On the social dimension of time and risk preferences: an experimental study.
Guth, Werner ; Levati, M. Vittoria ; Ploner, Matteo 等
I. INTRODUCTION
There is ample empirical evidence that people do not behave
rationally when rationality implies maximization of one's own
material rewards. To gain flexibility, economists have taken into
account nonlinear evaluation of material rewards (e.g., in the familiar
form of "utility of money" functions) as well as "social
utilities" including other-regarding concerns, like altruism as in
Andreoni and Miller (2002), inequality aversion as in Fehr and Schmidt
(1999) and Bolton and Ockenfels (2000), or quasi-maximin preferences as
in Charness and Rabin (2002). Undeniably, this provides a rich toolbox
for "neoclassical repair," which allows aligning rational
choice predictions with empirical data on decision behavior.
Nonetheless, this toolbox may be a curse (a Pandora's box) rather
than a blessing if, by combining the tools arbitrarily, everything can
be justified as rational. Some guidance on how risk attitudes, time
preferences, and other-regarding concerns are interrelated becomes,
therefore, necessary when we want to make sound behavioral predictions.
To derive theoretically the interrelation of risk and time
preferences over one's own and others' rewards, one could rely
on models of endogenous preference formation in the tradition, for
instance, of Guth and Yaari (1992). This would require knowing the
habitat in which our basic behavioral disposition to cooperation in
risky and dynamic endeavors has evolved. Rather than speculating on how
to model this scenario, we prefer to collect first empirical evidence so
as to learn the results of such possible preference evolution.
Except for a few attempts, (1) economic theory offers no idea of
whether risk aversion goes hand in hand with patience and
other-regarding concerns. Yet, such information may be crucial when
designing social institutions or deciding on a policy. (2) Consider a
cardinal utility function like
(1) [U.sub.i] = [summation over (x[member
of]X)]Prob{x}[f.sub.i]([r.sup.0.sub.i](x),[r.sup.1.sub.i](x),
[r.sup.0.sub.j](x),[r.sup.1.sub.j](x)),
where X is the set of random events x affecting the monetary
rewards [r.sup.1.sub.i] and [r.sup.t.sub.j] of two individuals i and j
in two successive periods t = 0 and t = 1. If the decision maker is not
spiteful, one can assume that [f.sub.i](*) reacts positively to all its
arguments. But how, and to what extent, can each argument be substituted
with another? We know that discounting allows to relate
[r.sup.1.sub.i](*) to [r.sup.0.sub.i](*), and other-regarding
preferences allow to relate [r.sup.t.sub.i](*) to [r.sup.t.sub.j](*).
But how does [r.sup.1.sub.j](*) relate to [r.sup.0.sub.i](*)? And if
[U.sub.i] is concave in [r.sup.t.sub.i](*), is it also concave in
[r.sup.t.sub.j](*)? Is somebody who is rather impatient when her own
reward is delayed also rather impatient when others' reward is
delayed? Rather than speculating about possible answers, we prefer to be
guided by data. Hence, we report on an experiment designed to explore
whether and how delaying outcomes, increasing their risk, and affecting
in this way also others are interrelated. (3)
All previous empirical studies have explored only the private
dimension of the interrelation between risk attitudes and time
preferences, that is, when risks and delays affect only one's own
rewards. The novelty of our study is that it relies on prospects with
social consequences where risk and delay pertain not only to own payoffs
(which is common) but also to others' payoffs.
Moreover, other-regarding concerns have mainly been modeled via
social utilities depending on the (expected) payoffs of other
individuals. To the best of our knowledge, the more subtle interrelation
of other-regarding concerns with attitudes to others' risks and
delays of rewards has been so far neglected. The Rawlsian philosophical
idea according to which "benevolent" individuals should locate
themselves in the shoes of others (see Rawls 1971) suggests
other-regarding agents to have attitudes toward risks and delays faced
by others similar to those they exhibit to risks and delays faced by
themselves. (4) Yet, not much has been done to test this conjecture.
The research presented in this article is a follow-up to the study
by Brennan et al. (forthcoming), who focus only on the relation between
other-regarding concerns and risk preferences when one's own and/or
another person's payoff is risky. Their major finding is that
behavior is influenced by the riskiness of own payoff but not by that of
the other's payoff: risk in what others get seems much less
important than own risk, even for those who are other-regarding. Here,
we move one step further by taking into account idiosyncratic private
and social time preferences, that is, when own and/or another
person's rewards are delayed.
In our experiment, each participant is asked to evaluate various
allocations, each of which assigns a payoff to herself and to another
participant. Payoffs can be immediate or delayed and certain or
stochastic. Since each of these four possibilities applies independently
to oneself as well as to the other, each participant must evaluate 16
different allocations. As elicitation procedure we use the
incentive-compatible random price mechanism introduced by Becker,
DeGroot, Marschak (1964). Given that the results of Brennan et al.
(forthcoming) reveal a significant difference in individual valuations
of risky prospects in the willingness-to-accept (but not in the
willingness-to-pay) treatment, we employ only the willingness-to-accept
mode. Thus, each participant is endowed with a prospect and asked to
state the minimum price at which she is willing to sell it. (5)
In the following Section II, the different prospects and the
experimental procedures are described in detail. The results of the
experiment are reported in Section III. Section IV concludes.
II. THE EXPERIMENT
Decision Task
To address our research questions, we rely on the random price
mechanism and elicit individual valuations of several prospects.
Valuations are defined as certainty equivalents in the form of
willingness to accept a randomly fixed amount of money to forgo a given
prospect. Each prospect allocates payoffs to both the decision maker and
another participant. More specifically, each member of the pair receives
either a sure payoff u or a lottery ticket U, assigning [U.bar] or
[bar.U] with 1/2 probability each. (6) The relation between the
different payoffs is given by 0 < [U.bar] <u< [bar.U] and EU =
([U.bar] + [bar.U])/2 = u. Furthermore, both the sure and the risky
payoff can be paid either immediately or after 3 mo.
We denote by [P.sup.j,[tau].sub.i,t] the prospect assigning reward
i to the decision maker at time t and reward j to her passive partner at
time [tau], where i, j = u, U and t, [tau] = 0, 3. Thus, we allow for 4
x 4 = 16 prospects as displayed in Table 1.
The decision maker is asked to submit a minimum selling price for
each prospect, b([P.sup.j,[tau].sub.i,t]), where 0 < [b.bar] [less
than or equal to] b([P.sup.j,[tau].sub.i,t]) [less than or equal to]
[bar.b]. Then a random draw from a uniform distribution determines an
offer p [member of] [[P.bar],[bar.p]] with 0 [less than or equal to]
[p.bar] [less than or equal to] [U.bar] < [U.bar] [less than or equal
to] [bar.p]. If p [greater than or equal to] b (*), the decision maker
sells the prospect and collects the random price p (that is paid
immediately after the experiment), while her partner receives nothing.
If p < b (*), the decision maker keeps the prospect, and she as well
as her partner obtain a realization of the payoffs specified by the
prospect. We preserve the riskiness of the final payoff for all possible
bids by imposing [p.bar] < [b.bar] < [bar.b] < [bar.p]. Thus,
notwithstanding b([P.sup.j,[tau].sub.i,t]) = [b.bar] (or
b([P.sup.j,[tau].sub.i,t]) = [bar.b]), the decision maker can never be
sure whether she will keep the prospect or not.
A risk-neutral and time-indifferent decision maker who cares only
for her own payoff should submit b([P.sup.j,[tau].sub.i,t]) = u = EU for
each of the 16 prospects. However, if the decision maker cares for her
partner and wants to increase the chances of keeping the prospect, she
should report b([P.sup.j,[tau].sub.i,t]) > u. Comparing bids across
prospects allows us to disentangle attitudes toward one's own risk
and delay from attitudes toward the other's risk and delay.
Procedures
The computerized experiment was conducted at the laboratory of the
Max Planck Institute in Jena, Germany, in August 2005. The experiment
was programmed using the z-Tree software (Fischbacher, 2007).
Participants were undergraduate students from different disciplines at
the University of Jena. After being seated at a computer terminal,
participants received written instructions (Appendix). Understanding of
the rules was checked by a control questionnaire that subjects had to
answer before the experiment started.
Thirty-two students participated in a single session, which lasted
about 60 min. The experimental currency unit (ECU) was converted into
Euro according to 10 ECU = 2.5 [euro]. Average earnings (including a
show-up fee of 2.5 [euro]) were 9.6 [euro] when delayed and 8.0 [euro]
when immediate. (7)
To collect as many as possible independent observations for all 16
prospects shown in Table 1, the strategy method was used. This means
that each participant had to submit 16 reservation prices, one for each
prospect, before the roles of decision makers and passive partners were
assigned. (8)
The parameter values were equal to those used by Brennan et al.
(forthcoming) in order to check for consistency of results as far as
possible (i.e., for the top row of Table 1 with no delay of rewards at
all). In particular, the lower and upper bounds, [P.bar] and [bar.p], of
the uniform distribution from which the random offer prices were
selected amounted to 4 and 50 ECU, respectively. (9) Participants could
submit any integer value between 8 and 46 ECU. The prospect's
parameters were u = 27, [U.bar] = 16, and [bar.U] = 38.
Deferred Payment
As in Anderhub et al. (2001), a problematic feature of our
experiment is that some of the payments should be made in the future,
that is, 3 mo after the experiment. The corresponding incentive scheme
may be ineffective if subjects doubt that they will actually be paid as
described in the instructions. To avoid the problem, we used written
assurances, attesting that the money would be transferred into the
subject's bank account 3 mo after the experiment. (10) In
particular, subjects whose payment had to be postponed were required to
fill in the details of their bank account, and they received a guarantee
of late payment that was signed by an executive representative of the
Max Planck Institute. Thus, at the end of the experiment, a subject
could receive either ready money (as in the case of the prospect's
sale) or a guarantee of late payment.
III. EXPERIMENTAL RESULTS
Figure 1 reports the reservation prices for each individual subject
across all 16 prospects.
Decisions are, in general, scattered around the opportunistic risk-neutral prediction given by b([P.sup.j,[tau].sub.i,t]) = 27. Apart
from five participants who stick to the same reservation price for all
prospects, the remaining participants undertake an "active"
approach to decision making, that is, they provide different valuations
of the various prospects. Two patterns are recurrent: one focuses on
personal risk and varies, mainly, with prospects assigning the lottery
to oneself (see, e.g., Subjects 1 and 2), and the other recurrent
pattern focuses on own delay and changes depending on whether one's
own payment date is 0 or 3 (see, e.g., Subjects 13 and 14). Though some
patterns appear more complex than those described above, they present
similar features.
Aggregate Analysis
The results are summarized in Figures 2 and 3, which inform on the
distribution of choices for each prospect. The 16 graphs in Figure 2 are
distributed over four rows and four columns that match those of Table 1.
Hence, the four distributions in, for example, the top row of the figure
refer to the prospects varying only in the risk component when t = [tau]
= 0.
Choices span from the minimum to the maximum of the distribution in
14 of the 16 cases. In most prospects (7 of 16), the mode is 27. The
highest mean reservation price (31.16) is paid for the prospect granting
sure and immediate payoffs to both the decision maker and her
"passive" partner. Distributions tend to be rightward skewed when own reward is certain and immediate and leftward skewed when own
reward is risky and/or delayed. The lowest mean reservation prices refer
to the four prospects with delayed and uncertain payments to the
decision maker. Figure 3 clearly illustrates how the distribution values
shift down dramatically for prospects of the form
[P.sup.j,[tau].sub.U,3]. (11) These observations already suggest that
decision makers show other-regarding concerns when they can rely on a
sure and prompt reward, but, in line with previous studies, uncertainty
and delay in own reward induce a decrease in reservation prices.
A series of Wilcoxon signed-rank tests (two sided) comparing
reservation prices for the prospect with no delay and no risk for both
parties and the prospects where, ceteris paribus, one's own payoff
is risky and/or delayed confirm that valuations are highly significantly
different (p < 0.05 for [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] vs. [P.sup.u,0.sub.U,0];
p < 0.001 for [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] vs. either [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,3] or
[P.sup.u,0.sub.U,3]). The prospect granting an uncertain and delayed
reward to oneself but not to the other is also evaluated significantly
differently than the prospects with neither own risk nor own delay (p
< 0.01 for [P.sup.u.0.sub.U.3] vs. either [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,3] or
[P.sup.u,0.sub.U.0]).
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
[FIGURE 2 OMITTED]
Next, we check whether reservation prices react also to the
other's risk or delay. Wilcoxon signed-rank tests comparing
[P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] with [P.sup.U,0.sub.u,0], [P.sup.u,3.sub.u,0] and
[P.sup.U,3.sub.u,0] indicate that valuations are not significantly
different when the other's payoff is delayed (p = 0.373 for
[P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] vs. [P.sup.u,3.sub.u,0]). On the contrary, in line
with the results of Brennan et al. (forthcoming), a weak significance is
registered when introducing risk in the other's payoff (p = 0.049
for [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] vs. [P.sup.U,0.sub.u,0]; p = 0.053 for
[P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] vs. [P.sup.U,3.sub.u,0]). The other's situation
has no impact on reservation prices when one's own payoff is both
risky and delayed (p > 0.1 for all possible comparisons).
The effects of own and other's risk and those of own and
other's delay on reservation prices are explored in more detail via
a generalized, linear, random effects model (based on a Poisson
distribution), regressing average reservation prices on the dummies
OwnRisk, OwnDelay, OtherRisk, and OtherDelay. The variable OwnRisk takes
value 1 for the prospects with risky payoff for the decision maker
(i.e., [P.sup.i,[tau].sub.U,t] for all j, t, and [tau]) and 0 otherwise.
OtherRisk equals 1 for the prospects involving risk for the other (i.e.,
[P.sup.U,[tau].sub.i,t] for all i, t, and [tau]) and 0 otherwise.
OwnDelay is 1 when the prospects include delayed payoff for the decision
maker (i.e., [P.sup.j,[tau].sub.i,3] for all i, j, and [tau]) and 0
otherwise. Finally, OtherDelay is 1 for the prospects with delay in the
other's payoff (i.e., [P.sup.j,3.sub.i,t] for all i, j, and t) and
0 otherwise. Table 2 lists the estimates for the coefficients, standard
errors, and z-statistics. (12)
While an increase in one's own risk and payment date tends to
significantly reduce reservation prices, a risky or delayed prospect for
the partner has no significant impact on behavior. These results
corroborate those suggested by the nonparametric tests: decision makers
do not react differently to variations in the other's reward but
remain particularly attentive to risk and delay in their own payoffs.
[FIGURE 3 OMITTED]
The time preferences with respect to oneself and to the other can
be better assessed via estimation of the intertemporal discount factor
embedded in the evaluation of alternative prospects. In particular, the
average "private" and "social" discount factors
([[delta].sub.own] and [[delta].sub.other], respectively) can be
estimated from [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,3] = (P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0])[(1 +
[[delta].sub.own]).sup.-t] and [P.sup.u,3.sub.u,0] =
([P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0])[(1 + [[delta].sub.other]).sup.-t], with t = 1/4.
The distributions of [(1 + [[delta].sub.own]).sup.-t] and [(1 +
[[delta].sub.other]).sup.-t] differ significantly. (13) The estimate for
the annual [[delta].sub.own] is 128.70%, whereas that for
[[delta].sub.other] is 11.71%, thereby confirming that one is much more
impatient when her own reward is delayed than when the other's
reward is delayed.
Individual Types
In this section, we investigate the interrelation of
other-regarding concerns with attitudes toward other's risk and
delay in more detail. First, we define a measure for each of the various
attitudes we are interested in, thereby identifying typologies of
behavior. Then we examine how types are related.
To assess individual i's concerns toward j's (j [not
equal to] i) payoffs, we look at i's valuation of the prospect
granting the sure reward u to both i and j at time 0. An
"other-regarding" individual i should evaluate the prospect
[P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] at a price higher than u. On the other hand, if i is
willing to accept less than u to sell the same prospect, she can be
viewed as "spiteful" (see Dufwenberg and Guth 2000).
To measure i's attitudes toward her own risk, we use the
difference in reservation prices between the prospects
[P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] and [P.sup.u,0.sub.U,0]. If this difference is
positive, the subject can be considered as "risk-averse"
since, ceteris paribus, she evaluates the prospect assigning her the
sure payoff more than the prospect assigning her the lottery.
Alternatively, if [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] - [P.sup.u,0.sub.U,0] is negative,
subject i can be considered as "risk-seeking." Attitudes
toward own delay are measured in a similar way by considering how the
valuation of [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] compares to that of
[P.sup.u,0.sub.u,3]. If [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] - [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,3] is
positive, the subject is classified as "delay-averse"; if it
is negative, she is categorized as "delay-seeking."
Finally, to assess subject i's attitudes toward risk and delay
faced by her partner j, we take into account i's preferences for
social allocation of risky and delayed prospects. Following Brennan et
al. (forthcoming), we capture social orientation by the difference in
reservation prices between the prospects [P.sup.u,0.sub.U,0] and
[P.sup.U,0.sub.u,0] as far as risk is concerned and the prospects
[P.sup.u,0.sub.u,3] a d [P.sup.u,3.sub.u,0] as far as time is concerned.
Combining i's risk (delay) attitudes and her social risk (delay)
orientation, we can define whether i is self- or other-oriented when
allocating risk (delay). In particular, a risk(delay)-averse subject
with a positive social risk (delay) orientation can be considered as
"other-oriented" with respect to risk (delay): notwithstanding
her aversion to risk (delay), she prefers the prospect including risk
(delay) for herself rather than for the other. Being other-oriented when
i is risk(delay)-seeking requires the corresponding measure to be
negative. A brief description of the identified measures for each type
is provided in Table 3, which also reports the number of observations
that comply with a specific typology.
Computing these measures for each individual and combining them
allow us to examine how the different attitudes interact. Table 4
displays Kendall's correlation coefficients between the various
attitudes. Risk aversion and delay aversion with respect to own payoffs
induce a negative correlation (-0.482 and -0.284) between
other-regarding concerns and social orientations, although the
correlation is not significant as to the time dimension. The opposite
holds for risk-seeking behavior. Given our definition of social
orientation, the observed correlation coefficients imply that people who
are more other-regarding tend, on average, to be more self-oriented when
allocating risky and delayed prospects.
Attitudes toward own risk and delay are always positively related
with other-regarding concerns, but only risk (delay) aversion is
significantly so. Furthermore, more risk-averse behavior induces, on
average, more self-oriented behavior in decisions involving social
redistribution of risk (the correlation coefficient between RA and
Soc.Or.RA is significantly negative). The same holds for delay-averse
behavior. Finally, risk attitudes and time preferences with respect to
own rewards are positively correlated (Kendall's coefficient equals
0.208, p = 0.1).
How concerns toward the other's payoffs compare with social
orientation to risk and delay is graphically illustrated in Figures 4
and 5, separately for risk-/delay-averse and risk-/delay-seeking
subjects.
In line with the correlation analysis, risk-averse subjects tend to
cluster in the upper-left quadrant, while risk-seeking subjects are more
likely found in the upper-right quadrant (see Figure 4). This confirms
that most individuals are concerned about what the other gets but remain
self-oriented when allocating social risk. The picture does not change
when considering time preferences (see Figure 5).
IV. CONCLUSIONS
In this article, we have studied the interrelation between
other-regarding concerns and attitudes toward risk and delay, when risk
and delay are borne not only by the actor but also by another person.
[FIGURE 4 OMITTED]
[FIGURE 5 OMITTED]
We find evidence of other-regarding concerns when monetary payoffs
are certain and immediate for both involved parties. Our results also
suggest that agents react to changes in the other's status (in
terms of both risk and delay) when their own reward is immediate and
certain. However, they disregard the other and focus on their own
condition when the latter becomes risky and/or delayed. In our view,
this suggests an interesting crowding-out effect in the sense that own
risky and delayed decision problems tend to crowd out concerns toward
others' problems, possibly due to some cognitive and emotional
overload. The regression results reveal, in fact, that only own risk and
delay have significant effect on individual behavior. This may mean that
the function [U.sub.i] reported in the Introduction is additively
separable and takes the form
(2) [U.sub.i] = [summation over (x[member of]X)]
Prob{x}[g.sub.i]([r.sup.0.sub.i](x), [r.sup.1.sub.i](x))
+ [h.sub.i](Prob{x}[g.sub.i]([r.sup.0.sub.j](x),
[r.sup.1.sub.j](x))),
that is, participants mind very much risk and timing of their own
reward but rely on expected total rewards when engaging in
other-regarding considerations (at least, when risk and delay affect
them). Again, the two evaluation functions [g.sub.i](*) and [h.sub.i](*)
should depend positively on their arguments for nonspiteful decision
maker i. This leaves some flexibility for neoclassical repairs and
provides more specific information about how we decide when risk and
timing of our own and another person's rewards are affected.
In agreement with previous research, we find that people are rather
impatient when their own reward is delayed. But this strong impatience
is not projected upon the other. Furthermore, in line with Anderhub et
al. (2001), risk attitudes and time preferences with respect to own
rewards are positively correlated: agents who are risk-averse (seeking)
when their own payoffs are uncertain tend to be delay-averse (seeking)
when their own payoffs are deferred. Hence, if the function g,{*) is
concave in its arguments, it is usually also more reactive to
[r.sup.0.sub.i](x) than to [r.sup.1.sub.i] (x).
Finally, our type analysis reveals that while exhibiting
other-regarding preferences with respect to the other's expected
payoff, individuals are mainly self-oriented as to social allocation of
risk and delay. This is consistent with findings of Brennan et al.
(forthcoming) indicating that risk in what others get is much less
important than own risk, even for those who are relatively
other-regarding.
ABBREVIATIONS
AIC: Akaike Information Criterion
ECU: Experimental Currency Unit
APPENDIX: TRANSLATED INSTRUCTIONS
Welcome and thanks for participating in this experiment. You
receive 2.50 [euro] for having shown up on time. Please read the
following instructions carefully. From now on any communication with
other participants is forbidden. If you have any questions or concerns,
please raise your hand. We will answer your questions individually. The
unit of experimental money will be the ECU (Experimental Currency Unit),
where 1 ECU = 0.25 [euro].
In this experiment you will be randomly paired with another
participant, whose identity will not be revealed to you at any time. In
the following, we will refer to the person whom you are paired with as
"the other."
You will face 16 different prospects, each of which pays to you and
to the other some positive amounts of ECU. These payments can be either
certain or uncertain, and either immediate or deferred.
The certain payment gives 27 ECU for sure. The uncertain payment
consists of a lottery giving either 16 ECU or 38 ECU, where both amounts
are equally likely.
Four cases are possible depending on whether the payment is 1)
certain for both you and the other; 2) uncertain for both you and the
other; 3) certain for you and uncertain for the other; 4) uncertain for
you and certain for the other.
The immediate payment will be paid out today; i.e., ECU will be
converted to Euros at the end of the experiment, and the obtained amount
will be paid to you and/or to the other in cash straight away. The
deferred payment will be paid out later; i.e., ECU will be converted to
Euros at the end of the experiment, but the obtained amount will be
transferred to your and/or the other's bank account in three
months. You and/or the other will receive a guarantee of late payment at
the end of the experiment, after filling out a form concerning your bank
account's details.
As before, four cases are possible depending on whether the payment
is 1) immediate for both you and the other; 2) deferred for both you and
the other; 3) immediate for you and deferred for the other; 4) deferred
for you and immediate for the other.
Combining the 4 cases related to the time of the payments with the
4 cases related to their certainty yields the 4 x 4 = 16 prospects that
you will face. In particular, these 16 prospects are:
1. You get 27 ECU for sure now, and the other gets the lottery now.
2. You get 27 ECU for sure later, and the other gets the lottery
later.
3. You get 27 ECU for sure now, and the other gets the lottery
later.
4. You get 27 ECU for sure later, and the other gets the lottery
now.
5. You get the lottery now, and the other gets 27 ECU for sure now.
6. You get the lottery later, and the other gets 27 ECU for sure
later.
7. You get the lottery now, and the other gets 27 ECU for sure
later.
8. You get the lottery later, and the other gets 27 ECU for sure
now.
9. Both you and the other get 27 ECU for sure now.
10. Both you and the other get 27 ECU for sure later.
11. You get 27 ECU for sure now, and the other gets 27 ECU for sure
later.
12. You get 27 ECU for sure later, and the other gets 27 ECU for
sure now.
13. Both you and the other get the lottery now.
14. Both you and the other get the lottery later.
15. You get the lottery now, and the other gets the lottery later.
16. You get the lottery later, and the other gets the lottery now.
What You Have to Do
Your task (as well as the task of each other participant) is to
report the lowest amount of ECU for which you would be willing to sell
each prospect. In other words, you have to state a minimum selling price
for each of the 16 prospects. Each of your sixteen choices must be not
smaller than 8 ECU and not greater than 46 ECU. Furthermore, it must be
an integer number (i.e., 8, 9, 10, ..., 44, 45, 46).
Your Payoffs
Your payoff depends on the choices made by the two members of the
group, and on three random choices made by the computer. These random
choices determine an "active" player, a "relevant"
prospect, and an "integer" between 4 and 50. More
specifically, payoffs are determined as follows.
(I) After you and the other participant have reported the minimum
selling price for each prospect, the computer will select either you or
the other participant as the "active player." The minimum
selling prices reported by the active player will affect the payoffs of
the group, whereas the minimum selling prices reported by the other
(non-active) participant do not have any effect.
(II) Once the active player has been determined, the computer will
select one of the sixteen prospects faced by this player as the
"relevant prospect," where all sixteen prospects are equally
likely.
(III) Finally, the computer will randomly choose an
"integer" between 4 and 50. You can think of this choice as
drawing a ball from a bingo cage containing 47 balls numbered 4, 5, ...,
50. Any number between 4 and 50 is equally likely.
Your final payoff is computed by comparing this random integer to
the minimum selling price reported by the active player (either you or
the other participant) for the relevant prospect.
* If the random integer is smaller than the minimum selling price
reported by the active player for the relevant prospect, the active
player keeps the relevant prospect and the two members of the group
obtain the payments specified by it.
* If the random integer is equal to or greater than the minimum
selling price reported by the active player for the relevant prospect,
the active player sells the relevant prospect and earns an amount of ECU
equal to the random integer, which will be paid out to him/her in cash
today. In this case, the other (non-active) player earns nothing.
If the active player does not sell the relevant prospect and this
prospect consists of a lottery, the lottery will be played for real
today although its outcome may be paid out in three months.
Example
Suppose that the computer chooses you as the active player, and
that the prospect paying to you 27 ECU for sure now and to the other
either 16 or 38 ECU later is the relevant prospect. Suppose also that
you have reported a minimum selling price of 20 ECU for that particular
prospect.
* If the computer chooses the integer 18, you keep the prospect
(because 18 < 20). This implies that you get 27 ECU today, and the
other obtains either 16 or 38 ECU in three months, where these two
amounts are equally likely.
* If the computer chooses the integer 22, you sell the prospect
(because 22 > 20). This implies that you get 22 ECU today, and the
other participant earns nothing.
Before the experiment starts, you will have to answer some control
questions to verify your understanding of the rules of the experiment.
Please remain quiet until the experiment starts and switch off your
mobile phone. If you have any questions, please raise your hand now.
MATTEO PLONER, We thank Sebastian Briesemeister for writing the
program for the experiment and Bettina Bartels and Frederic Bertels for
their valuable assistance during the experimental session.
REFERENCES
Anderhub, V., W. Guth, U. Gneezy, and D. Sonsino. "On the
Interaction of Risk and Time Preferences: An Experimental Study."
German Economic Review, 2, 2001, 239-53.
Andreoni, J., and J. Miller. "Giving According to GARP: An
Experimental Test of the Consistency of Preferences for Altruism."
Econometrica, 70, 2002, 737-53.
Becker, G. M., M. H. DeGroot, and J. Marschak. "Measuring
Utility by a Single-Response Sequential Method." Behavioral
Science, 9, 1964, 226-32.
Bolton, G., and A. Ockenfels. "ERC: A Theory of Equity,
Reciprocity and Competition." American Economic Review, 90, 2000,
166-93.
Brennan, G., L. Gonzalez, W. Guth, and M. V. Levati.
"Attitudes toward Private and Collective Risks in Individual and
Strategic Choice Situations." Journal of Economic Behavior and
Organization, forthcoming.
Charness, G., and M. Rabin. "Understanding Social Preferences
with Simple Tests." Quarterly Journal of Economics, 117, 2002,
817-69.
Chesson, H., and W. Viscusi. "Commonalities in Time and
Ambiguity Aversion for Long-Term Risks." Theory and Decision, 54,
2003, 57-71.
Dufwenberg, M., and W. Guth. "Why Do you Hate Me? On the
Survival of Spite." Economics Letters, 67, 2000, 147-52.
Fehr, E., and K. Schmidt. "A Theory of Fairness, Competition,
and Cooperation." Quarterly Journal of Economics, 114, 1999,
817-68.
Fischbacher, U. "z-Tree: Zurich Toolbox for Readymade Economic
Experiments." Experimental Economics, 10, 2007, 171-8.
Green, L., J. Myerson, and P. Ostaszewski. "Amount of Reward
has Opposite Effects on the Discounting of Delayed and Probabilistic
Outcomes." Journal of Experimental Psychology-Learning Memory and
Cognition, 25, 1999, 418-27.
Guth, W., and M. Yaari. "Explaining Reciprocal Behavior in
Simple Strategic Games: An Evolutionary Approach," in Explaining
Process and Change. Approaches to Evolutionary Economics, edited by U.
Witt. Ann Arbor, MI: The University of Michigan Press, 1992, 23-34.
Mazur, J. E. "Choice, Delay, Probability, and Conditioned
Reinforcement." Animal Learning & Behavior, 25, 1997, 131-47.
Rawls, J. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1971.
Ross, L., D. Greene, and P. House. "The False Consensus
Effect: An Egocentric Bias in Social Perception and Attribution Processes." Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 13, 1977,
279-301.
Samuelson, W., and R. Zeckhauser. "Status Quo Bias in Decision
Making." Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 1, 1988, 7-59.
Smith, V. L. "Microeconomic Systems as an Experimental
Science." American Economic Review, 72, 1982, 923-55.
Tietz, R. "An Endowment Effect in Market Experiments," in
New Directions in Economic Psychology: Theory, Experiment and
Application, edited by S. E. Lea, P. Webley, and B. M. Young.
Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar, 1992, 99-113.
Tversky, A., and D. Kahneman. "Advances in Prospect Theory:
Cumulative Representation of Uncertainty." Journal of Risk and
Uncertainty, 5, 1992, 297-323.
Guth: Director, Max Planck Institute of Economics, Strategic
Interaction Group, Kahlaische Strasse 10, D-07745 Jena, Germany. Phone
0049-3641-686620, Fax 0049-3641-686667, E-mail
[email protected]
Levati: Research Associate, Max Planck Institute of Economics,
Strategic Interaction Group, Kahlaische Strasse 10, D-07745 Jena,
Germany, and Dipartimento di Scienze Economiche, Bari University, Via C.
Rosalba 53, I-70124 Bari, Italy. Phone 0049-3641686629, Fax
0049-3641-686667, E-mail levati@econ. mpg.de
Ploner: Research Fellow, LEM, Sant' Anna School of Advanced
Studies, Piazza Martiri della Liberta 33, I-56127 Pisa, Italy. Phone
0039-461-882246, Fax 0039-461-882222, E-mail
[email protected]
(1.) See, for example, Anderhub et al. (2001); Chesson and Viscusi
(2003); Green, Myerson, and Ostaszewski (1999); and Mazur (1997).
(2.) For instance, pension funds should reduce risky options if
investors in such funds, who do not mind delaying rewards, are rather
risk-averse.
(3.) Smith (1982) referred to experiments, where the primary
purpose is to discover empirical regularities in areas where no theory
exists as heuristic.
(4.) This "replication" of attitudes may be due to false
consensus effects (see Ross, Greene, and House 1977) or to a Kantian
imperative suggesting how oneself and all others should cope with risk.
Brennan et al. (forthcoming) discuss the issue in more details.
(5.) We are interested more in the differences among individual
evaluations of the several prospects than in absolute evaluations of
each prospect. Thus, we do not check whether our findings are robust
with respect to the method of eliciting certainty equivalents. Samuelson
and Zeckhauser (1988) and Tietz (1992) provided experimental evidence on
the endowment effect.
(6.) By assigning equal probabilities to [U.bar] and [bar.U], we
try to avoid the possibility of probability transformations as in
cumulative prospect theory (see, e.g., Tversky and Kahneman 1992).
(7.) Note that only the immediate average earnings include zero
payments to the passive partner in case the prospect is sold.
(8.) In order to avoid portfolio diversification effects,
participants were paid according to one choice only.
(9.) Although there is no (normative) need of uniformity, this has
been assumed because it seems the most unbiased and understandable (by
the participants) distribution.
(10.) The German system did not allow us to use "deferred
checks" as Anderhub et al. (2001) could do in Israel.
(11.) These prospects together with [P.sup.U,0.sub.u,3] (the mean
evaluation of which is 24.97) are the only ones that are evaluated, on
average, less than 27.
(12.) We estimated several models to test the interaction between
the various explanatory variables. The reported model fits better the
data on the basis of the Akaike Information Criterion (AIC). Although
the best AIC was observed for the model omitting OtherDelay, we
preferred to include this variable for completeness of information.
(13.) The p value obtained from the Wilcoxon rank-sum test with
continuity correction is 0.004.
TABLE 1
The 16 Prospects Evaluated by Each Participant
Risk
Delay No One Own
No one [p.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] [p.sup.u,0.sub.U,0]
Own [p.sup.u,0.sub.u,3] [p.sup.u,0.sub.U,3]
Other [p.sup.u,3.sub.u,0] [p.sup.u,3.sub.U,0]
Both parties [p.sup.u,3.sub.u,3] [p.sup.u,3.sub.U,3]
Risk
Delay Other Both Parties
No one [p.sup.U,0.sub.u,0] [p.sup.U,0.sub.U,0]
Own [p.sup.U,0.sub.U,3] [p.sup.U,0.sub.U,0]
Other [p.sup.U,3.sub.U,0] [p.sup.U,0.sub.U,0]
Both parties [p.sup.U,3.sub.U,3] [p.sup.U,0.sub.U,0]
TABLE 2
Generalized Linear Mixed Effects Regression
on Reservation Prices
Coefficient Standard z Pr([absolute
Error value of z])
Intercept 3.485 *** 0.028 124.01 0.000
OwnRisk -0.098 *** 0.017 -5.770 0.000
OwnDelay -0.142 *** 0.017 -8.376 0.000
OtherRisk -0.020 0.017 -1.212 0.225
OtherDelay 0.002 0.017 0.144 0.885
*** 0.1% significance level.
TABLE 3
Measures of Individual Attitudes toward
Payoffs, Risks, and Delays
Attitudes Description n
Other-regarding [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] - u > 0 20
Spiteful [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] - u < 0 5
Risk-averse [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] - [P.sup.u,0.sub.U,0] 16
> 0
Risk-seeking [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] - [P.sup.u,0.sub.U,0] 7
< 0
Delay-averse [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] - [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,3] 18
> 0
Delay-seeking [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,0] - [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,3] 2
< 0
Risk other-oriented [P.sup.u,0.sub.U,0] - [P.sup.U,0.sub.u,0] 0
Risk self-oriented [P.sup.u,0.sub.U,0] - [P.sup.U,0.sub.u,0] 22
Delay other-oriented [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,3] - [P.sup.u,3.sub.u,0] 1
Delay self-oriented [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,3] - [P.sup.u,0.sub.u,3] 19
Notes: n denotes the number of observations. We do not report
the (neutral) cases in which the values were 0.
TABLE 4
Kendall's Correlation Coefficients between Attitudes
Attitudes OR Soc.Or.RA Soc.Or.RS Soe.Or.DA
Soc.Or.RA -0.482 ***
Soc.Or.RS -0.617 *
Soc.Or.DA -0.284
Soc.Or.DS -
RA 0.637 *** -0.735 ***
RS 0.264 0.098
DA 0.346 ** -0.599 ***
DS 1.000
Notes: Missing values are due to low number of observations.
DA = delay-averse; DS= delay-seeking; OR = other-regarding;
RA = risk-averse; RS = risk-seeking;
Soc.Or. = social orientation.
*** 1% significance levels.
** 5% significance levels.
* 10% significance levels.