Game theory for playing games: sophistication in a negative-externality experiment.
Spraggon, John M. ; Oxoby, Robert J.
I. INTRODUCTION
A significant body of literature addresses the behavior of
individuals in experimental games and how this behavior often deviates
from theoretical predictions. Specifically, this literature raises a
concern with the lack of observed behaviors supporting theoretical
(Nash) predictions. For example, voluntary contribution experiments
often yield significant deviations from the Nash predictions, and
participants' behaviors typically respond to experimental
treatments that have no effect on the Nash predictions (Holt and Laury,
(2008); Laury and Holt, (2008)). Moreover, greater than Nash
contributions continue even in relatively long treatments (50 rounds and
more). This tendency to over-contribute has been attributed to
reciprocal altruism and decision errors. c While these explanations may
be correct, there may be reasons for these deviations which are
supported by standard theory (e.g., Binmore 1999).
We conjecture that some of the observed differences from
theoretical predictions may be due to inexperience with the concepts of
maximizing behavior and strategic interactions. Simply put, if
individuals do not know what constitutes optimal decision making, it
should not be surprising that optimal decision making is not observed.
As a result, individuals may rely on simple rules or heuristics to make
decisions even though these rules may be suboptimal.
To test this conjecture, we conduct a series of moral hazard experiments with participants who vary in their familiarity with the
concepts and tools of optimal and strategic decision making.
Specifically, we compare the behaviors of a "sophisticated"
subject pool with those of a more standard pool of participants (i.e.,
undergraduate university students). In identifying sophisticated
participants, we chose individuals who (at a minimum) had taken an
undergraduate game theory course. Our rationale was that these students
should be familiar not only with the idea of marginal analysis but also
with the concepts of the Nash equilibrium and the identification of
dominant strategies in games. Thus, our sophisticated subject pool can
be thought of as having been trained in "payoff maximization."
(2) Our interest lies in how these individuals behave relative to a more
standard pool of "unsophisticated" participants. As such, our
analysis is akin to that which attempts to induce behavior which is
consistent with theoretical predictions such as Plott and Zeiler (2005),
Cherry, Crocker, and Shogren (2003), and Charness, Frechette, and Kagel
(2004).
In our environment, subjects choose decision numbers for which
higher decision numbers correspond to higher individual payoffs and
higher social costs, analogous to the emission of a pollutant that is
costly to abate. Under the assumption that these decision numbers are
private information, this is a classic moral hazard in groups problem
similar to the worker effort problem in the labor literature (e.g.,
Holmstrom 1982) and the nonpoint source pollution in the environmental
literature (e.g., Segerson 1988).
We use two instruments based on the family of exogenous targeting
instruments suggested by Segerson (1988). These instruments involve an
exogenously chosen target for aggregate (i.e., group) decision numbers,
analogous to the aggregate environmental level of a nonpoint source
pollutant. The two instruments we use create incentives for individuals
to choose optimal decisions by providing penalties (a tax) or rewards (a
subsidy) for implementing aggregate decisions greater than or less than
the exogenous target. (3) Our Tax/Sub sidy instrument involves a tax if
the sum of individual decision numbers exceeds the target and a subsidy
if the sum is below the target. Under this instrument, there is a
unique, interior dominant strategy Nash equilibrium and a group (Pareto)
optimal outcome. Our Tax instrument involves only the tax if the
aggregate decision number of subjects in the group exceeds the target
level. Under this instrument, there is a unique, interior Nash
equilibrium (although it is not a dominant strategy). The differences
between equilibria under each instrument allow us to discern how
individuals' experience affects their ability to play equilibrium
strategies and identify superior (i.e., Pareto-dominant) equilibria.
The environment investigated in this paper differs significantly
from standard social dilemma experiments such as public goods,
ultimatum, and gift exchange games. In these standard social dilemmas,
there is a clear choice between self-interested and other-regarding
plays. In our experiment, the instrument (either the Tax/Subsidy or the
Tax) is designed so as to eliminate the social dilemma. As a result,
both the self-interested and the other-regarding play outcomes are the
same. This alignment of self-interested and other-regarding preferences
should provide the theoretical prediction a better chance of being
observed than in social dilemma experiments. That it does not (Cochard,
Willinger, and Xepapadeas 2005; Poe et al. 2004; Spraggon 2002, 2004a,
2004b; Vossler et al. 2006) is a question that must be resolved before
the behavior in social dilemma experiments can be fully understood.
Laury and Holt (2008) survey the literature on public goods games
with interior Nash equilibria, concluding that moving to an interior
Nash equilibrium does not result in decisions that are more consistent
with the Nash predictions. They find that average decisions are
typically between the Nash equilibrium and the midpoint of the decision
space. In group moral hazard environments similar to that employed here,
previous research has shown that under different conditions (e.g.,
market environments, communication), aggregate decisions are close to
the Nash prediction, whereas individual-level decisions differ
significantly from these predictions (Cochard, Willinger, and Xepapadeas
2005; Poe et al. 2004; Spraggon 2002, 2004a, 2004b; Vossler et al.
2006). In this paper, we show that the disparity between actual behavior
and the Nash predictions can be reconciled when the participants
understand the concepts of the Nash equilibrium and dominant strategies.
Overall, we find that the behavior of sophisticated participants is
much closer to the Nash predictions than that of unsophisticated
participants. This is particularly true under the Tax instrument. In
addition, we find the behaviors of sophisticated subjects to be much
less volatile than those of unsophisticated subjects. This is true even
when sophisticated subjects attempt to "signal" their desire
to coordinate on the group optimal outcome. Thus, while training in
economics may inhibit cooperativeness (Frank, Gilovich, and Regan 1993;
Marwell and Ames 1981), this training may also improve decision making
in environments embodying strategic behavior and information problems.
Thus, our results are related to and build upon the work of Cherry,
Crocker, and Shogren (2003) in which the rationality participants
demonstrate as a result of market discipline spills over into a
nonmarket setting. Our results complement this research, demonstrating
that the rationality one is exposed to and practices in developing an
understanding of game theory affect decision making in our
negative-externality environment.
Our results suggest that the practical value of exogenous targeting
instruments may be underestimated in a moral hazard environment where
decision makers have experience with profit maximization (e.g.,
professionals in the field making decisions in nonpoint pollution and
team production environments). On the other hand, the behavior of
unsophisticated participants is much more volatile than that of
sophisticated decision makers and is much less likely to be consistent
with the Nash predictions. Perhaps surprisingly, we identify several
"rules" or heuristics that appear to guide the decisions of
unsophisticated individuals. That is, many of the decisions made by
unsophisticated decision makers converge to focal points that are
consistent with simple decision-making rules.
Our results provide a clear indication that an understanding of
optimal decision making and Nash behavior (or a lack thereof) goes a
long way in explaining the observed deviations from equilibrium
predictions. While various preference specifications may account for the
deviations, it is striking that these alternate motivations are
essentially absent among our sophisticated decision makers, who differ
from the unsophisticated pool not based on preferences but rather based
on the understanding of basic economic theory. (4) When this knowledge
is absent, individuals appear to use alternate (and naively reasonable)
rules to motivate their decisions.
We continue as follows. Section II lays out the environment used in
our experiments and describes the two instruments participants faced. In
Section Ill, we analyze the results of the experimental data at the
aggregate level, by participant type, and at the individual decision
level. We find that sophisticated decision makers (i.e., those with an
understanding of game theory and profit maximization) are more likely to
make decisions supporting the Nash predictions. Furthermore, the
variability of individual decisions appears to be significantly muted in
experiments with sophisticated participants. In Section IV, we discuss
our results, casting our findings in light of the behavior of
individuals in experiments and the practical use of exogenous targeting
instruments.
II. EXPERIMENTAL DESIGN
Moral hazard in groups is inherent in situations as varied as the
workplace (Holmstrom 1982), insurance (Rothschild and Stiglitz 1976),
and the environment (Segerson 1988). The moral hazard in this experiment
is due to a regulator wanting to reduce a negative externality resulting
from consumption. This is analogous to an environmental problem in which
unabated pollution maximizes firm profits but reduces social welfare. In
the worker effort and insurance problems, the regulator seeks to
increase the positive externality associated with increased effort (the
more effort exerted by the worker, the better off the firm). (5)
In our experiment, groups consist of four participants, two of whom
choose decision numbers between 0 and 100 (medium-capacity participants)
and two between 0 and 125 (large-capacity participants). (6) Both types
of participants face the same private payoff function
(1) [B.sub.n] ([x.sub.n]) = 25 - 0.002 [([x.sup.max.sub.n] -
[x.sub.n]).sup.2],
where [x.sup.max.sub.n] = 100 for medium-capacity participants and
[x.sup.max.sub.n] = 125 for large-capacity participants. These payoffs
are described to the participants by way of a table, and private payoff
is maximized when [x.sub.n] = [x.sup.max.sub.n. (7)
The moral hazard aspect of the experiment is implemented through an
external cost (8) proportional to the aggregate decision number X =
[[summation].sup.4.sub.n] [x.sub.n] given by
(2) D(X) = 0.3X.
In this environment, individual decisions [x.sub.n] are private
information, while X is observable. Thus, a Paretian regulator
interested in efficient aggregate outcomes should use instruments based
on the aggregate decision number X via an exogenous target X* (as in
Holmstrom 1982; Segerson 1988). Given an aggregate decision number X and
an exogenous target X*, each individual pays the tax (if X > X*) or
receives the benefit (if X [less than or equal to] X*) [T.sub.n](X)
given by
(3) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
For our experiment, we chose X* = 150 and consider two instruments:
a Tax/Subsidy instrument in which [t.sub.n] = [s.sub.n] = 0.3,
[[tau].sub.n] = [[beta].sub.n] = 0 and a Tax instrument in which
[t.sub.n] = 0,3, [s.sub.n] = [[tau].sub.n], = [[beta].sub.n] = 0. Thus,
under the Tax/Subsidy instrument, an individual's private payoff is
given by
(4) [[pi].sub.n], = 25 - 0.002 [(x.sup.max.sub.n] -
[x.sub.n]).sup.2] - 0.3 (X - 150).
while under the Tax instrument, an individual's private payoff
is given by
(5) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
We consider the Nash equilibria under each of these instruments.
Under the Tax/Subsidy instrument, for any X, an individual's best
response [x.sup.*.sub.n] is
(6) [x.sup.*.sub.n] = [x.sup.max.sub.n] - 75.
This is also the solution for the Tax instrument if participants
believe that X [greater than or equal to] 150. However, if subjects
believe that X < 150, then their payoff-maximizing strategy is given
by
(7) [x.sub.n] = min [(x.sup.max.sub.n], 150 - [x.sub.-n]).
where [X.sub.-n] = [[summation].sub.j[not equal to]n]. Whereas the
Tax/ Subsidy instrument results in a clear dominant strategy independent
of the decisions of others, there is no such strategy under the Tax
instrument. There is also a second (Pareto superior from the point of
view of members of the group) optimum under the Tax/Subsidy instrument:
if all participants choose [x.sub.n] = 0, the payoff to the group is
maximized.
The above analysis is based on the assumption that participants
maximize their monetary payoff. We also consider the possibility that
our subjects may be boundedly rational. (9) In the environment presented
here, we are particularly interested in theories involving rules of
thumb (Bagnoli and Lipman 1989; Hackett, Schlager, and Walker 1994;
Rapoport and Suleiman 1993). For example, a simple decision rule in this
environment is choosing a decision number equal to the target divided by
the number of participants. Such a rule provides a simple way for the
group to avoid paying a fine. Similarly, participants may make decisions
based on focal points (e.g., the midpoint of their decision space).
III. RESULTS
In this section, we present our experimental results. We first
consider whether or not the sophisticated groups are more consistent
with the Nash prediction than the unsophisticated groups at the
aggregate level. We then look at the decisions over participant type
(medium or large capacity) and at the individual level.
The data were collected from eight sessions, each consisting of two
groups of four subjects, conducted at our universities. Participants
were recruited from economics courses and classified as sophisticated if
they had taken an undergraduate game theory course. (10) Each group
consisted of either all sophisticated or all unsophisticated
individuals, and each experiment consisted of 25 decision-making periods
under either the Tax instrument or the Tax/ Subsidy instrument. (11) The
decision was not presented as a maximization problem. Subjects were
given a tabular version of Equation (1) and both verbal and mathematical
descriptions of the group payoff function (Equation 4 or 5). The
software used for the sessions provided the subjects with a calculator,
allowing them to determine their payoff from different combinations of
their decisions and the decisions of the others in the group. Sessions
took approximately 90 min, and average earnings varied between $10 and
$25 Canadian.
A. Analysis at the Aggregate Level
Previous experiments by Spraggon (2002, 2004b) lead us to believe
that the instruments will be effective in inducing groups to the Nash
equilibrium at the aggregate level (i.e., X = X* = 150). Here, while we
expect variability in aggregate decision numbers, this variability
should be significantly lower within groups of sophisticated
participants. Indeed, this is demonstrated in Table 1, which presents
the aggregate decision number X by session. As expected, means are
closest to X* = 150 and less variable for groups of sophisticated
participants under both instruments. The median aggregate decision
numbers (Table 2) show this even more sharply. Note that only the
aggregate decisions for the unsophisticated subjects under the Tax
instrument is significantly different from the target of 150.
Analysis of variance on the aggregate data (Table 3) suggests that
both participant type (sophisticated or unsophisticated) and instrument
are significant (at the 10% level). The difference between sophisticated
and unsophisticated groups is confirmed for the Tax instrument by the
Mann-Whitney U-test (hereafter MW) and Kruskal-Wallis [chi square] test
(hereafter KW) (for the difference between sophisticated and
unsophisticated, p = .0253 for the Tax and p = .157 for the Tax/ Subsidy
instrument [the p values are the same for both tests]). (12) This
suggests that sophisticated participants made, generally speaking,
choices that were more consistent with the Nash predictions. Moreover,
choices by these participants are much less variable than those by
unsophisticated participants. The MW and KW tests do not indicate any
significant differences across treatments for either unsophisticated (p
= .2752) or sophisticated (p = .6242) subjects. Thus, we conclude that
at the aggregate level, sophistication matters for both Tax and
Tax/Subsidy in the same way.
B. Analysis by Capacity
Recall that subjects differed in their capacity (i.e., the size of
their decision space). These differences in capacities permit us to
analyze decisions to discern the different rules of thumb, which may
have been used by unsophisticated subjects. Table 4 presents mean
decision numbers by treatment, capacity, and five-period groupings. Note
that decision making is very consistent with the Nash predictions for
all except the unsophisticated medium-capacity subjects. Specifically,
the means for the unsophisticated participants are much closer to 50
(the middle of their decision space) than 25 (the Nash equilibrium)
under both the Tax and the Tax/Subsidy instruments. There are at least
two potential explanations for the difference from the Nash prediction
observed for the unsophisticated medium-capacity subjects. The first is
confusion (random play), and the second is that they are maximizing
their relative payoff by choosing higher numbers. (13)
For unsophisticated large-capacity subjects under the Tax
instrument, Table 4 indicates that decisions are reasonably similar to
the theoretical prediction (50). The decisions of sophisticated
large-capacity subjects under the Tax instrument, however, are much more
consistent with the theoretical prediction. This is evident by comparing
the standard errors, medians, and modes between these two groups in
Table 4. Both Levene's (1960) and Brown and Forsythe's (1974)
tests for equality of variance suggest that the variances are
significantly different (p = .0000 for both of these tests). The
distributions of individual decisions presented in Figure 1 also support
this finding. These distributions are significantly different using the
MW test (p = .0000) and KW test (p = .0001). For unsophisticated
medium-capacity subjects under the Tax instrument, average, median, and
modal decisions are much higher than the theoretical prediction of 25.
This is not the case for sophisticated medium-capacity subjects under
the Tax instrument whose decisions are very consistent with the
theoretical prediction. Again, standard errors are significantly lower
for sophisticated subjects in this treatment (p = .000 for the Levene
and Brown and Forsythe tests). Figure 2 shows the difference in the
distributions of individual decisions between the unsophisticated and
sophisticated subjects for this treatment. Again, the MW test (p =
.0000) and KW test (p = .0001) confirm that these distributions are
different.
As with the Tax, under the Tax/Subsidy instrument, decisions of the
sophisticated subjects for both medium- and large-capacity subjects are
completely consistent with the theoretical predictions. However,
unsophisticated large-capacity subjects are less consistent with the
theoretical prediction than they were under the Tax instrument. In both
cases, the standard errors are significantly higher for the
unsophisticated subjects (Tax/Subsidy large: p = .0000 for the Levene
test and p = .0000 for the Brown and Forsythe test; Tax/Subsidy medium:
p = .0016 for the Levene test and p = .001 for the Brown and Forsythe
test). Figures 3 and 4 compare the distributions of individual decisions
for medium- and large-capacity subjects. Again, the MW and KW tests both
confirm that the distributions of decisions for unsophisticated and
sophisticated subjects are significantly different (p = .0000 for the MW
test for large-capacity subjects and p = .0710 for medium-capacity
subjects; p = .0001 for the KW test for large-capacity subjects and p =
.0710 for medium-capacity subjects).
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
Table 4 and the distributions (Figures 14) do not suggest any
dynamic adjustments. We use the nonparametric (MW and KW tests) and
variance (the Levene and the Brown and Forsythe tests) comparison to
compare the first and last five periods of each treatment to confirm
this hypothesis. Under the Tax instrument, there is no significant
difference between the first and last five periods for either
unsophisticated or sophisticated medium-capacity or unsophisticated
large-capacity subjects (p > .16 in all cases). For large-capacity
sophisticated subjects, the difference in the distributions is close to
significance (p = .1019 for both the MW and the KW tests). Comparing the
distributions in Figure 1 for these subjects, we see that decisions are
a bit less random in the last five periods than they were in the first
five periods for this group. Under the Tax/Subsidy, we observe a
significant difference between the first and last five periods only for
the unsophisticated large-capacity subjects (p = .0132 for both the MW
and the KW tests and p > .54 for all the other cases). Looking at the
distributions in Figure 3, we again see that decisions are a bit less
random by the last five periods in this case. In terms of variance, we
observe significant differences between the variance of decisions in the
first and last five periods for medium sophisticated and large
sophisticated under the Tax instrument (p < .052 for these treatments
and p > .15 for the other treatments) and large unsophisticated under
the Tax/Subsidy instrument (p < .01 for this treatment and p > .59
for the other treatments). For the sophisticated subjects under the Tax
instrument, Table 4 and Figures 1 and 2 indicate that decisions become
more consistent with the theoretical prediction over time. Indeed, the
unsophisticated large-capacity subjects are becoming as consistent with
the theoretical prediction by the last five periods as the sophisticated
subjects are in the first five periods (p = .0191 for both the MW and
the KW tests).
[FIGURE 2 OMITTED]
Note that in addition to being more variable, the decisions of the
unsophisticated participants have peaks at points conforming with the
aforementioned simple rules. For large-capacity subjects, while we
observe a peak at the Nash prediction of [x.sub.n] = 50 under the Tax
instrument, we also observe a large peak at the middle of the decision
space ([x.sub.n] = 62.50). With respect to these subjects under the
Tax/Subsidy instrument, we observe two peaks, one to the right of the
middle of the decision space and the other at the simple rule of
dividing the target by the number of participants ([x.sub.n] = 37.50).
The decisions of the medium-capacity unsophisticated subjects under both
instruments are much more random. There is no peak at the Nash
prediction under either of the instruments for this group, and the only
large peak is in the middle of the decision space under the Tax
instrument. This randomness may be attributable to the positioning of
the Nash prediction relative to the alternate decision-making rule: for
large-capacity subjects, the Nash prediction lies between the
rule-of-thumb solution (target divided by the number of participants)
and the simple heuristic solution (middle of decision space). This may
help focus the decision making of large-capacity subjects. This is not
the case for the medium-capacity subjects whose Nash prediction
([x.sub.n] = 25) is below both the rule-of-thumb and simple heuristic
solutions. As a result, medium-capacity subjects may exhibit greater
"experimentation" in their decision making.
In contrast, the decisions of sophisticated subjects of both types
and under each instrument are sharply centered on the Nash prediction
([x.sub.n] = 50 for large-capacity subjects and [x.sub.n] = 25 for
medium-capacity subjects). We take this as strong evidence that
sophisticated subjects are better able to understand how to make
profit-maximizing decisions in this environment relative to
unsophisticated participants. We find it telling the proportion of
unsophisticated participants' decisions that are explained by our
simple decision rules under the Tax instrument but surprising the degree
of randomness under the Tax/Subsidy instrument.
[FIGURE 3 OMITTED]
C. Analysis by Participant
We now consider the decisions of individual participants. Figures
5-8 present each subject's time series of decisions. With respect
to unsophisticated subjects (Figures 5 and 6), we see significant
volatility and little convergence to the Nash prediction. Indeed, under
the Tax instrument, we observe only 2 of 12 subjects choosing their Nash
decision numbers by the end of the 25 decision-making periods, and 3 of
the 12 have median decisions that are .equal to the Nash prediction.
Similarly, only 3 of 12 subjects under the Tax/Subsidy instrument arrive
at their Nash prediction, while none have medians that are equal to this
value.
This stands in sharp contrast to the behavior of sophisticated
subjects (Figures 7 and 8). Under the Tax instrument, the median
decision of 14 of the 20 subjects is equal to the Nash prediction (with
6 subjects always choosing Nash and 4 others showing almost no deviation
from this decision). Note that while Subjects 205 and 206 did not choose
the Nash prediction, their behavior is optimal given that the other
subjects in their group (207 and 208) chose slightly below their Nash
predictions. Taken together, this yields 95% of sophisticated subjects
under the Tax instrument whose decisions are consistent with the
predictions of a Nash equilibrium. Under the Tax/Subsidy instrument,
decisions are somewhat more volatile. However, the median decision of 12
of 16 subjects is equal to the Nash prediction. Some of the increased
volatility (particularly that seen in Subjects 102, 901, and 1501) may
be the result of trying to signal to other participants a willingness to
move to the Pareto-superior outcome in which each individual chooses
[x.sub.n] = 0.
Again, we see a marked difference between the behavior of
sophisticated and that of unsophisticated participants. It is
particularly striking how many of the sophisticated participants
immediately identify the dominant strategy and play this strategy
consistently (or more or less consistently). It is clear that these
subjects understand the concept of profit maximization in a strategic
environment and the idea of a dominant strategy. As such, it is perhaps
unsurprising that their performance is so well predicted by a
traditional Nash best-response strategy. On the other hand, the fact
that the decisions of unsophisticated subjects stand in such sharp
contrast to those of the sophisticated emphasizes the importance of the
understanding of profit maximization when evaluating the performance of
participants in an experimental game.
[FIGURE 4 OMITTED]
[FIGURE 5 OMITTED]
[FIGURE 6 OMITTED]
[FIGURE 7 OMITTED]
[FIGURE 8 OMITTED]
IV. CONCLUSIONS
Our results demonstrate that when subjects understand optimization,
their behavior is rationalizable and predicted by standard economic
theory. In contrast, the behavior of subjects who are not trained in
game theory (our unsophisticated subjects) displays evidence of the use
of simple rules for making decisions. Having taken a course in game
theory significantly reduces the decision cost of finding an optimal or
a dominant strategy, suggesting that an extreme form of bounded
rationality (one that is not necessarily based on Nash payoff
maximization) would be more consistent with the behavior of the standard
subject pool used for these types of experiments. This contention is
consistent with Goeree and Holt (2001) who conclude that bounded
rationality models based on initial beliefs coupled with experiments
that elicit these beliefs is the most profitable approach to explaining
individual-level decision making. Using subjects who are trained in game
theory helps to control initial beliefs as not only do the individuals
understand game theory, but also they know that the other people in
their group understand game theory. This mitigates at least some of the
strategic uncertainty found with the standard pool. Moreover (and
perhaps thankfully), our results are consistent with those of Cherry,
Crocker, and Shogren (2003) in that the rationality one acquires in
taking a game theory course carries over into decision making in a
negative-externality environment.
In our assessment, two implications derive from our results. Having
course work in game theory had a significant effect on the behaviors of
individuals. This is not surprising: if one does not know how to
identify or what constitutes a dominant strategy, it is unlikely that
such a strategy will be identified or chosen by a participant. It is not
that the concept of dominance is not predictive but rather that
participant inexperience in a relatively complex decision environment
makes it highly unlikely that such a concept will be readily applied in
decision making. Our results imply that in the many experiments where we
fail to observe equilibria which support theoretical predictions,
inexperience with the mechanics of optimization or strategic thinking
may be to blame. Thus, the absence of behavior confirming theoretical
conjectures may not be due to individuals having ulterior motives,
decision errors, or unaccounted for arguments in their preferences but
rather due to a basic naivete with the types of decision making posited
by rational choice theory. (14) More importantly, our results indicate
that once people understand the tools of profit maximization and
strategic decision making, they are relatively quick to implement and
apply these concepts. (15)
The fact that individuals who know these concepts are able to
implement ideas of profit maximization and play dominant strategies
leads to a second implication of our results. The use of exogenous
targeting instruments has often been criticized with respect to its
application to environmental economics (Shortle and Horan 2001). Thus,
while exogenous targeting instruments serve as a natural mechanism to
cope with the problems of non-point pollution, they are rarely observed
in practice. The relative dearth of these instruments may be
attributable to concerns regarding how individuals behave when
confronted with these types of incentives. Our results indicate that
these instruments may work very well at implementing efficient
allocations. In the economic environments where these instruments are
most likely to be implemented, decision making is done by business
people and entrepreneurs who, for the most part, are familiar with the
idea of profit maximization, the functioning of markets, and strategic
interactions. (16) With these sophisticated decision makers, the
potential of these instruments to implement desired aggregate pollution
levels in an efficient manner is greatly enhanced.
ABBREVIATIONS
MW: Mann-Whitney
KW: Kruskal-Wallis
REFERENCES
Andreoni, J. "Warm Glow versus Cold Prickle: The Effects of
Positive and Negative Framing on Cooperation." Quarterly Journal of
Economics, 1995, 110, 1-22.
Bagnoli, M., and B. Lipman. "Provision of Public Goods: Fully
Implementing the Core through Voluntary Contributions." Review of
Economic Studies, 1989, 56, 583-601.
Bagnoli, M., and M. McKee. "Voluntary Contribution Games:
Efficient Private Provision of Public Goods." Economic Inquiry,
1991, 29, 351-66.
Banks, J., C. Camerer, and D. Porter. "An Experimental
Analysis of Nash Refinements in Signaling Games." Games and
Economic Behavior, 1994, 6, 1-31.
Binmore, K. "Why Experiment in Economics?" Economic
Journal, 1999, 109, F16-F24.
Brandts, J., and C. A. Holt. "Adjustment Patterns and
Equilibrium Selection in Experimental Signaling Games."
International Journal of Game Theory, 1993, 22, 279-302.
Brown, M. B., and A. B. Forsythe. "Robust test for the
equality of variances." Journal of the American Statistical
Association, 1974, 69, 364-7.
Charness, G., G. R. Frechette, and J. H. Kagel. "How Robust Is
Laboratory Gift-Exchange?" Experimental Economics, 2004, 7,
189-205.
Cherry, T. g., T. D. Crocker, and J. F. Shogren. "Rationality
Spillovers." Journal of Environmental Economics and Management,
2003, 45, 63-84.
Cochard, F., M. Willinger, and A. Xepapadeas. "Efficiency of
Nonpoint Source Pollution Instruments: An Experimental Study."
Environmental and Resource Economics, 2005, 30, 393-22.
Fehr, E., and U. Fischbacher. "Why Social Preferences
Matter--The Impact of Non-Selfish Motives on Competition, Cooperation,
and Incentives." Economic Journal, 2002, 112, C1-C33.
Frank, R. H., T. Gilovich, and D. T. Regan. "Does Studying
Economics Inhibit Cooperation?" Journal of Economic Perspectives,
1993, 7(2), 159-71.
Goeree, J. K., and C. A. Holt. "Ten Little Treasures of Game
Theory, and Ten Intuitive Contradictions." American Economic
Review, 2001, 91, 1402-22.
Hackett, S., E. Schlager, and J. Walker. "The Role of
Communication in Resolving Commons Dilemmas: Experimental Evidence with
Heterogeneous Appropriators." Journal of Environmental Economics
and Management, 1994, 27, 99-126.
Holmstrom, B. "Moral Hazard in Teams." Bell Journal of
Economics, 1982, 13, 32-40.
Holt, C. A., and S. K. Laury. "Theoretical Explanations of
Treatment Effects in Voluntary Contributions Experiments," in
Handbook of Experimental Economic Results, edited by C. Plott and V.
Smith. New York: Elsevier Press, 2008.
Laury, S. K., and C. A. Holt. "Voluntary Provision of Public
Goods: Experimental Results with Interior Nash Equilibria," in
Handbook of Experimental Economic Results, edited by C. Plott and V.
Smith. New York: Elsevier Press, 2008.
Ledyard, J. O. "Public Goods: A Survey of Experimental
Research," in Handbook of Experimental Economics, edited by J. H.
Kagel and A. E. Roth. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1995.
Levene, H. "Robust tests for equality of variances," in
Contributions to Probability and Statistics: Essays in honor of Harlod
Hotelling, edited by I. Olkin, S. G. Ghurye, W. Hoeffding, et al. Menlo
Park, CA: Stanford University Press, 1960, 278-92.
Levitt, S. D., and J. A. List. "Viewpoint: On the
Generalizability of Lab Behaviour to the Field." Canadian Journal
of Economies, 2007, 40, 347-70.
Marwell, G., and R. E. Ames. "Economists Free Ride, Does
Anyone Else? Experiments on the Provision of Public Goods, IV."
Journal of Public Economics, 1981, 15, 295-310.
Park, E.-S. "Warm-Glow versus Cold-Prickle: A Further
Experimental Study of Framing Effects on Free-Riding." Journal of
Economic Behavior and Organization, 2001, 43, 405-21.
Plott, C. R., and K. Zeiler. "The Willingness to
Pay-Willingness to Accept Gap, the 'Endowment Effect', Subject
Misconceptions, and Experimental Procedures for Eliciting
Valuations." American Economic Review, 2005, 95, 530-45.
Poe, G. L., W. D. Schulze, K. Segerson, J. F. Sutter, and C. A.
Vossler. "Exploring the Performance of Ambient-Based Policy
Instruments When Nonpoint Source Polluters Can Cooperate." American
Journal of Agricultural Economics, 2004, 86, 1203-10.
Potters, J., and F. van Winden. "Professionals and Students in
a Lobbying Experiment: Professional Rules of Conduct and Subject
Surrogacy." Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 2000,
43,499-522.
Rapoport, A., and R. Suleiman. "Incremental Contribution in
Step-Level Public Goods Games with Asymmetric Players."
Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 1993, 55, 171-94.
Rothschild, M., and J. Stiglitz. "Equilibrium in Competitive
Insurance Markets: An Essay on the Economics of Imperfect Information." Quarterly Journal of 'Economics, 1976, 90,
629-50.
Segerson, K. "Uncertainty and Incentives for Nonpoint
Pollution Control. " Journal of Environmental Economics and
Management, 1988, 15, 87-98.
Shortle, J. S., and R. D. Horan. "The Economics of Nonpoint
Pollution Control. " Journal of Economic Surveys, 2001, 15, 255-89.
Sonnemans, J., A. Schram, and T. Offerman. "Public Good
Provision and Public Bad Prevention: The Effect of Framing."
Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 1998, 34, 143-61.
Spraggon, J. "Exogenous Targeting Instruments as a Solution to
Group Moral Hazard." Journal of Public Economics, 2002, 84, 427-56.
--. "Individual Decision Making in a Negative Externality
Experiment." Experimental Economics, 2004a, 7, 249-269.
--. "Testing Ambient Pollution Instruments with Heterogeneous
Agents." Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 2004b,
48, 837-856.
Vossler, C. A., G. L. Poe, W. D. Schulze, and K. Segerson.
"Communication and Incentive Mechanisms Based on Group Performance:
An Experimental Study of Nonpoint Pollution Control." Economic
Inquiry, 2006, 44, 599-613.
Willinger, M., and A. Ziegelmeyer. "Framing and Cooperation in
Public Good Games: An Experiment with an Interior Solution."
Economics Letters, 1999, 65, 323-28.
(1.) See Ledyard (1995) and Laury and Holt (2008) for reviews of
this literature in public goods experiments. Similar arguments have been
made regarding deviations from theoretical predictions in ultimatum and
gift-giving games (Fehr and Fischbacher 2002) as well as a wide range of
other games (Goeree and Holt 2001).
(2.) An anonymous reviewer points out that these subjects may find
game-theoretical principles more intuitive than our standard subject
pool. We admit that this is a valid concern but feel that to the extent
we are interested in the behavior of competitive agents (be it firms in
the nonpoint source pollution problem or workers in the worker effort
problem), presumably these agents are also selected from those who are
better at optimization.
(3.) This type of mechanism is similar to the provision point
public goods mechanisms analyzed by Bagnoli and Lipman (1989) and
Bagnoli and McKee (1991).
(4.) Similar points have been made regarding refinements in
signaling games (Banks, Camerer, and Porter 1994; Brandts and Holt
1993).
(5.) See Park (2001), Willinger and Ziegelmeyer (1999), Sonnemans,
Schram, and Offerman (1998), and Andreoni (1995) for empirical
comparisons of positive- and negative-externality environments.
(6.) This environment is based on the moral hazard in group
experiments conducted by Spraggon (2002).
(7.) Instructions and the payoff table are provided on the lead
author's Web site: http://www.umass.edu/resec/
faculty/spraggon/index.shtml.
(8.) Natural examples of this cost are pollution generated from the
individual production decisions of individual firms or individuals in
work teams free riding on the efforts of others in the team.
(9.) We could also consider the possibility that subjects are
maximizing utility functions, which include variables other than their
own payoff. In a similar environment, Spraggon (2004b) suggests that
alternate preferences are not appropriate.
(10.) In general, subjects may have been familiar with each other
having taken courses together. We are not concerned that implicit
cooperation is an issue here as no groups were able to coordinate on the
group optimal outcome of all subjects choosing zero.
(11.) The experimental sessions were conducted by research
assistants and not professors with whom participants may have had
contact in their game theory courses.
(12.) We thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing out that the
optimal decisions 25 and 50 are likely focal points for subjects, which
makes finding significant differences between sophisticated and
unsophisticated subjects less likely.
(13.) Since everyone in the group pays the same fine, choosing
higher numbers results in higher relative payoffs for the subjects
choosing larger numbers.
(14.) In a similar vein, Charness, Frechette, and Kagel (2004) find
that behavior in gift exchange experiments is sensitive to the
presentation of payoff tables, which more overtly indicate
payoff-maximizing decisions.
(15.) Levitt and List (2007) make a related point regarding
external validity and field experiments.
(16.) Potters and van Winden (2000) suggest that the decisions of
professionals are more consistent with the Nash equilibrium than those
of students in a lobbying game.
JOHN M. SPRAGGON and ROBERT J. OXOBY *
* The authors thank Bill Morrison for his comments and suggestions
and Emily Birtwell and Kendra McLeish for valuable research assistance.
J.M.S. acknowledges financial support from the Social Science and
Humanities Research Council of Canada. R.J.O. acknowledges financial
support from the W. E. Upjohn Institute for Employment Research and the
Institute for Advanced Policy Research (University of Calgary).
Spraggon: Associate Professor, Department of Resource Economics,
University of Massachusetts Amherst, 80 Campus Center Way, Amherst, MA
01003. Phone 413-545-6651, Fax 413-545-5853, E-mail jmspragg@
resecon.umass.edu
Oxoby: Associate Professor, Department of Economics, University of
Calgary, 2500 University Drive NW, Calgary, AB, Canada T2N IN4. Phone
403-220-2586, Fax 403-282-5262, E-mail
[email protected]
TABLE 1
Mean Aggregate Decision Numbers (X) by Treatment.
Instrument Unsophisticated Sophisticated Total
Tax
Mean (a) 209.96 * 153.07 175.41
SE 7.43 2.24 10.77
n (b) 3 5 8
Tax/Subsidy
Mean (a) 181.37 152.13 164.66
SE 17.34 4.35 9.13
n (b) 3 4 7
Total
Mean (a) 195.67 152.65 169.86
SE 10.59 2.14 7.02
n (b) 6 9 15
Note: SE: standard error.
(a) Mean of the mean aggregate decision number for each
treatment over the number of sessions.
(b) Number of observations.
* indicates that the mean is significantly different from
the target of 150 at the 5% level.
TABLE 2
Median Aggregate Decision Numbers by
Treatment
Treatment Unsophisticated Sophisticated Total
Tax
Median (a) 205 * 150 153
SE (b) 9.49 1.20 11.46
n (c) 3 5 8
Tax/Subsidy
Median (a) 199 150 150
SE (b) 21.20 1.25 10.61
n (c) 3 4 7
Total
Median (a) 202 150 150
SE (b) 12.17 0.92 7.71
n (c) 6 9 15
(a) Median of the median aggregate decision number for
each treatment over the number of sessions.
(b) Standard error based on the mean of the medians.
(c) Number of observations.
* indicates that the median is significantly different
from the target of 150 at the 5%. level.
TABLE 3 Analysis of Variance for Median Aggregate Results
Source Partial df MS F Probability
SS > F
Model 7,888.30 3 2,629.43 11.74 .0009
Instrument 780.84 1 780.30 3.49 .0887
Participant type 6,643.53 1 6,643.53 29.67 .0002
Instrument x type 684.38 1 684.38 3.06 .l082
Residual 2,462.97 11 223.91
Total 10,351.26 14 739.38
Number of
observations 15
[R.sup.2] 0.7621
Root mean squared
error 14.96
Adjusted [R.sup.2] 0.6971
Note: Partial SS: partial sum of squares; df degrees of freedom;
MS: mean square; F: standard F-test.
TABLE 4
Individual Results by Five-Period Groups and Treatment
Period
Treatment 1-5 6-10 11-15
Large capacity, Tax, Mean 55.2 53.37 59.03
unsophisticated SE 4.15 2.85 3.07
(n = 30) Median 57.5 50 57.5
Mode 90 50 60
Large capacity, Tax, Mean 45.96 50.06 47.52
sophisticated (n = 50) SE 0.87 1.36 0.816
Median 50 50 50
Mode 50 50 50
Medium capacity, Tax, Mean 46.97 47.43 48.67
unsophisticated SE 3.25 3.42 3.17
(n = 30) Median 50 46.50 48
Mode 50 50 40
Medium capacity, Tax, Mean 29.72 29.34 29.24
sophisticated SE 1.33 1.61 1.09
(n = 50) Median 25 25 25
Mode 25 25 25
Large capacity, Mean 53.5 53.57 47.7
Tax/Subsidy, SE 3.77 3.37 3.26
unsophisticated Median 51 51.50 41.50
(n = 30) Mode 50 65 37.4
Large capacity, Mean 49.96 49.33 47.95
Tax/Subsidy, SE 1.52 0.857 0.622
sophisticated Median 50 50 50
(n = 50) Mode 50 50 50
Medium capacity, Mean 46.37 39.4 34.03
Tax/Subsidy, SE 4.48 2.92 3.80
unsophisticated Median 42.5 40 40
(n = 30) Mode 40.50 40 50
Medium capacity, Mean 25.3 31.58 26.5
Tax/Subsidy, SE 3.10 3.12 1.14
sophisticated Median 25 25 25
(n = 50) Mode 25 25 25
Period
Treatment 16-20 21-25 Total
Large capacity, Tax, Mean 56.33 56.37 56.06
unsophisticated SE 2.54 3.23 1.43
(n = 30) Median 50 51.5 50
Mode 50 49.70 50
Large capacity, Tax, Mean 47.24 47.72 47.70
sophisticated (n = 50) SE 0.793 0.660 0.422
Median 50 50 50
Mode 50 50 50
Medium capacity, Tax, Mean 48.83 52.70 48.92
unsophisticated SE 2.25 2.56 1.32
(n = 30) Median 50 50 50
Mode 50 50 50
Medium capacity, Tax, Mean 28.10 27.78 28.84
sophisticated SE 0.726 0.681 0.510
(n = 50) Median 25 25 25
Mode 25 25 25
Large capacity, Mean 47.87 44.93 49.51
Tax/Subsidy, SE 2.43 1.87 1.36
unsophisticated Median 45 45 46
(n = 30) Mode 46 46 36.40
Large capacity, Mean 49.93 52.65 49.96
Tax/Subsidy, SE 1.11 2.61 0.680
sophisticated Median 50 50 50
(n = 50) Mode 50 50 50
Medium capacity, Mean 41.90 44.17 41.17
Tax/Subsidy, SE 3.87 4.62 1.79
unsophisticated Median 39 38.5 40
(n = 30) Mode 30 30.100 40
Medium capacity, Mean 20.83 26.33 26.11
Tax/Subsidy, SE 2.24 3.30 1.22
sophisticated Median 25 25 25
(n = 50) Mode 25 25 25