War of attrition: evidence from a laboratory experiment on market exit.
Oprea, Ryan ; Wilson, Bart J. ; Zillante, Arthur 等
I. INTRODUCTION
Young industries often undergo a process of shakeout (Gort and
Klepper 1982 and Klepper 1996), attracting excess firms and gradually
shedding them over time. More mature industries are likewise often
forced to contract in the face of recession or product specific negative
demand shocks. When an overcrowded industry is forced to shrink, which
firms exit and which ones survive? The conventional answer in economics
is that overcrowded industries tend to shed inefficient firms and retain
efficient ones. We might call this "survival of the most
efficient", a process analogous to natural selection that can
adaptively improve the efficiency of industries over time (Nelson and
Winter 1982).
Fudenberg and Tirole (1986) model firms' exit decisions in
overcrowded duopoly markets as wars of attrition and show that the
intuition of survival of the most efficient has merit even if firms have
little information regarding their costs relative to their competitors.
However, the equilibrium of their game is complex, involving a solution
to a system of differential equations. Since neither Fortune 500 chief
executive officers in the naturally occurring markets nor undergraduate
participants in laboratory markets deliberately solve differential
equations when deciding whether or not to exit a declining market, it is
an open question as to how well Fudenberg and Tirole's rational
reconstruction of the exit decision corresponds to the facts of how
people make such decisions.
We report the results of a laboratory experiment designed to answer
this question. Nearly 200 subjects in 16 sessions participated in a
total of 3,800 wars of attrition based on Fudenberg and Tirole's
model. At the beginning of each period, subjects were randomly paired
and given a private cost draw that (usually) induced negative net per
second payoffs in a shared market and positive net payoffs per second in
monopoly. Subjects then decided in real time whether and when to exit
the market, never to return. Monotonic equilibrium strategy functions
predict higher cost (inefficient) participant exit at an earlier time
than their lower cost competitor, that is, the relatively efficient
competitor survives in the market.
We find that Fudenberg and Tirole's model organizes our data
surprisingly well, especially considering its complexity. We observe
exit by the higher cost firm in 76% of cases. When differences between
the costs faced by firms are substantial, the rate of efficient exit
rises to nearly 100%. The data on exit times are likewise quite close to
the point predictions, particularly in the crucial higher portion of the
cost distribution that generally governs exit times. The median
deviation from equilibrium exit times falls to zero by the end, and on
average subjects earn payouts identical to those predicted in
equilibrium.
Our design permits tests of two other conjectures in Fudenberg and
Tirole. First our data supports Fudenberg and Tirole's core
comparative static prediction that a decrease in the ex ante likelihood
of actually being in a war of attrition leads to an increase in the
speed of exit. (1) Second, half of our sessions use costs framed as
Fixed Costs (suffered while in the market) and half use costs framed as
Opportunity Costs (earned by exiting the market). There is no evidence
that this treatment variable affects exit behavior. This isomorphism
between gains and losses, predicted by standard theory, stands in stark
contrast to evidence from previous individual decision-making
experiments suggesting asymmetries in how people react to potential
losses and potential gains.
Although wars of attrition have an important place in the game
theoretic literature, there are surprisingly few experimental studies
directly relating to them. (2,3) Bilodeau, Childs, and Mestelman (2004)
study a three-player full information war of attrition (framed as a
volunteer game) and report widespread failure of equilibrium predictions
(the predicted volunteer in a subgame perfect Nash equilibrium only
volunteers 41% of the time). Phillips and Mason (1997) consider a
quantity choice game between subjects with identical cost structures.
They vary the level of Fixed Costs between treatments and find evidence
that subjects voluntarily enter wars of attrition in an effort to drive
the other participant from the market when Fixed Costs are relatively
large. However, given that the participants have identical cost
structures, their study does not address the question of whether the
efficient firm survives.
The most closely related experimental study to ours is Horisch and
Kirchkamp (2010), which was developed independently from our article.
They find evidence of overbidding in all pay auctions (a result found
also in a number of previous all pay auction experiments) but
underbidding in wars of attrition. Our results on exit behavior match
theoretical predictions better than any of the prior war of attrition or
all pay auction experiments. What drives this closer match between
theory and experiment?
We suspect the answer lies in our experiment's unique setting
which is motivated by an important problem from the field. Unlike much
of the previous literature, our subjects do not bid explicit monetary
amounts to win a prize--they "bid" using time. This is a
feature shared with some treatments in Horisch and Kirchkamp (2010) and
like them we find little evidence of delayed exit (the war of attrition
analogue of "overbidding"). Unlike Horisch and Kirchkamp
(2010) we do not observe much underbidding either. We conjecture that
this is due to another departure of our game from those studied in the
previous literature. Subjects in our game do not compete for a fixed
prize. Rather, they receive flow payoffs and their earnings constantly
change over time. Even when a participant leaves a market (in our
Opportunity Cost treatments), she may observe her earnings increasing,
likely minimizing winner/loser effects that might tempt subjects to exit
early. We suspect that these unique features of our game (and the
problem from the field that inspired it) contribute significantly to our
theoretically consistent results.
The remainder of this article is organized as follows. In Section
II, we describe a simplified version of the Fudenberg-Tirole model.
Section III presents our experimental design, procedures, and
predictions. In Section IV we present the experimental results and
conclude in Section V.
II. MODEL
Consider the following stripped down version of Fudenberg and
Tirole (1986). (4) Firms i = 1,2 compete in a market in continuous time,
earning duopoly revenues [R.sup.D] while they do. If one firm exits the
market, the remaining firm earns monopoly revenues [R.sup.M] >
[R.sup.D] forever. Firm i incurs a fixed cost [c.sub.i] drawn
independently and privately from a common (and common knowledge) uniform
distribution U[[c.bar], [bar.c]] as long as it is in the market. Without
loss of generality assume [c.sub.1] < [c.sub.2]. Firm i's
profits at each instant are:
(1) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
Time is discounted at a rate r [member of] (0, 1). The agent's
strategy is a time [t.sub.i] at which to exit the market if her
counterpart has not yet left.
When [C.sub.1] > [R.sup.D], agents are in a war of attrition;
both suffer losses as long as they share the market yet each would
prefer the other leave first. If war of attrition is guaranteed ex ante
(if [c.bar] > [R.sup.D]), such a game notoriously has a continuum of
perfect Bayes equilibria (Riley 1980 and Nalebuff and Riley 1985).
However, by introducing a small probability that [c.sub.1] <
[R.sup.D] (accomplished by setting [c.bar] < [R.sup.D]), the set of
symmetric equilibria shrinks to one. The unique equilibrium strategy
function takes the form of a monotonically decreasing time
[T.sub.i]([c.sub.i]) at which agent i leaves the market if (and only if)
her counterpart has not yet exited. This monotonicity guarantees
survival of the most efficient; the highest cost firm is the one driven
from the market.
The intuition for this result is relatively straightforward. A firm
plans to exit at the moment when the cost of staying in the market for
another moment just equals the expected benefit. The instantaneous cost
of remaining in the market is [R.sup.D] - [C.sub.i](t) (where
[C.sub.i](t) [equivalent to] [T.sup.-1.sub.i] (t)) while the benefit is
that the competitor may leave yielding discounted returns of [[R.sup.M]
- [c.sub.i](t)]/r. The probability a competitor actually leaves in the
coming instant, conditional on not having left already, is given by the
probability that the firm faces a cost that would not induce it to exit
now but would induce it to exit in an instant. This in turn is given by
the product of the hazard rate at the cost that would induce present
exit, 1/[[c.sub.i] (t) [c.bar]], and the slope of the exit cost
function, [C'.sub.-i](t). Setting cost equal to expected benefits,
imposing symmetry and rearranging, we arrive at the following
differential equation:
(2) [C'.sub.i](t) = r[[C.sub.i](t) - [c.bar]] x [([c.sub.i](t)
- [R.sup.D])/([c.sub.i](t) - [R.sup.M])].
Finally, a firm with a cost as high as the monopoly revenue should
immediately exit the market. Firm i's strategy function,
[T.sub.i]([c.sub.i]) is therefore the inverse of the solution to (2),
subject to the boundary condition [C.sub.i](0) = [R.sup.M]. (5) This
function is strictly monotonic on [[R.sup.D], [R.sup.M]], infinite below
this range and zero above.
A core comparative static prediction of Fudenberg and Tirole (1986)
is that increasing the mass of the distribution towards [c.bar] leads to
(weakly) earlier exit times for each cost type. This is because doing so
increases the probability that one's competitor will never leave.
The uniform distribution has constant mass, ruling out an exact test of
this prediction. An analogous prediction, available under a uniform
distribution, is that a distribution with a lower value of [c.bar] will
induce earlier exit for each cost draw. Numerical results, provided in
Section III.A, indicate that this is indeed true for our parameters and
we use this fact to test the spirit of this prediction from Fudenberg
and Tirole (1986).
We have so far framed costs as fixed losses suffered by remaining
in the market. As Fudenberg and Tirole (1986) note, the model can
alternatively be described in terms of opportunity costs foregone by
remaining in the market. To be precise, changing the profit function to
(3) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
yields identical equilibrium strategy functions.
III. DESIGN, PROCEDURES, AND PREDICTIONS
We ran a total of 16 sessions each with 12 subjects (except for one
session with 10 subjects) and 20 periods of play. In each period we
randomly matched subjects into pairs to play discrete, real-time
implementations of Fudenberg and Tirole's model.
Subjects begin each period in duopoly and each can unilaterally
exit at any time prior to the period's random expiration time. In
all sessions, subjects earn revenues [R.sup.D] = 100 for each second
they spend sharing the market and [R.sup.M] = 400 for each second spent
in the market alone. Because infinite periods are impractical, we induce
impatience by instituting a 1% per-second hazard that the current second
would be the period's last (equivalent to setting a discount rate r
= 0.01). (6)
At the beginning of each period subjects are assigned an
independent cost drawn from a symmetric, common knowledge distribution.
In eight sessions costs are drawn from the Narrow cost distribution
([c.sub.i] [member of] [95,405]) and in eight further sessions they are
drawn from the Wide cost distribution ([c.sub.i] [member of] [40,460]).
(7) This between-session variation constitutes our main treatment
variable, allowing us to test Prediction 3, below.
As Fudenberg and Tirole point out, these predictions do not depend
on the type of costs faced by market participants. Opportunity Costs
waiting outside the market and Fixed Costs suffered in the market should
lead to isomorphic reactions by firms. To enable tests of this
prediction (Prediction 4, below), half of our sessions use a Fixed Cost
implementation and half use an Opportunity Cost implementation. In eight
Opportunity Cost sessions (four under each cost distribution) subjects
earn [R.sup.D] when sharing the market, [R.sup.M] when in the market
alone, and [c.sub.i] when out of the market. In eight Fixed Cost
sessions (again four under each cost distribution), subjects are
assigned 25,000 in initial capital. (8) They then earn [R.sup.D] -
[c.sub.i] for each second they spend as duopolists, [R.sup.M] -
[c.sub.i] for each second as monopolists, and 0 for each second spent
outside the market. We pose the predicted isomorphism between these
sessions as Prediction 4 below.
Half of our sessions were conducted at George Mason University in
October 2005 and half at Chapman University in April 2009 and these
locations were balanced across the treatment design. Twelve subjects
participated in each session but one (which contained 10 subjects).
Subjects were paid based on one randomly selected period and received $1
for each 3,000 points earned. Subject payments, including a $5 payment
for showing up ($7 in Chapman sessions), range from $7.75 to $33.75, and
averaged approximately $15 for sessions lasting up to 75 min.
A. The Model's Predictions and Alternatives
The model makes four main testable predictions under our
experimental design. We outline and motivate them below and conclude the
section with a discussion of their plausibility and reasonable
alternative predictions.
Most of the predictions of the model can be visualized in Figure 1
which plots numerical strategy functions derived from (2). A first and
main prediction follows directly from the monotonicity of these strategy
functions; a higher cost firm must exit before the lower cost firm,
generating an efficient pattern of exit and "survival of the most
efficient."
PREDICTION 1. Higher cost firms tend to exit the market and lower
cost firms tend to remain.
A far more stringent prediction is that subjects employ strategy
functions quantitatively similar to equilibrium ones. Testing the point
predictions is complicated by two forms of censoring in our data,
unavoidable in our design. First, period lengths are random and
sometimes end prior to either subject making an exit decision. Second,
we can only observe one exit decision per pair.
The theory provides guidance on how to form testable predictions in
the face of these complications. First, the model provides predictions
only for periods that last long enough to permit equilibrium behavior.
Therefore our predictions are necessarily specialized to periods that
last long enough to admit equilibrium exit times. Second, the theory
makes predictions about the exit times experienced by pairs of subjects.
Specifically, the timing of exit events should follow the equilibrium
strategy function of the higher cost firm. (9) Together these generate a
quantitative prediction, testable using our data.
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
PREDICTION 2. In periods long enough to admit equilibrium behavior,
the observed exit time will be close to the higher cost firm's
equilibrium strategy, plotted in Figure 1.
The strategy functions plotted in Figure 1 are distinct because the
two cost distributions have different mass below the duopoly revenue
level. The differences between these strategy functions predict a
treatment effect across sessions under our design:
PREDICTION 3. Wars of attrition resolve more quickly in Wide
distribution sessions than in Narrow distribution sessions.
Finally, Fudenberg and Tirole point out and standard economic
theory predicts that the direct losses incurred in Fixed Cost sessions
and the earnings foregone out-of-market in Opportunity Cost sessions
will induce similar behavior.
PREDICTION 4. Exit behavior is similar in Opportunity Cost and
Fixed Cost sessions.
The model's predictions are computationally demanding,
requiring agents to solve a system of differential equations and to
properly impute similar reasoning to their opponents. The literature is
littered with examples of models (e.g., the theory of competitive
equilibrium) that organize complex human decision making quite well
though not because human subjects are adroit theorists. Clearly neither
subjects nor business executives employ involved mathematics when making
timing decisions, and this is not the question posed by our experiment
(we are pretty confident our subjects were not solving differential
equations in their heads during our sessions). Rather our aim is to
learn whether Fudenberg and Tirole's model is a good description of
heuristic human decision making.
Of course the literature is also littered with examples of models
failing to predict human behavior (e.g., centipede games).
Interestingly, such a failure need not spell disaster for the
model's central prediction that efficient firms survive in markets
(Prediction 1). Even if the point predictions (Prediction 2) of the
model fail spectacularly, efficient exit will prevail as long as
strategy functions are monotonically decreasing. Other plausible
heuristics will lead to inefficient exit and a rejection of Prediction
1. For instance subjects may choose to exit without much regard to
variations in costs, hoping only to outlast their opponents. The
resulting flat strategy functions will fail to systematically weed out
inefficient subjects.
Prediction 4 rests on a fundamental isomorphism in economic theory
between explicit losses and foregone opportunities. There is some
experimental evidence showing that subjects sometimes treat the two
types of payoff possibilities quite differently and these observations
have been formalized as the theory of loss aversion (Kahneman and
Tverksy 1979, 1991). Loss aversion would seem to predict earlier exit
times under Fixed Cost sessions (where losses are explicitly suffered
while in the market) than under Opportunity Cost sessions (where gains
are simply smaller than those available outside of the market). We
consider this a reasonable alternative hypothesis to Prediction 4 and
the experiment was designed to enable a sharp test.
IV. RESULTS
As we point out in the previous section, the model only makes
predictions for periods that last long enough to admit equilibrium
behavior. We therefore restrict attention to period/pair combinations
for which equilibrium strategies are, in principle, observable. (10)
Further, to focus on the decisions of relatively experienced subjects we
focus our analysis on data from the final half (final 10 periods) of
each session.
The model's first prediction is that the higher cost firm in
any pair tends to exit the market and the lower cost firm tends to
remain. In our data higher cost firms exit the market 76% of the time
while lower cost firms exit in only 18% of pairs. The remaining 6% of
cases are censored by expiration.
In order to formally test the prediction, we examine, for each
session, the difference in rates of exit by higher and lower cost firms.
Using the difference in session level rates (high cost rate of exit
minus low cost rate of exit) as our unit of observation, we conduct
Wilcoxon signed rank tests for Narrow and Wide cost distributions
(giving us eight data points for each test). This statistic is
significantly greater than zero under both Narrow (p = .01415) and Wide
(p = .008) cost ranges. (11)
Very inefficient firms are far more likely to exit first than only
slightly inefficient firms. Figure 2 plots rates of exit for higher cost
and lower cost firms as a function of the cost difference between the
two firms in a pair. Under both Narrow and Wide cost ranges, we observe
a strong increasing (decreasing) relationship between the difference in
costs and the rate of exit by higher (lower) cost firms. Thus,
inefficient firms are more likely to exit the more inefficient they are
relative to their competitors. Efficient exit is substantially more
likely the more it enhances efficiency. (12)
RESULT 1. The higher cost firm in a pair tends to exit and the
lower cost firm tends to remain. Greater cost differences induce higher
rates of efficient exit.
The model's second prediction is that subjects exit at times
consistent with the equilibrium strategy function. As we pointed out
above, our data here are doubly censored. First, in roughly 6% of cases
the period ends before an exit decision is made. Second, we only observe
one exit time per pair. Were we to look only at observed exit times as a
function of cost, we would necessarily face a severely downward biased
sample.
We can reduce or eliminate this bias by focusing on the behavior of
the pair's higher cost subject, (13) whose decisions in both theory
and fact are generally uncensored. When we do not observe the higher
cost firm's exit decision due to censoring either by the lower cost
firm or expiration, we are provided a lower bound on the higher cost
firm's exit time. The combination of observed exit behavior and
censoring times gives us a lower bound estimate on the higher cost
firm's strategy function. Since expiration censoring is rare and
lower cost exit tends to occur when costs are similar, this lower bound
is likely to be close to the true strategy function. (14)
Figure 3 plots cumulative density functions (CDFs) of
subjects' deviations from equilibrium exit times in the final half
of periods for each treatment. The median subject moves one second too
late in the Wide treatment and two seconds too late in the Narrow
treatment. Although the median deviation is economically small in each
case, it is statistically significant under the Narrow distribution (p =
.023) and statistically insignificant under the Wide cost distribution
(p = .174). (15) The median deviation across treatments is one second in
the last half of periods. By the final quarter of periods this measure
shrinks to zero and under neither cost distribution can we reject at the
5% level the hypothesis that deviations are zero.
[FIGURE 2 OMITTED]
RESULT 2. Exit times tend to be close to predicted times. Across
treatments, the median deviation is one second in the final half of
periods and zero by the final quarter. Deviations tend to be slightly
larger under the Narrow cost distribution than under the Wide cost
distribution.
On average, observed exit times tend to be close to theoretical
predictions. How much do subjects on average actually forego by playing
observed strategies rather than precise equilibrium strategies? To find
out we look, for each subject, at the difference between expected
earnings and expected earnings from joint equilibrium play. We plot CDFs
for each treatment in Figure 4. The median earnings foregone relative to
equilibrium are less than half of a cent. The median Wide distribution
subject loses nothing (p = .201) while Narrow distribution subjects lose
a small though statistically significant (p = .034) 0.6 cents. By the
final quarter of periods, the overall median loss drops to zero and
losses are statistically insignificant at the 5% level in each cost
condition.
RESULT 3. Observed earnings are insignificantly different from
equilibrium earnings.
[FIGURE 3 OMITTED]
We now turn to treatment level tests of the model's
comparative static predictions. The model's first comparative
static prediction (Prediction 3) is that Narrow cost distributions
induce later exit than Wide cost distributions. In order to test this
prediction we compare by-session median exit times across cost
distributions. Mann-Whitney tests allow us to reject the hypothesis that
the two are equal at the 1% level (p < .001).
RESULT 4. As predicted, wars of attrition are lengthier when the
support of the cost distribution is less diffuse.
The final prediction of the theory (Prediction 4) is that behavior
in Opportunity Cost sessions is no different from behavior in Fixed Cost
sessions. Figure 3 shows that deviations from predictions tend to be
similar under each cost distribution. If anything, Fixed Cost deviations
seem to tend to be a bit larger than Opportunity Cost deviations, the
opposite of the effect suggested by loss aversion.
We conduct two statistical tests of Prediction 4. First we consider
whether the efficiency of exit is impacted by the type of cost
experienced. We examine the difference in rates of exit by higher cost
and lower cost firms for each session. Comparing session-wise medians of
these differences across Fixed and Opportunity Cost implementations with
a Wilcoxon test, we cannot reject the hypothesis that the net rate of
efficient exit is identical (p =. 172). Next, we consider whether the
timing of exit events is affected by the type of cost. We compare
by-session median exit times across Opportunity and Fixed Cost
implementations using a Mann-Whitney test and fail to reject the
hypothesis that subjects exit at the same times (p = 0.399). Thus:
RESULT 5. Exit behavior is not significantly affected by the type
of cost.
V. DISCUSSION
We examined 3,800 laboratory exit timing games conducted with
nearly 200 subjects over 16 experimental sessions at two universities.
In most duopoly pairs, the subject assigned the higher cost exited prior
to their lower cost competitor. Our results therefore support Fudenberg
and Tirole's (1986) prediction that efficient firms tend to survive
in markets.
[FIGURE 4 OMITTED]
Finer points of Fudenberg and Tirole's computationally
intensive model are surprisingly well supported by the data. The median
deviation of exit times from equilibrium predictions is very small and
earnings of the median pair are indistinguishable from counterfactual
equilibrium earnings.
The data also support two ancillary predictions. First, as the
Fudenberg-Tirole model predicts, firms engage in shorter wars of
attrition when there is a greater probability that one's rival has
no incentive to exit. Second, firms react to the potential for gain
outside of the market in a way that is nearly symmetric to the way they
react to losses suffered while in the market. That is, subject behavior
is not affected significantly by changing Fixed Costs suffered in the
market into Opportunity Costs captured by leaving the market. This
result contradicts asymmetric reactions to gains and losses observed in
a number of individual decision-making environments. Along with Rapoport
et al. (1998), our results suggest that these types of asymmetries may
be less prevalent or have a lesser impact in strategic settings.
Besides providing direct facts on an important market mechanism,
our experiment highlights the powerful predictive potential of economic
theory. Economics experiments often emphasize deviations from models,
usefully illuminating the failure of economic theory to account for
important features of individual decision making. No less illuminating
is the large body of evidence to which we contribute showing that even
mathematically involved models often usefully predict the outcomes of
human interactions.
Our experiment is conducted in real time, allowing subjects to
experience a relatively realistic simulation of the problem. While we
believe this is the appropriate way to study models with time
dimensions, it does not come without costs. Censoring, unavoidable in a
real-time implementation, allows us a credible estimate of only the
upper 2/3 of the strategy function. Future research might revisit this
model using the strategy method, perhaps yielding additional insight on
the empirical strategy function.
ABBREVIATION
CDF: Cumulative Density Function
REFERENCES
Barut, Y., D. Kovenock, and C. N. Noussair. "A Comparison of
Multiple-Unit All-Pay and Winner-Pay Auctions under Incomplete
Information." International Economic Review, 43(3), 2002, 675-708.
Bilodeau, M., J. Childs, and S. Mestelman. "Volunteering a
Public Service: An Experimental Investigation." Journal of Public
Economics, 88(12), 2004, 2839-55.
Bulow, J., and P. Klemperer. "The Generalized War of
Attrition." American Economic Review, 89(1), 1999, 175-89.
Davis, D., and R. J. Reilley. "Do Too Many Cooks Always Spoil
the Stew? An Experimental Analysis of Rent-Seeking and the Role of a
Strategic Buyer." Public Choice, 95(1-2), 1998, 89-115.
Duffy, J., and E. Hopkins. "Learning, Information, and Sorting
in Market Entry Games: Theory and Evidence." Games and Economic
Behavior, 51(1), 2005, 31-62.
Duffy, J., and J. Ochs. "Equilibrium Selection in Static and
Dynamic Entry Games." Games and Economic Behavior, 39(1), 2011,
97-116.
Fudenberg, D., and J. Tirole. "A Theory of Exit in
Duopoly." Econometrica, 54(4), 1986, 943-60.
Gneezy, U., and R. Smorodinsky. "All-Pay Auctions--An
Experimental Study." Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization,
61(2), 2006, 255-75.
Gort, M., and S. Klepper. "Time Paths in the Diffusion of
Product Innovations." Economic Journal, 92(367), 1982, 630-53.
Horisch, H., and O. Kirchkamp. "Less Fighting Than
Expected--Experiments with Wars of Attrition and All Pay Auctions."
Public Choice, 144(1-2), 2010, 347-67.
Kahneman, D., and A. Tversky. "Prospect Theory: An Analysis of
Decision under Risk." Econometrica, 47(2), 1979, 263-92.
--. "'Loss Aversion in Riskless Choice: A Reference
Dependent Model." Quarterly Journal of Economics, 106(4), 1991,
1039-61.
Klepper, S. "Entry, Exit, Growth and Innovation over the
Product Life Cycle." American Economic Review, 86(3), 1996, 562-83.
Muller, W., and A. Schotter. "Workaholics and Drop Outs in
Organizations." Journal of the European Economic Association, 8(4),
2010, 717-43.
Nalebuff, B., and J. Riley. "Asymmetric Equilibria in the War
of Attrition." Journal of Theoretical Biology, 113, 1985, 517-27.
Nelson, R., and S. Winter. An Evolutionary Theory of Economic
Change. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1982.
Oprea, R., D. Friedman, and S. Anderson. "Learning to Wait: A
Laboratory Investigation." Review of Economic Studies, 76(3), 2009,
1103-24.
Phillips, O., and C. Mason. "Wars of Attrition in Experimental
Duopoly Markets." Southern Economic Journal, 63(3), 1997, 726-42.
Potters, J., C. G. de Vries, and F. van Winden. "An
Experimental Examination of Rational Rent-Seeking." European
Journal of Political Economy, 14(4), 1998, 783-800.
Rapoport, A., D. Seale, I. Erev, and J. Sundali. "Equilibrium
Play in Large Group Market Entry Games." Management Science, 44(1),
1998, 119-41.
Rapoport, A., D. Seale, and E. Winter. "Coordination and
Learning Behavior in Large Groups with Asymmetric Players." Games
and Economic Behavior, 39(1), 2002, 111-36.
Riley, J. "Strong Evolutionary Equilibirum and the War of
Attrition." Journal of Theoretical Biology, 82(3), 1980, 383-400.
Selten, R., and W. Guth. "Equilibrium Point Selection in a
Class of Market Entry Games," in Games, Economic Dynamics, and Time
Series Analysis, edited by M. Diestler, E. Ftirst, and G. Schwadiauer.
Cambridge, MA: Physica-Verlag, 1982.
Sundali, J., A. Rapoport, and D. Seale. "Coordination in
Market Entry Games with Symmetric Players." Organizational Behavior
and Human Decision Processes, 64(2), 1995, 203-18.
SUPPORTING INFORMATION
Additional Supporting Information may be found in the online
version of this article:
Appendix S1. Instructions and screenshot (for OCL sessions).
Figure S1. Screenshot for the OCL sessions.
Figure S2. Screenshot for the FCL sessions
(1.) Horisch and Kirchkamp (2010) report a similar comparative
static result.
(2.) While there are few experimental studies directly related to
wars of attrition, there are some that examine all-pay auctions (e.g.,
Davis and Reilley 1998; Potters, de Vries, and van Winden 1998; Barut,
Kovenock, and Noussair 2002; Gneezy and Smorodinsky 2006; and Muller and
Schotter 2010). Though Bulow and Klemperer (1999) show that the two are
theoretically isomorphic, Horisch and Kirchkamp (2010) provide evidence
that they, in fact, generate very different behaviors.
(3.) Another strand of related literature involves the market entry
game, described in Selten and Guth (1982), in which n potential entrants
compete for a market with capacity of c where n > c. Experimental
work on behavior in this game includes Sundali, Rapoport, Seale (1995),
Rapoport et al. (1998), Rapaport, Seale, and Winter (2002), Duffy and
Hopkins (2005), and Duffy and Ocbs (2011). While related to wars of
attrition, the market entry experiments differ because they primarily
focus on behavior in static games. However, the results of this strand
of literature suggest that aggregate behavior tends to be consistent
with Nash equilibrium, subjects behave similarly in the domain of gains
and losses, and if entry costs are asymmetric there is an inverse
relationship between entry costs and probability of entry.
(4.) Fudenberg and Tirole provide analogous results for firms
facing a more general class of cost distributions and time varying
revenues.
(5.) Another available boundary condition is that firms with costs
equal to duopoly profits should never exit meaning [MATHEMATICAL
EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
(6.) Instructions and screenshots for the OCL and FCL sessions are
available as online supporting information.
(7.) These cost distributions (a) satisfy the necessary condition
for uniqueness of equilibrium in FT given our parameters of [R.sup.M] =
400 and [R.sup.D] = 400 and furthermore (b) allow some separation
between the predicted equilibrium exit times for subjects who draw the
same cost under different cost treatments. The mean of each is the mean
of the duopoly and monopoly revenues meaning, in equilibrium, subjects
were equally likely to exit instantly and to never exit at all.
(8.) The starting capital is calibrated to cover equilibrium
duopoly losses given randomly determined period lengths.
This calibration worked well; in only three cases did a subject
exhaust this capital and all three cases occurred prior to period 10. In
these cases subjects were forced out of the market as it is infeasible
to allow subjects to earn negative cash amounts.
(9.) Jointly, these two restrictions mean that we will have access
to data on the strategy function for, roughly, the upper 2/3 of the cost
function. As it turns out this is the most important part of the
strategy function as it is the part most likely to govern the timing of
the exit event.
(10.) Expiration times are exogenous, unknowable to subjects and
uncorrelated with observables such as cost. This method of sampling
therefore does not introduce any new source of bias and has been used in
previous work (see, e.g.. Oprea, Friedman, and Anderson 2009).
(11.) We pool Fixed and Opportunity Cost sessions to fully take
advantage of our factorial design and to permit higher power tests. As
we show below (and as predicted) there are no significant differences
between Fixed and Opportunity Cost sessions.
(12.) This is precisely the pattern expected with any noisy
implementation of the strategy function.
(13.) Note that subjects do not know whether they are the higher
cost subject in any given period and in general a subject will be the
high cost and the low cost subject multiple times in the experiment.
Thus estimates of the higher cost subject's strategy function also
function as estimates of the latent strategy utilized by lower cost
subjects.
(14.) Other research, notably Horisch and Kirchkamp (2010) and
Muller and Schoner (2010), has examined bifurcation strategies in games
with continuous best response functions. We find no such evidence of
bifurcation in our data, though the discovery of such strategies is
limited by the censoring of the data. Additionally, the range of cost
values we use is larger than in these studies which may lead to subjects
using more than one cost as a point at which they alter their strategy.
(15.) In order to provide a conservative test of the null
hypothesis that deviations from predicted exit times are zero, we
examine the eight by-session median deviations of resolution times from
predicted times for each cost distribution. We conduct Wilcoxon tests
using these completely independent samples.
Oprea: Associate Professor, Department of Economics, University of
California--Santa Cruz, Santa Cruz, CA 95064. Phone 1-604-822-2408, Fax
1-604-822-5915, E-mail
[email protected]
Wilson: Donald P. Kennedy Endowed Chair of Economics and Law,
Economic Science Institute, Chapman University, Orange, CA 92866. Phone
1-714-628-7306. Fax 1-714-628-2881, E-mail
[email protected]
Zillante: Associate Professor, Department of Economics, University
of North Carolina Charlotte, Charlotte, NC 28223. Phone 1-704-687-7589,
Fax 1-704-687-1384, E-mail
[email protected]
doi: 10.1111/ecin.12014