proposition useful or even true?
III. THE FUNDAMENTAL ECONOMICS OF THE LAW OF ONE PRICE
An initial problem attends analysis of the amended law of one
price: As normally stated, the law has at least two interpretations.
Does the law mean that a market is definable as a location in which
price is set by the marginal costs of production, differing only by
transportation costs, ceteris paribus? Or does the law mean that once a
market has been identified, prices therein predictably will be uniform,
allowing for transportation costs? In other words, does equality of
prices (but for transportation costs) define a market endogenously? Or
does the delineation of the market, however it is defined exogenously,
imply uniform prices (but for transportation costs)?
As will be discussed in this section, those propositions are not
logically the same. Nor is the economic evaluation of the two plausible
interpretations the same. Our analysis confines attention to the ceteris
paribus conditions contemplated by the Marshall-Stigler statement of the
law of one price: Reference to prices differing only by transportation
costs means that all else (e.g., product quality) is held constant.
Equality of Price Defines a Market
Let us interpret the modified law of one price, first, as stating
that one can define places as belonging in a single market by their
having the same price but for transportation cost. All firms by
assumption have equal production costs. However, transportation costs to
particular customers differ, being a function of distance from one of a
firm's plants.
Consider the situation portrayed in Figure 1. Let two firms, 1 and
2, operate plants at points of local resource supplies, points A and B
respectively. Spatially, A and B are located at distances OA and OB,
measured from arbitrary point O. (For simplicity, there is no firm
closer to point O than firm A, nor are there any customers to the left
of point A or to the right of point B.) Each firm charges the f.o.b.
price that covers its marginal production costs (OP), to which is added
unit transportation cost ([t.sub.1] for firm 1 and [t.sub.2] for firm
2). (5) Thus, purchasers at points A and B will pay prices OP.
Purchasers located away from points A and B would have to pay prices
increasing with distance as shown along OP + [t.sub.1] or OP +
[t.sub.2].
To turn to the question of interest, are points A and B in the same
market? Under the first interpretation of the amended law of one price,
the answer is no. Out to point M, all buyers will purchase from firm 1,
the one producing at point A. But beyond OM, prices paid will no longer
be firm 1's f.o.b. price plus transportation costs. Buyers at those
distances will prefer to buy from firm 2. Point M is the boundary
between two markets. Firm 1 serves all of the customers in the space up
to M; firm 2 serves all of the customers beyond M.
If this first interpretation is what the Marshall-Stigler version
of the law of one price means, it is economically problematic for two
reasons. First, more obviously, the law of one price effectively means
that every plant comprises its own spatial (geographic) market. Area AM
is one market; area MB defines a separate market. Within each of these
markets, there is not one price but a multitude of prices tailored to
individual customers' locations. Customers in AM pay firm 1's
f.o.b. price plus the cost of transportation from point A. Customers in
MB pay firm 2's f.o.b. price plus its transportation costs. Only at
location M are both firms in the same market in the sense that they
charge the same price, OP + [t.sub.1] = OP + [t.sub.2]. (6)
This leads to the paradoxical result that apart from the market
boundary at M, firms are in the same market only if they are located
atop one another. The moment plants diverge spatially, under the
modified law of one price they each define a separate market if they
charge f.o.b. prices. In making every firm a market, the
transportation-cost amendment surely creates a definition of market that
will seem of little operational use to most economists and likely
confuse most noneconomists. Why use the term market if its meaning is
identical to that of firm or plant? Or if market refers to multiple
firms at the same point, why make special note of transportation costs?
There is a second problem with this first interpretation of the
amended law of one price. In Figure 1, would firms in fact charge prices
equal to marginal production cost (OP) plus transportation cost, as the
law of one price says they would? Seemingly not, absent further
assumptions. Out to point M, firm 1 can charge all of its customers up
to some maximum price just [alpha] below firm 2's production and
transportation costs. Likewise, beyond point M, firm 2 can charge all of
its customers a maximum price just A less than firm 1's production
and transportation costs. (7)
Again to quote Stigler (1987, 77), the law of one price works
"for one reason: the buyers at point B refuse to pay more than the
price at point A plus transportation, and the buyers at A act
similarly." But this Stiglerian notion of price formation assumes
that only buyers matter in the setting of price within a market. If
every firm is a market, then sellers by definition have some market
power that must also be taken into account. In Figure 1, the sellers at
A and B have no incentive to offer prices calibrated solely to their own
production and transportation costs. (8) Only at M, where both firms are
in the same market, need the price that one firm charges be tightly
constrained by the other firm. At that single point the price might
actually equal the sum of marginal production and transportation costs.
(9)
In other words, if under the amended law of one price each
spatially separated plant defines a market, that plant has a locational
monopoly. It therefore will not charge a price equal to its production
and transportation costs, but rather a higher price limited by the other
firm's production and transportation costs. Ironically, if there
truly was a law by which price varies within a market only by
transportation cost, firm 1's price would be a negative function of
distance between points A and M. The highest prices would be charged at
sites most isolated from competition from firm 2's plant at point B
and the lowest prices at the market boundary. (10)
In short, if the amended law of one price is interpreted to mean
that a market is defined by the area surrounding a firm (plant) where
prices are the same but for transportation cost, two implications
follow. First, every firm (plant) is a market, essentially stripping the
term market of any useful meaning. Second, although price in the market
is indeed a function of distance under this interpretation, the limit
price does not vary positively with own-firm distance, as the
transportation-cost-modified law of one price suggests. Rather, it
varies positively with distance from other firms (i.e., price is
inversely related to own-firm distance)--the very opposite of what the
amended law predicts. (11) For firm 1, prices are higher at A (near the
plant) than at M (further away). The same relationship between limit
price and distance would hold for firm 2.
A Market Implies Price Equality
The key implication of the foregoing section is that for a firm to
charge a price at a point dictated by its own marginal production cost
plus transportation, there must be other firms competing with it at that
point, holding price equal to marginal cost (including both production
and transportation costs). So, if one observes different firms selling
in the same place, each constraining other firms' ability to raise
price above marginal production and transportation costs, that place
would seem to define a market as the term is popularly used.
But in this locale (point M) where multiple firms compete, if there
is one price, is that single price equal to firms' production plus
transportation cost, as the law of one price claims? Consider the
situation depicted in Figure 2. A set of firms located at point A is
willing to supply any quantity of output up to [q.sub.A] units at price
p. Another firm (or set of firms) located at point B has a higher supply
price of p + t for sales in A.
Given multiple firms at A, if the demand for the product were D,
the market price would be p and firms located at B would not be in the
market. (12) The law of one price would apply, but only because all
firms selling in A were located in A, as discussed in the previous
section. But by hypothesis, firms located at both A and B have been
observed selling in A. So, the demand for the product must be D'.
For firms at B to sell in A, the market price must be p + t. (13)
Under the law of one price, all of the firms in the market charge the
same price. But if so, some of them earn inframarginal rents owing to their more favorable location, because they charge prices exceeding
their production and transportation costs. Locational rents are earned
on sales to customers at A by local firms who would have been willing to
supply them at price p, but actually can get p + t. (14) Once again,
price is determined not by a firm's own transportation costs but as
limited by the transportation costs of the more remote firm(s), just the
opposite of what the amended law of one price posits.
The point is that in either set of circumstances, the price is not
one that "tends to uniformity, allowance being made for
transportation costs." Two places are not in the same market
"if the prices at the two places differ by transportation
costs." For two places to be in the same market, it is necessary
that the prices at the two places be the same, period. (15) If the
sellers of an otherwise homogeneous product differ only as to location,
they must charge the same price if they compete in one market. If they
do not charge the same price, they are in the same market only if the
boundary line between two other markets is defined as "the
market." (16)
Reevaluating the Law of One Price
Recognizing that (unlike the law of demand, for example) the law of
one price does not necessarily hold always and everywhere, economists
have for a long time been ambivalent about it. As noted, the law
abstracts from any number of nonlocational factors, owing to which a
buyer might not patronize a seller who is closest to him. Promptness of
delivery, reputation, willingness to extend credit, warranty policies,
and willingness to repair or replace defective items all may differ
among firms. Other things are not always equal.
More recently, though, economists have offered more Coasean reasons
why, ceteris paribus, the law of one price might not hold. Failures of
the law have been ascribed to information or transaction-cost factors,
for example. On the demand side, echoing Stigler (1961), Stiglitz (1993,
19) discusses imperfect information and buyer search costs as reasons
why, "in fact, many markets are marked by noticeable differences in
prices." (17) Building on the work of Varian (1980), in which
consumers are either informed or uninformed about the distribution of
prices and sellers randomly conduct sales, Baye and Morgan (2001, 2002)
propose a model of Internet pricing wherein a gatekeeper charges fees to
firms wanting to advertise prices and to consumers wanting to access
that information. Prices for homogeneous goods are shown to be dispersed
in equilibrium under those assumptions. Asplund and Friberg (2001) rely
on "costs of arbitrage" to explain why the prices of the same
goods quoted in different currencies at the same duty-free shops fail to
converge in apparent violation of the law of one price. Similarly,
Goldberg and Knetter (1997, 1270) conclude that "deviations in the
law of one price" observed in otherwise integrated international
markets "appear to be largely a result of third-degree price
discrimination."
On the supply side, Carlton and Perloff (2000, 365) write,
"Because prices reflect costs in competition, economists expect
purchasers to pay for FOB pricing and for actual freight under
competition." But in fact, Carlton and Perloff continue, firms
often do not charge for shipping, using uniform delivered pricing (a
single freight charge, regardless of distance) instead "because it
is simple and saves on administrative costs.... It appears that uniform
delivered pricing is often followed as long as the variation in freight
charges among customers is 10 percent or less." (18) Or, as Hay
(1999, 196) writes, the law may not hold at any given point because
temporally the system is in disequilibrium: "While it is true that
in a 'perfect' market prices for identical products tend
toward equality, there is generally enough friction in the system that
the process does not work instantly."
In short, some modern economists who have considered the law of one
price do not seem to regard it as falsifiable. When price does not equal
marginal production plus transportation costs, dei ex machinis, such as
asymmetric or costly information, price discrimination, transaction
costs or disequilibrium, are invoked to save the law. Being consistent
with any observed pattern of prices, the law of one price predicts
nothing.
Recognizing that as Varian (1980, 651) notes, "most retail
markets are ... characterized by a rather large degree of price
dispersion," instead of attempting to rescue the law of one price
from empirical contradiction, others have been prompted to recommend
jettisoning it altogether: Again quoting Varian (1980), "economists
have belatedly come to recognize that the 'law of one price'
is no law at all." Routinely observed phenomena, such as f.o.b.
pricing, the willingness to absorb freight to sell to distant customers
and the "high degree of overlap and cross-shipping found among
spatially dispersed producers," all "obviate the
usefulness" of the law, according to Elzinga and Hogarty (1973,
51).
The analysis here illustrates that neither of these reactions is
justified. As stated originally, the law of one price was never meant to
accommodate frictions like transaction and information costs. Nor was it
expected to hold in situations where underlying demand and cost
conditions are in flux, except to point toward the equilibrium to which
prices would tend to converge. Indeed, internal contradictions are
introduced even in the starkest case where transportation cost is the
only complication allowed. In that simplest case, the most
straightforward interpretation of the amended law of one price implies
that every firm or plant is a separate market, that prices within that
market vary by customers' locations and that prices in one market
may well be a negative function of transportation costs from adjacent
markets, not a positive function of transportation costs for the
particular market itself. Interpreted correctly, the law of one price is
a law of one price, not a law of one price adjusted for differences in
transportation costs. In other words, under this alternative
interpretation transportation costs generate Ricardian rents for
favorably located sellers but do not result in price differences within
a market.
There is, in short, a law of one price, but it is not the one
stated by Alfred Marshall or George Stigler. The transportation-cost
qualification they appended erroneously added an element of spatial
product differentiation to a proposition that was meant to apply only to
perfectly competitive markets, wherein knowledge is perfect and goods
are costlessly mobile. The original meaning can be restored by defining
a market as Cournot did: "The entire territory of which the parts
are so united by the relations of unrestricted commerce that prices take
the same level throughout with ease and rapidity." Jevons's
law of indifference, as quoted in Edgeworth (1987, 786) is equally apt:
"In the same open market, at any one moment, there cannot be two
prices for the same kind of article." Alternatively, one can define
a market in amended Stiglerian terms as the area within which the price
of a commodity tends to uniformity. That is, two places are in the same
market for a good if the prices at the two places are the same.
IV. CONCLUSIONS AND IMPLICATIONS
The foregoing analysis demonstrates that, encumbered with its
modern transportation-cost proviso, the law of one price is incoherent.
It cannot therefore be rescued by amending it further to control for
other complications of the real world.
The law of one price restated by the masters, as Stigler refers to
them, is a more subtle proposition than those writing about it have
grasped. Errors of interpretation have been multiplied by failing to be
clear about what the transportation-cost amendment implies. If it means
that price equality defines a market, then the law is of no use, except
in that small minority of instances in which transportation cost is
essentially zero: Every production site is a market, robbing the latter
term of any relevance. It is also wrong. Price does not necessarily vary
positively with a producer's own transportation costs; the upper
limit on price varies positively with other producers'
transportation costs.
Alternatively, if the amended law means that a market (however
defined) will exhibit prices that are equal but for spatially dispersed
firms' own transportation costs, the law again is incorrect. It is
not true, as Stigler (1987, 77) asserts, that "two places are in
the same market for a good if the prices at the two places differ by
transportation costs." Rather, any number of plants can compete in
any given market place as long as each quotes the same price, though
they may or may not compete in other marketplaces. Under the usual
simplifying assumptions, all other things equal, as spatially separated
firms face important transportation costs, the number of places in which
they compete will diminish. Within a market, however, it is only the
marginal producer's transportation costs that matter. Corn shipped
to town from distant locations, as Adam Smith long ago recognized, sells
at the same price as corn shipped from nearby farms, whose owners
thereby benefit.
Stripped of interpretive errors, the law of one price must prevail.
It identifies a tendency for equilibration that follows as a logical
consequence of the assumptions of the model of pure competition and,
being an implication of it, is therefore neither more nor less useful
than that model. Qualifying the law of one price to make allowance for
transportation costs turns out to have been a mistake, subsequently
multiplied by trying to force it also to be consistent with other messy
properties of the real world, such as transaction and information costs.
That error has caused economists to treat the law of one price the same
way that Montana's drivers treated the 55 mph legal speed limit.
Most knew the law was on the books (or, more accurately, in the books),
but few observed it or expected others to.
(1.) In the same passage, Stiglitz refers to the law of the single
price as a "major principle of economics." Nearly a century
ago, Henry Moore listed what William Stanley Jevons called the law of
indifference--that "there is but one price for commodities of the
same quality in the same market"--as one of the hallmarks of (pure)
competition. Indeed,"--as quoted in Moore (1906, 214), Jevons
thought they were the same thing: "This law of indifference, in
fact, is but another name for the principle of competition which
underlies the whole mechanism of society." That was Francis
Edgeworth's interpretation as well. Edgeworth (1987, 786; emphasis
added) wrote that Jevons's law of indifference rests on
"certain ulterior grounds: namely, certain conditions of a perfect
market," one being that "monopolies should not exist." He
specifically ruled out the existence of market "power in virtue of
which a proprietor of a theater, in Germany for instance, can make a
different charge for the admission of soldiers and civilians, of men and
women." Edgeworth went on to say in the next sentence that
"the indivisibility of the articles dealt in appears to be another
circumstance which may counteract the law of indifference in some kinds
of market, where price is not regulated by the cost of production."
(2.) One of this journal's referees called the law of one
price the "mother of all economic laws." Nowadays the
proposition appears in a number of popular principles of economics texts
under the heading of international trade and finance. According to
Lipsey et al. (1999, 129), for example, "the law of one price
states that when a product that can be cheaply transported is traded
throughout the entire world, it will tend to have a single worldwide
price--the world price." Similarly, O'Sullivan and Sheffrin
(1998, G-6) state the law of one price as "the theory that goods
easily tradable across countries, should sell at the same price,
expressed in a common currency." Mankiw's (2004, 689)
discussion of purchasing power parity likewise is based on the law of
one price, which "asserts that a good must sell for the same price
in all locations."
(3.) Economists were aware of the analytical consequences of
product differentiation even before Jevons (1970, 137) wrote that price
differences for even otherwise identical products can "arise from
extraneous circumstances, such as the defective credit of the
purchasers, their imperfect knowledge of the market, and so on."
The multidimensional character of competition was in fact recognized as
early as 1844 in the writings of the great French engineer-economist
Jules Dupuit. See Ekelund (1970) for a summary of Dupuit's
contributions to the analysis of price discrimination and product
differentiation. Later, Edward Chamberlain (1962), Joan Robinson (1969),
and Nicholas Kaldor (1934), among others, explored the significance of
"gaps in the chain of substitutes" that might be used to
identify distinct market boundaries in common situations where, as the
last of these masters put it, "different producers are not selling
either 'identical' or "different' products, but
'more or less different products'--the demand confronting them
being neither completely sensitive nor completely unsensitive to the
prices charged by other producers."
(4.) Empirical applications of the law of one price have attempted
to grapple with complications like product differentiation by, for
example, testing whether the prices of two candidates for inclusion in
the same market tend to converge over time, as in Horowitz (1981), or
whether the prices of the candidates are sufficiently correlated to
warrant inclusion in the same market, as in Stigler and Sherwin (1985).
An alternative approach that avoids the problem of determining the price
at which a heterogeneous good sells is the "shipments test"
proposed by Elzinga and Hogarty (1973, 1978).
(5.) Firms 1 and 2 may have equal or different production and
transportation costs without any important points of the analysis here
being affected. Transportation costs need not be a linear function of
distance.
(6.) F.o.b. pricing thus creates a natural territorial monopoly for
each seller. Ironically, Stigler (1949) himself noted this point.
Alternatively, because the same price is paid for the same thing at the
same time only by the customers who are located a specific distance from
a seller's plant, perhaps every point on OP+ [t.sub.1] and OP+
[t.sub.2] is a separate "market."
(7.) The hypothetical price schedules shown in Figure 1 are maxima,
not necessarily the prices a profit-maximizing firm will charge. The
appropriate model here is one of limit-entry pricing, as in Modigliani
(1958). The limit price represents an upper bound, and the spatial set
of prices actually chosen within that constraint will correspond to the
quantities at which marginal revenue equals marginal cost. Depending on
cost and demand conditions, Greenhut and Greenhut (1975) show that those
prices might increase away from a plant at a rate faster than shipping
charges do, decrease at the same rate as shipping charges from the
competing plant fall, or more likely track some pattern in between. The
set of prices charged might induce a new firm to enter and locate
between points A and B, as in the standard Hotelling (1929) model. Entry
would cause the two existing firms to exit parts of their markets, but
would result in a firm's charging a price equal to its mill price
plus its own transportation cost only if the two firms were located atop
one another or at razor point M.
(8.) If the market is contestable, price will be held to potential
entrants' marginal cost. But except in the unlikely event of
building its plant atop that of an existing firm, the law of one price
would still dictate that the existing firm could charge a price more
than its own production plus transportation cost. The exercise of local
market power might likewise be constrained by buyers, if they can ship
more cheaply than sellers (see note 10).
(9.) No statement of the law of one price refers to the number of
firms, nor requires that the "one price" be a competitive one.
Strictly speaking, the law of one price is a positive proposition, but
it has obvious normative implications. Prices that just cover marginal
(production plus transportation) costs maximize output and wealth,
ceteris paribus. Obviously, in the absence of price discrimination, the
first interpretation of the law of one price depicted in Figure 1
implies just the opposite: higher prices, reduced output, and deadweight
welfare losses.
(10.) As already noted, buyers may be lower-cost shippers than
sellers. But that possibility does not change any of the analysis here.
Buyers closer to point A would still purchase only from firm 1, ceteris
paribus; buyers closer to B would still purchase only from firm 2. Each
firm operates in an isolated market over the relevant spatial distance.
Moreover, firm I would still charge a price based on the cost of
transportation from firm 2's market (that cost now determined by
the cost to buyers, not sellers, of transporting from point B); firm
2's prices would be determined according to buyers' cost of
transporting from firm 1's market.
(11.) To the extent that firm 2 faces lower transportation costs
than those shown in Figure 1, the size of its market relative to that of
firm 1 increases, and the prices that the two firms charge will fall. To
go one step further, to the extent that other firms face nonprohibitive
transportation costs, entry by other firms becomes possible, and their
production plus transportation costs will set an upper limit on prices
any firm can charge. In the limit, if transportation costs are zero
(e.g., securities or foreign exchange markets), then all firms wherever
located are competitors, but then any interest in transportation costs
as affecting price and defining markets disappears.
(12.) The only way firms at B can compete for sales at A would be
to absorb freight charges, that is, to quote prices to customers in A
that are less than the prices they charge in B plus transportation
costs. That strategy is characteristic of a delivered pricing system where all sellers designate A as a basing point and which would, at
least under some plausible circumstances, as shown by Haddock (1982) and
Carlton (1983), be consistent with procompetitive behavior. But it would
be inconsistent with the law of one price. The inclusion of
transportation costs in determinations of what should constitute
competitive pricing nevertheless is common in antitrust cases. Recently,
for example, a well-known economist testified on behalf of plaintiffs
that at tempts to orchestrate a collusive agreement should be inferred
from evidence that defendant sellers charged lower prices to distant
customers, "although the transportation costs of delivering to
those customers were higher." See A. A. Poultry Farms, Inc. v. Rose
Acre Farms, Inc., 881 F.2d 1396 (7th Cir. 1989) (Easterbrook, J.).
(13.) For a mathematical demonstration of this same point, showing
that in Nash equilibrium, Betrand duopolists selling products
differentiated only by location both charge prices of p* = c + t, where
c is the (constant) unit cost of production at the seller's plant
and t is the unit cost of transportation to customers uniformly
distributed along a line segment of length 1, see Mas-Colell et al.
(1995, 396-98). Mas-Colell et al. do not address the implications of
their result for market definition, however.
(14.) These locational rents may be quasi-rents, eventually
capitalized in input prices. In that case, all firms charge the same
price (p + t) and none earns above-normal returns. Such an equilibrium
is insightfully described by Adam Smith (1976, 366-67), the most
renowned of the masters:
The greater the number and revenue of the
inhabitants of a town, the more extensive is the
market which it affords to those of the country;
and the more extensive that market, it is always
the more advantageous to a greater number. The
corn which grows within a mile of the town, sells
there for the same price with that which comes
from twenty miles distance. But the price of the
latter must generally, not only pay the expence of
raising and bringing it to market, but afford too
the ordinary profits of agriculture to the farmer.
The proprietors and cultivators of the country,
therefore, which lies in the neighborhood of the
town, over and above the ordinary profits of
agriculture, gain, in the price of what they sell, the
whole value of the carriage of the like produce
that is brought from more distant parts, and they
save, besides, the whole value of the carriage in
the price of what they buy. Compare the
cultivation of the lands in the neighborhood of
any considerable town, with that of those which
lie at some distance from it, and you will easily
satisfy yourself how much the country is benefited
by the commerce of the town.
(15.) Price equality is a necessary but not sufficient condition
for defining a market. Though eggs may sell for $13 per case in Moscow
and $13 per case in Chicago, the two cities are probably not in the same
market.
(16.) Although the same price must prevail in all parts of a
properly defined economic market, one should not confuse the discussion
here with legal (antitrust) definition of markets. According to
[section] 1.1 of the Department of Justice/ Federal Trade Commission
Horizontal Merger Guidelines, promulgated on 2 April 1992, antitrust
market definition asks what alternatives are (or will become) available
to consumers if, hypothetically, one firm (or set of firms) attempts to
impose a "small but significant and nontransitory" increase in
price on them. Hence, for purposes of antitrust analysis, places that
are not currently "in" the market on our interpretation of the
law of one price might well be included when delineating the boundaries
of the area within which the forces of supply and demand interact to
constrain any attempt to exercise monopoly power; see, for example,
Landes and Posner (1981).
(17.) If the appropriate interpretation of the amended law is that
depicted in Figure 1, imperfect information might also lead to more than
one firm selling in a market where another firm, perfectly informed,
could price so as to maintain a total monopoly. Firm 1 may not know
perfectly what firm 2's costs are, and so choose a limit price that
is high enough to allow firm 2 to compete with firm 1.
(18.) Transportation typically occurs from shipping hubs (often
large cities) rather than from every single point on the spatial
continuum. In Illinois, producers in Joliet are some 50 miles closer to
Los Angeles than those in Waukegan. But these cities are more or less
equidistant from Chicago, the point where shipments to Los Angeles are
aggregated, and so face equivalent costs to ship to Los Angeles.
REFERENCES
Asplund, M., and R. Friberg."The Law of One Price in
Scandinavian Duty-Free Stores." American Economic Review, 91(4),
2001, 1072-83.
Baye, M. R., and J. Morgan. "Information Gatekeepers on the
Internet and the Competitiveness of Homogeneous Product Markets."
American Economic Review, 91(3), 2001, 454-74.
--. "Information Gatekeepers and Price Discrimination on the
Internet." Economics Letters, 76(1), 2002, 47-51.
Carlton, D. W. "A Reexamination of Delivered Pricing
Systems." Journal of Law and Economics, 26(1), 1983, 51-70.
Carlton, D. W., and J. M. Perloff. Modern Industrial Organization,
3rd ed. New York: Addison-Wesley, 2000.
Chamberlain, E. H. The Theory of Monopolistic Competition: A
Re-Orientation of the Theory of Value, 8th ed. 1933; Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1962.
Cournot, A. Researches into the Mathematical Principles of the
Theory of Wealth, translated by N. T. Bacon. 1838; New York: Macmillan,
1927.
Edgeworth, F. Y. "Indifference, Law of," in The New
Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, vol. 2, edited by J. Eatwell, M.
Milgate, and P. Newman. 1896; London: Macmillan and New York: Stockton
Press, 1987, 786-87.
Ekelund, R. B. Jr. "Price Discrimination and Product
Differentiation in Economic Theory: An Early Analysis." Quarterly
Journal of Economics, 84(2), 1970, 268-78.
Elzinga, K. G., and T. F. Hogarty. "The Problem of Geographic
Market Definition in Antimerger Suits." Antitrust Bulletin, 18(1),
1973, 45-81.
--. "The Problem of Geographic Market Delineation Revisited:
The Case of Coal." Antitrust Bulletin, 23(1), 1978, 1-18.
Goldberg, P. K., and M. M. Knetter. "Goods Prices and Exchange
Rates: What Have We Learned?" Journal of Economic Literature,
35(3), 1997, 1243-72.
Greenhut, J. G., and M. L. Greenhut. "Spatial Price
Discrimination, Competition, and Locational Effects." Economica,
42(168), 1975, 401-19.
Haddock, D. D. "Basing-Point Pricing: Competitive vs.
Collusive Theories." American Economic Review, 72(3), 1982,
289-306.
Hay, G. A. "Facilitating Practices: The Ethyl Case," in
The Antitrust Revolution: Economics, Competition, and Policy, 3rd ed.,
edited by J. E. Kwoka Jr. and L. J. White. New York and Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1999, 182-201.
Horowitz, I. "Market Definition in Antitrust Analysis: A
Regression-Based Approach." Southern Economic Journal, 48(1), 1981,
1-16.
Hotelling, H. "Stability in Competition." Economic
Journal, 34(153), 1929, 41-57. Reprinted in AEA Readings in Price
Theory, edited by G. J. Stigler and K. E. Boulding. Chicago: Richard D.
Irwin, 1952, 467-84.
Jevons, W. S. The Theory of Political Economy, edited by R. D. C.
Black. 1871; Baltimore: Penguin, 1970.
Kaldor, N. "Mrs. Robinson's 'Economics of Imperfect
Competition.'" Economica, 1(3), 1934, 335-41.
Landes, W. M., and R. A. Posner. "Market Power in Antitrust
Cases." Harvard Law Review, 94(3), 1981, 937-96.
Lipsey, R. G., P. N. Courant, and C. T. S. Ragan. Principles of
Microeconomics, 12th ed. Boston: Addison-Wesley, 1999.
Mankiw, N. G. Principles of Economies, 3rd ed. Mason, OH: Thomson
South-Western, 2004.
Marshall, A. Principles of Economies: An Introductory Volume, 8th
ed. 1890; London: Macmillan, 1930.
Mas-Colell, A., M. D. Whinston, and J. R. Green. Microeconomic Theory. New York: Oxford University Press, 1995.
Modigliani, F. "New Developments on the Oligopoly Front."
Journal of Political Economy, 66(3), 1958, 215-32.
Moore, H. L. "Paradoxes of Competition." Quarterly
Journal of Economics, 20(2), 1906, 211-30.
O'Sullivan, A., and S. M. Sheffrin. Microeconomics Principles
and Tools, 2nd ed. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1988.
Robinson, J. The Economics of Imperfect Competition, 2nd ed. 1933;
London: Macmillan, 1969.
Shrives, R. E. "Geographic Market Areas and Market Structure
in the Bituminous Coal Industry." Antitrust Bulletin, 23(3), 1978,
589-625.
Smith, A. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of
Nations, vol. 1. Glasgow Edition of the Works and Correspondence of Adam
Smith, edited by R. H. Campbell and A. S. Skinner with W. B. Todd. 1776;
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1976.
Stigler, G. J. The Theory of Price, 4th ed. 1942; New York:
Macmillan, 1987.
--. "A Theory of Delivered Price Systems." American
Economic Review, 39(6), 1949, 477-89.
--. "The Economics of Information." Journal of Political
Economy, 69(3), 1961, 213-25.
--. "Price and Nonprice Competition." Journal of
Political Economy, 76(1), 1968, 149-54.
Stigler, G. J., and R. A. Sherwin. "The Extent of the
Market." Journal of Law and Economics, 28(3), 1985, 555-85.
Stiglitz, J. E. "Information," in The Fortune
Encyclopedia of Economics, edited by D. R. Henderson. New York: Warner
Books, 1993, 16-21.
Varian, H. R. "A Model of Sales." American Economic
Review, 70(4), 1980, 651-59.
FRED S. McCHESNY, WILLIAM F. SHUGHART II, and DAVID D. HADDOCK *
* We benefited from discussions with William Breit, Kenneth
Elzinga, Barry Hirsch, David Laband, John Mayo, Russell Sobel, and
Robert Tollison and from the comments of Michael Reksulak and Hilary
Shughart. Helpful comments also were received in presentations at the
meeting of the Southern Economic Association in Tampa, Florida, and at
New York University's Colloquium on Market Institutions and
Economic Processes. The thoughtful suggestions of the editor and two
anonymous referees were of particular value in improving the article.
Thanks also to Michael Reksulak and Birsel Tavukcu for help with the
diagrams and to Lina Zhou for efficient research assistance. As is
customary, however, we accept full responsibility for any remaining
errors.
McChesney: Class of 1967/James B. Haddad Professor of Law and
Professor, Kellogg School of Management, Northwestern University, 357 E.
Chicago Avenue, Chicago, IL 60611. Phone 1-847-425-1134, Fax
1-847-328-4213, E-mail
[email protected]
Shughart: F. A. P. Barnard Distinguished Professor of Economics and
holder of the Robert M. Hearin Chair, Department of Economics,
University of Mississippi, P.O. Box 1848, University, MS 38677-1848.
Phone 1-662-915-7579, Fax 1-662-915-6943, E-mail
[email protected]
Haddock: Professor of Law and Professor of Economics, Northwestern
University, 3238 Arthur Andersen Hall, 2001 Sheridan Road, Evanston, IL
60208-2600. Phone 1-847-491-8225, Fax 1-847-491-7001, E-mail
[email protected]