Debt default and the insurance of labor income risk.
Athreya, Kartik B. ; Tam, Xuan S. ; Young, Eric R. 等
All of these results are obtained without recalibrating the model.
To ensure that our findings are not particularly sensitive to this
strategy, we also recalibrate the model for different values of p and
[sigma], to the extent that this recalibration is possible; Table 1
contains the new parameter values that best fit the targets under
alternative settings. By doing so, we attempt to shut off the extensive
margin, although we are not completely successful. When we recalibrate,
we find that with high EIS all welfare gains from eliminating default
are substantially reduced, with both noncollege types now barely
benefiting at all (see Table 4), while for high risk aversion the
welfare gains increase slightly. As noted above, this welfare change is
entirely due to the shifts in the pricing function that higher EIS
and/or higher risk aversion engender. Thus, for no parameter combination
that we consider do we observe welfare gains from retaining the default
option.
Table 4 Welfare Gains (with Recalibration)
[sigma] =2& EIS = 0.5 College High School Non-High School
DM [right arrow] SM 1.21% 0.54% 0.52%
[sigma] = 2 & EIS = 0.67 College High School Non-High School
DM [right arrow] SM 0.28% 0.05% 0.04%
[sigma] = 5 & EIS = 0.5 College High School Non-High School
DM [right arrow] SM 1.28% 0.57% 0.56%
A summary of findings thus far is that default significantly
worsens allocations for income risk and preference parameters that are
empirically plausible for U.S. data, as well as for more extreme values
of preference parameters within the class of Epstein-Zin non-expected
utility preferences. We turn now to the question of whether such
policies continue to remain desirable under two additional (and more
substantial) departures from the settings studied so far.
Is the Standard Model Ever Worse?
We begin this section by allowing for the underlying volatility of
income to be driven by relatively more and less persistent income
shocks. For this experiment, we hold the unconditional variance of labor
income fixed and vary the relative contributions of the persistent
component e and the transitory component v. We then ask whether a
relaxation in the household's understanding of the probabilistic
structure of earnings risk can open the door for welfare-improving
default. For this experiment, we allow for households to display
ambiguity aversion in the sense of Klibanoff, Marinacci, and Mukerji
(2009). (20)
The Roles of Persistent and Transitory Income Risk
It has long been known that self-insurance, and therefore also the
benefit of insurance markets, hinges critically on the persistence of
the risks facing households. As a general rule, the more persistent are
shocks, the more difficult they are to deal with via the accumulation of
assets in good times and decumulation and borrowing in bad times. In
contrast, purely transitory income shocks can typically be smoothed
effectively. In a pure life-cycle model, however, there are additional
impediments to self-insurance: Young households are born with no wealth
and often face incentives to borrow arising from purely intertemporal
considerations. In particular, those with relatively high levels of
human capital, especially the college-educated, can expect age-earnings
profiles with a significant upward slope into late middle age. As a
result, such households would like to borrow even in the absence of any
shocks to income, often substantially, against their growing expected
future income. In contrast, those households with low human capital face
a far less income-rich future, and as a result borrow primarily to deal
with transitory income risk.
In order to understand the role that the persistence of income risk
plays in the welfare gains or losses arising from U.S.-style bankruptcy
and delinquency, we now evaluate the effects of changes in the
persistent component of household income risk for all three classes of
households. However, in order to avoid conflating persistence and
overall income volatility, we adjust the variance of transitory income
volatility such that the overall variance of log labor income remains
constant. (21) Figure 10 and Tables 5 and 6 present the welfare and
consumption smoothing implications of the standard model under varying
income shock persistence. The first column of each table documents the
fraction of total variance contributed by the persistent component.
[FIGURE 10 OMITTED]
Table 5 Consumption Smoothing (DM)
Intra Inter Total
Coll HS NHS Coll HS NHS Coll HS
1.0% 0.0306 0.0462 0.0575 0.0359 0.0364 0.0386 0.0665 0.0826
10.0% 0.0377 0.0561 0.0872 0.0343 0.0367 0.0357 0.0720 0.0938
20.0% 0.0459 0.0807 0.1092 0.0336 0.0347 0.0325 0.0795 0.1154
30.0% 0.0538 0.0884 0.1367 0.0327 0.0327 0.0297 0.0865 0.1211
40.0% 0.0619 0.1013 0.1472 0.0316 0.0301 0.0280 0.0925 0.1314
50.0% 0.0700 0.1146 0.1613 0.0305 0.0284 0.0263 0.1005 0.1430
60.0% 0.0779 0.1280 0.1797 0.0294 0.0264 0.0241 0.1065 0.1544
70.0% 0.0859 0.1413 0.1992 0.0283 0.0247 0.0224 0.1141 0.1660
80.0% 0.0946 0.1543 0.2182 0.0272 0.0231 0.0211 0.1218 0.1774
90.0% 0.1053 0.1681 0.2368 0.0258 0.0212 0.0199 0.1311 0.1893
99.0% 0.1248 0.1863 0.2566 0.0235 0.0187 0.0180 0.1483 0.2050
Coll NHS
1.0% 0.0306 0.0961
10.0% 0.0377 01229
20.0% 0.0459 0.1417
30.0% 0.0538 0.1664
40.0% 0.0619 0.1752
50.0% 0.0700 0.1876
60.0% 0.0779 0.2038
70.0% 0.0859 0.2216
80.0% 0.0946 0.2393
90.0% 0.1053 0.2567
99.0% 0.1248 0.2680
Table 6 Consumption Smoothing (SM)
Intra Inter Total
Coll HS NHS Coll HS NHS Coll HS
1.0% 0.0196 0.0307 0.0474 0.0318 0.0314 0.0120 0.0514 0.0621
10.0% 0.0271 0.0397 0.0577 0.0315 0.0298 0.0124 0.0586 0.0695
20.0% 0.0360 0.0541 0.0771 0.0311 0.0290 0.0131 0.0671 0.0831
30.0% 0.0444 0.0683 0.0971 0.0306 0.0284 0.0137 0.0750 0.0967
40.0% 0.0524 0.0820 0.1173 0.0300 0.0277 0.0144 0.0824 0.1097
50.0% 0.0600 0.0951 0.1364 0.0295 0.0271 0.0151 0.0895 0.1222
60.0% 0.0673 0.1076 0.1550 0.0291 0.0267 0.0158 0.0964 0.1343
70.0% 0.0743 0.1197 0.1729 0.0288 0.0262 0.0164 0.1031 0.1495
80.0% 0.0811 0.1314 0.1903 0.0285 0.0258 0.0171 0.1096 0.1627
90.0% 0.0878 0.1428 0.2072 0.0282 0.0255 0.0178 0.1160 0.1638
99.0% 0.0935 0.1528 0.2218 0.0280 0.0253 0.0182 0.1215 0.1781
Coll NHS
1.0% 0.0196 0.0594
10.0% 0.0271 0.0801
20.0% 0.0360 0.0902
30.0% 0.0444 0.1108
40.0% 0.0524 0.1317
50.0% 0.0600 0.1515
60.0% 0.0673 0.1708
70.0% 0.0743 0.1893
80.0% 0.0811 0.2075
90.0% 0.0878 0.2250
99.0% 0.0935 0.2400
Normatively, three findings are noteworthy. First, and perhaps most
importantly, the standard model displays higher welfare irrespective of
the nature of shocks accounting for observed income volatility. This
result strengthens our findings thus far, and it further suggests that
defaultable debt is simply unlikely to be useful to households. It is
also a particularly important form of robustness, given both the general
importance of persistence for the efficacy of self-insurance and
borrowing and because estimates of income shock persistence vary
dramatically--see Guvenen (2007), Hryshko (2008), or Guvenen and Smith
(2009) for discussions of the debate between so-called "restricted
income profiles" (RIP), in which all households draw earnings from
a single stochastic process, and "heterogeneous income
profiles" (HIP), in which households vary in the processes from
which they derive earnings. This debate has implications for models like
ours because these two models differ, sometimes strongly, in the
persistence of earnings shocks their structure implies. Most recent work
now suggests that income-process parameters vary over the life cycle as
well (Karahan and Ozkan 2009).
Second, the effect of the contribution of persistent shocks to
income volatility depends on the education level of households. In
particular, when volatility is driven primarily by persistent shocks,
the relatively well-educated benefit from the elimination of default
substantially more than their less-educated counterparts. Conversely,
when most income variability is driven by large but transitory shocks,
it is the relatively less-educated who benefit most from the elimination
of the default option. The intuition for this result comes from the
nature of borrowing: College types borrow primarily to use future
expected income today while less-educated types borrow to smooth shocks
Third, within each educational class, the welfare losses from
default decline monotonically as the relative contribution of the
persistence of the shock grows; default on debt is least (most) useful
when income volatility is driven primarily by shocks that are transitory
(persistent). What is surprising, but in keeping with the main theme of
our results, is that in no case is it true that U.S.-style default is ex
ante more desirable than allocations obtaining under the standard model.
Moreover, even in the case where essentially all income risk is
delivered in the form of persistent shocks where credit markets are
least useful in dealing with income risk, outcomes that allow for
default are worse for agents than those arising in the standard model.
The welfare in the standard model is non-trivially higher, at up to 1.24
percent of consumption for college-educated households (as seen in
Figure 10).
In Figures 11 and 12 we display the measure of borrowers at each
age and the conditional mean of debt among those who borrow for two
levels of the importance of persistent income risk.22 The fact that the
losses from allowing default rise for all agent types with the
importance of transitory shocks is a consequence of the increased
usefulness of credit in dealing with transitory income risk. Conversely,
when shocks are primarily persistent, a negative realization requires
more frequent borrowing and leads, all else equal, to more debt in
middle age; the combination is ultimately unable to stern the transfer
of income risk to consumption volatility. In Tables 5 and 6, we see
that, irrespective of default policy, persistence translates into higher
consumption volatility, and that the presence of lax default policy seen
in Table 6 does little to stem the flow of income risk into consumption
risk (echoing our previous result in Athreya, Tam, and Young [2009]).
[FIGURE 11 OMITTED]
[FIGURE 12 OMITTED]
We turn next to the relationship between shock persistence and
equilibrium default rates, displayed in Figure 13. Default is
"U-shaped," with high default rates at both ends. To
understand this shape, consider first the case where the labor income
shocks are nearly all transitory (the left side of the graph). Here,
agents can generally manage their risk effectively via saving and
dissaving, but they choose to augment the self-insurance mechanism with
default at higher rates than they do in the benchmark setting. The
reason they do so is that risk-based pricing is not effective here,
because there is no useful information contained in the current labor
income of the borrower that would identify future bad risks. In
contrast, in the case where labor income is driven entirely by the
persistent component (the right side of the graph), high default is the
result of agents being generally unable to smooth consumption;
persistent shocks are hard to smooth using assets alone (and if
permanent are in fact impossible). As a result, despite the pricing
effects, borrowers will use default relatively often (and pay the costs
to do so). The middle parts of the graph, where default is lowest,
balance these two effects.
[FIGURE 13 OMITTED]
Intuitively, in the standard model, borrowers realize that debt
must be repaid, and under high persistence, heavy borrowing in response
to a negative shock makes low future consumption relatively likely.
Nonetheless, credit markets are willing to lend to such households at
the risk-free rate (adjusted for any transactions costs of
intermediation), making total debt rise. When default is available,
borrowing today to deal with persistent income risk does not expose the
borrower to severe consumption risk in the long term as default offers
an "escape valve," but it does expose lenders to severe credit
risk in the near term. Creditors then price debt accordingly; as seen in
Figure 14, when shocks are primarily persistent, as the current shock
deteriorates so do the terms at which borrowers can access credit.
Moreover, under a bad current realization of income, households facing
persistent risk see a disproportionate decline in the price of any debt
they may issue, while the reverse occurs in the event of a good current
realization of income; the pricing functions essentially "switch
places."
[FIGURE 14 OMITTED]
Yet, despite the increased sensitivity of loan pricing to the
borrower's current income state under relatively high persistence,
the welfare gains under the SM, though still positive, fall. This result
obtains because of the reduction in the ability of self-insurance,
inclusive of borrowing, to prevent income fluctuations from affecting
consumption. To sum up, income risk is quantitatively relevant in
governing the losses conferred by default, but irrelevant for altering
the qualitative welfare property that, in the absence of expense shocks,
the default option lowers welfare.
Ambiguity Aversion
We turn next to the question of whether default can improve
outcomes when households are not perfectly certain about the
probabilistic structure of income risk. Households that face ambiguity
are uncertain about the probability process for their incomes; if
ambiguity-averse, these households behave pessimistically and therefore
adopt views about their income that would, for example, imply that it
would mean-revert more slowly from low realizations. In such a
situation, borrowing to smooth away temporary falls may not be optimal,
since asset decumulation is not effective against permanent shocks, and
therefore in the absence of a default option households may be unwilling
to do so. In contrast, if default is an option, the household may be
willing to borrow since, even if their pessimism is validated,
consumption can be protected via discharge. We formalize this idea, as
in Klibanoff, Marinacci, and Mukerji (2009), by assuming agents are
averse to ambiguity. In this formulation, a household of age j solves
the dynamic programming problem
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
EU = [[SIGMA].sub.e', v', [lambda]']
[[pi].sub.e](e'|e) [[pi].sub.v] (v') [[pi].sub.[lambda]]
([lambda]' | [lambda]) x V (b, y, e', v', [lambda]',
j + 1) (10)
subject to budget constraints, (1) and (3), where ([empty set])(*)
is given as follows:
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
determines preferences over ambiguity. [eta] [greater than or equal
to] 0 controls the attitude toward ambiguity; as [eta] increases, the
household becomes more averse to ambiguous stochastic processes. The
restrictions on the choices of p (e', v' | e, v) are that they
must sum to 1 for each (e, v) and every element must lie in some set P
[subset] [0, 1]; we nest the standard model by setting the P to be an
arbitrarily small interval around the objective probabilities. (23) We
use to denote objective probabilities and p to denote subjective ones;
note that households are assumed to be uncertain only about the
distribution of income shocks, not the process for [lambda].
Because we are interested in these preferences only to the extent
that they may provide an environment in which relatively low-cost
default and debt discharge are welfare-enhancing, we will deliberately
take the most extreme case of [eta] = [infinity], yielding the max-min
specification from Epstein and Schneider (2003):
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
EU = [[SIGMA].sub.e', v', [lambda]'] p (e',
v' | e, v) x [[pi].sub.[lambda]] V (b, y, e', v',
[lambda]', j + 1)
V (b, y, e', v', A', j + i) = (i - d (e',
v', [lambda]')) v (b, y, e', v', [lambda]', j +
i) + d(e', v', [lambda]') [v.sup.D] (0, y, e',
v', [lambda]', j + 1), (11)
where
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
EU = [[SIGMA].sub.e', v', [lambda]'] p (e',
v' | e, v) x [[pi].sub.[lambda]] ([lambda]' | [lambda])v (0,
y, e', v', [lambda]', j + 1) (12)
is the value of default.
The min operator that appears in front of the summation reflects
the agent's aversion to uncertainty; as shown by Epstein and
Schneider (2003), a household who is infinitely uncertainty-averse
chooses the subjective distribution of future events that is least
favorable and then makes their decisions based on that subjective
distribution. The size of the set of possible processes P measures the
amount of ambiguity agents face; a typical [p.sub.ij] element lies in
the interval [[p.sub.1.sup.ij], [p.sub.2.sup.ij]] [subset] [0, 4] (24)
Standard ambiguity aversion models imply that households will learn
over time and reject stochastic processes that are inconsistent with
observed data (for example, a household who initially entertains the
possibility of permanently receiving the worst possible income level
forever will dismiss this process as soon as one non-worst realization
occurs). For simplicity, we will focus our attention on a special case
of extreme ambiguity aversion in which this learning does not occur; if
default is not useful in this environment, it is likely of less use to
households than when they face less uncertainty over time. The intuition
is that the income process we buffet agents with is a non-unit process.
To the extent that households would realize by a certain age that the
data they've received makes unit-root earnings unlikely, they would
be able to rule out such a persistent process and thereby smooth more
effectively, and as a result, may not value default as much as someone
viewing shocks as permanent.
Given the qualifications and considerations discussed above, we now
evaluate outcomes in the standard model in the case where P = [0, 1],
the most extreme case possible (households behave as if the minimum
income draw will be realized with probability 1 next period). The
intuition is that such a case offers the possibility, discussed at the
outset, that lax penalties for default might actually encourage the use
of credit for consumption in a setting where the agent's aversion
to ambiguity would otherwise preclude becoming indebted. And in fact, we
do find that this case delivers default as welfare-improving for some
agents (see Table 7). However, this finding is very limited: Benchmark
default costs improve welfare for only the college type and the welfare
gain is tiny (under 0.2 percent of consumption). As a result,
unconditional ex ante welfare is negative since college types are not a
large enough group to overcome the losses to the remainder of the
population. It is interesting to see, however, that the welfare changes
from allowing default are now reversed--the largest gains are
experienced by the most educated, while the least educated suffer more.
Part of the intuition for this result is that it is the best educated
who face the steepest mean age-earnings profiles. Therefore, these
agents would have the strongest purely intertemporal motives to borrow,
absent any ambiguity. Low default costs mitigate the effect of ambiguity
and allow for states in which a temporarily unlucky college-educated
agent would find borrowing desirable.
Table 7 Welfare Effects Under Ambiguity Aversion
P = [0, 1] Non-High School High School College
DM [right arrow] SM 0.215% 0.189% -0.185%
P = min(1, [pi] + 0.5) Non-High School High School College
DM [right arrow] SM 0.296% 0.219% 0.044%
Pricing is presented in Figures 15 and 16. Notice that for the low
realization of e, the pricing function under ambiguity aversion is
everywhere below the baseline expected utility case, but for the higher
realization they switch places; ambiguity-averse agents with high income
actually pose less of a default risk. The difference in pricing stems
only from a difference in the households' willingness to default
next period for a given b. Since default has a fixed cost component
([DELTA]), households want to time their usage of default; in
particular, households must balance the gains from defaulting tomorrow
from those arising from waiting until additional shocks have been
realized. This fact places the expectations of income in periods after
tomorrow at the heart of the timing of default decisions, and here
households who face ambiguity about the income process act quite
differently from those in the benchmark economy. (25)
[FIGURE 15 OMITTED]
[FIGURE 16 OMITTED]
Take first the household with low e. For a "rational
expectations" household, income in the distant future is expected
to be better than whatever is realized tomorrow, as e is persistent but
mean-reverting; for the household facing ambiguity, however, income is
actually expected to be no better, or even worse, than tomorrow's
realization. Since ambiguity-averse households do not think the future
will be better, they may as well default next period if the realization
of income is bad; lenders must therefore offer them higher interest
rates to break even. In contrast, the ambiguity-averse household with
higher e views a realization near the mean for next period as
unexpectedly good, but does not expect better times in the more-distant
future. Default in the next period is therefore not as valuable as
waiting for a future period when those bad states are expected to occur.
In contrast, without ambiguity a bad realization will induce the
household to substantially revise their future expectations downward,
making default today more attractive (the decline in future income makes
the fixed cost of default worth paying). (26) The result is that
ambiguity-averse households with high current income obtain better
terms.
Is such extreme ambiguity aversion "reasonable?" It seems
highly unlikely that households entertain a stochastic process in which
they receive the worst possible outcome forever with probability one as
reasonable, at least not for long--after all, they need only observe the
fact that their income is occasionally higher than the lower bound to
discard this process empirically. As we noted above, we could introduce
this learning into the model--since the households are simply learning
about an exogenous process, it can be done "offline"--but it
is computationally quite burdensome to condition the set of permissive
stochastic processes on the history of observations. (27) It is also the
case that this extreme ambiguity leads to a discrepancy between model
and data in terms of borrowing patterns; there is far too little debt,
which lessens our interest in making this economy "more
realistic." If we consider smaller limits for P, such as 10 percent
above or below the objective value, we find that default is
welfare-reducing for all education levels. Thus, while ambiguity
aversion provides a theoretical foundation for default options, it does
not appear to provide an empirically tenable one.
3. CONCLUDING REMARKS
We have studied the efficacy of default in helping households
better insure labor income risk in a large range of settings in which
risk aversion, intertemporal smoothing motives, income risk, and
uncertainty--and attitudes to uncertainty--over income risk itself were
all varied. Our findings here suggest that within the broad class of
models used thus far to develop quantitative theory for unsecured
consumer credit and default, relatively generous U.S.-style default does
not appear to be capable of providing protection against labor income
risk.
Despite the fact that we find that labor income risk is not well
hedged from the ex ante perspective, we also show that there are ex post
beneficiaries from allowing default as it currently is; specifically, we
show that the standard model generates a positive measure of agents ex
post who would vote to introduce default. Our calibrated model predicts
that these agents do not constitute a majority, though, since they are
primarily college-educated middle-aged households who have been unlucky
enough to still have significant debt. This result warrants further
investigation since it may help explain why default penalties are
becoming less stringent over time (with the exception of some aspects of
the most recent reform).
Our results also suggest that "expense" shocks or
catastrophic movements in net worth are likely to be essential to
justify the view of default as a welfare-improving social institution.
To the extent that uninsured, catastrophically large, and
"involuntary" expenditures are indeed a feature of the data, a
natural question is whether consumer default is the best way to deal
with such events. Given the nature of resource transfers created by
default and the constraints that it imposes on the young, who
disproportionately account for both the income-poor and uninsured, this
statement seems unlikely.
With respect to future work, it is worth stressing that since
expense shocks and their absence seem so important to the implications
of the class of models considered here, the value of purely empirical
work better documenting the nature of expense shocks, and their (a
priori plausible) connection to income shocks (for example, job loss
leading to insurance loss, which in turn exposes households to out of
pocket expenditures), is high. Relatedly, the pivotal role played by
borrowing costs "moving against" unlucky borrowers seems
important to independently substantiate. In the absence of such work, it
remains a possibility that the welfare findings of this article (and
essentially all others) hinges too much on an institutional arrangement
for borrowing that is inaccurate. Use of detailed household level credit
card pricing and income information seems productive.
In addition to the preceding, in light of the findings of this
article and the larger quantitative theory of consumer default, two
directions seem particularly useful. First, a more "normative"
approach that asks if observed default procedures can arise an optimal
arrangement under plausible frictions, may yield different conclusions.
One interesting example of the latter approach is the theoretical work
of Grochulski (2010), where default is shown to be one method for
decentralizing a constrained Pareto optimum in the presence of private
information. Quantifying models with default and endogenously derived
asset market structures may lead to better understanding of policy
choices in this area (such as why Europe has chosen to make default
available under very strict conditions, and social insurance generous,
while the United States has chosen the opposite).
Second, with respect to the experiments we studied, we were led to
allow for two specific preference extensions beyond CRRA expected
utility in order to accurately assess the particular tradeoffs created
by default. While we emphatically did not attempt to turn the article
into a survey of any larger variety of non-expected utility preferences,
some further extensions seem potentially important: disappointment
aversion (Gul [1991] or Routledge and Zin [2010]), deviations from
geometric discounting (Laibson 1997), habit formation (Constantinides
1990), and loss aversion (Barberis, Huang, and Santos 2001). Why these
preferences specifically? In each case, the more general preference
structure breaks the link between risk aversion and intertemporal
substitution (and generally makes risk aversion state-dependent), and
some (such as nongeometric discounting and loss aversion) provide
arguments for government intervention; there is also extensive empirical
work supporting many of them. A recent contribution to this literature
is Nakajima (2012), who investigates whether the temptation preferences
of Gul and Pesendorfer (2001) alter the consequences of default reform.
(28) We suspect other work will follow.
APPENDIX: COMPUTATIONAL CONSIDERATIONS
We make some brief points here regarding the computation of the
model. The model is burdensome to calibrate, and all programs are
implemented using Fortran95 with OpenMP messaging.
In all the models we study, the objective function (the right-hand
side of the Bellman equation) is not globally concave, since the
discrete nature of the bankruptcy decision introduces convex segments
around the point where the default option is exercised (we find that, as
in Chatterjee et al. [2007], the default decision encompasses an
interval and in our case it extends to b = - [infinity] as [delta] is
smaller than even the worst income realization). The nonconcavity poses
a problem for local optimization routines, so we approach it using a
global strategy. We use linear splines to extend the value function to
the real line and a golden section search to find the optimum, with some
adjustments to guarantee that we bracket the global solution rather than
the local one. It is straightforward to detect whether we have converged
to the local maximum at any point in the state space, as the resulting
price function will typically have an upward jump.
For the ambiguity aversion case we have a saddlepoint problem to
solve. By the saddlepoint theorem we can do the maximization and
minimization in any order; the minimization (conditional on b and d) is
a linear program that we solve using a standard simplex method
conditional on some b (as in Routledge and Zin [2009]). We then nest
this minimization within our golden section search, again with
adjustments to deal with the presence of the local maximum. For our
model, this linear program turns out to be extremely simple to
solve--the household puts as much weight as allowed on the worst
possible outcome, then as much weight as allowed on the next worst, and
so on.
To impose boundedness on the realizations of income, we approximate
both e and v by Markov chains using the approach in Floden (2008).
Having income be bounded above is convenient since it implies that there
always exists a cost of default [delta] such that bankruptcy is
completely eliminated because it becomes infeasible. Quite naturally,
bankruptcy is also likely not to occur when [delta] is high enough even
if filing is feasible for some types; in general, households with high
income are not interested in the default option in our mode1. (29)
Figure 17 shows a typical objective function for a household in our
benchmark case (expected utility with [sigma] = [p.sup.-1] = 2). The
objective function has three distinct segments. The first segment is at
the far right, where the values for both the low- and high-cost types
coincide. In this region, default is suboptimal because borrowing either
does not or barely exceeds [delta]. The second segment is at the other
end, where q (b) = 0; although impossible to see in the picture, the
low-cost default experiences slightly more utility in this region since
default is less painful. The action is all in the middle segment. For
this particular individual, the high-cost type ([[lambda].sub.L])
borrows significantly more than the low-cost type; this extra borrowing
reflects primarily the pricing function (as seen in the lower panel) and
not any particular desire to borrow. High-cost types have more implicit
collateral and are less likely to default at any given debt level, so
they face lower interest rates. As a result, high-type borrowers today
who become low-type borrowers tomorrow are a main source of default in
our model--they both have debts and are not particularly averse to
disposing of those debts through the legal system. Since type is
persistent, low-type borrowers today will not generally make the same
choice--the supply side of their credit market will contract.
[FIGURE 17 OMITTED]
Athreya is an economist at the Richmond Fed; Tam is affiliated with
the University of Cambridge; Young is an economist at the University of
Virginia. This article previously circulated under the title "Are
Harsh Punishments for Default Really Better?" We would like to
thank seminar and conference participants at UT-Austin, the Board of
Governors, the Cleveland Fed, Georgetown University, the Philadelphia
Fed, and Queen's University for comments on the earlier versions.
We thank the EQ committee, especially Huberto Ennis, for detailed
comments. Tam thanks the John Olin Foundation for financial support. The
opinions expressed here do not reflect those of the Federal Reserve
System or the Federal Reserve Bank of Richmond. All errors are the
responsibility of the authors. E-mail:
[email protected].
REFERENCES
Athreya, Kartik. 2002. "Welfare Implications of the Bankruptcy
Reform Act of 1999." Journal of Monetary Economics 49 (November):
1,567-95.
Athreya, Kartik. 2004. "Shame As It Ever Was: Stigma and
Personal Bankruptcy." Federal Reserve Bank of Richmond Economic
Quarterly 90 (Spring): 1-19.
Athreya, Kartik. 2008. "Default, Insurance, and Debt over the
Life-Cycle." Journal of Monetary Economics 55 (May): 752-74.
Athreya, Kartik, Juan M. Sanchez, Xuan Tam, and Eric R. Young.
2013. "Bankruptcy and Delinquency in a Model of Unsecured
Debt." Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis Working Paper 13-2.
Athreya, Kartik, Xuan S. Tam, and Eric R. Young. 2009.
"Unsecured Credit Markets Are Not Insurance Markets." Journal
of Monetary Economics 56 (January): 83-103.
Athreya, Kartik, Xuan S. Tam, and Eric R. Young. 2012. "A
Quantitative Theory of Information and Unsecured Credit." American
Economic Journal: Macroeconomics 4 (July): 153-83.
Ausubel, Lawrence M., and Amanda E. Dawsey. 2008. "Penalty
Interest Rates, Universal Default, and the Common Pool Problem of Credit
Card Debt." Unpublished manuscript, University of Maryland and
University of Montana.
Barberis, Nicholas, Ming Huang, and Tano Santos. 2001.
"Prospect Theory and Asset Prices." Quarterly Journal of
Economics 116 (February): 1-53.
Bewley, Truman F. 2002. "Knightian Decision Theory, Part
I." Decisions in Economics and Finance 25 (November): 79-110.
Campanale, Claudio. 2008. "Learning, Ambiguity, and Life-Cycle
Portfolio Allocation." Mimeo, Universidad de Alicante.
Carroll, Christopher D. 1997. "Buffer-Stock Saving and the
Life Cycle/Permanent Income Hypothesis." The Quarterly Journal of
Economics 112 (February): 1-55.
Chatterjee, Satyajit, P. Dean Corbae, Makoto Nakajima, and
Jose-Victor Rios-Rull. 2007. "A Quantitative Theory of Unsecured
Consumer Credit with Risk of Default." Econometrica 75 (November):
1,525-90.
Constantinides, George M. 1990. "Habit Formation: A Resolution
of the Equity Premium Puzzle." Journal of Political Economy 98
(June): 519-43.
Deaton, Angus. 1992. Understanding Consumption. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Dubey, Pradeep, John Geanakoplos, and Martin Shubik. 2005.
"Default and Punishment in General Equilibrium." Econometrica
73 (January): 1-37.
Epstein, Larry G., and Martin Schneider. 2003. "Recursive
Multiple-Priors." Journal of Economic Theory 113 (November): 1-31.
Epstein, Larry G., and Stanley E. Zin. 1989. "Substitution,
Risk Aversion, and the Temporal Behavior of Consumption Growth and Asset
Returns I: A Theoretical Framework." Econometrica 57 (July):
937-69.
Evans, David S., and Richard L. Schmalensee. 2005. Paying with
Plastic: The Digital Revolution in Buying and Borrowing. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
Fay, Scott A., Erik Hurst, and Michelle J. White. 1998. "The
Bankruptcy Decision: Does Stigma Matter?" University of Michigan
Working Paper 98-01 (January).
Floden, Martin. 2008. "A Note on the Accuracy of Markov-Chain
Approximations to Highly Persistent AR(1) Processes." Economics
Letters 99 (June): 516-20.
Friedman, Milton. 1957. A Theory of the Consumption Function.
Princeton, N. J.: Princeton University Press.
Furletti, Mark. 2003. "Credit Card Pricing Developments and
Their Disclosure." Federal Reserve Bank of Philadelphia Payment
Cards Center Discussion Paper 03-02 (January).
Grochulski, Borys. 2010. "Optimal Personal Bankruptcy Design
under Moral Hazard." Review of Economic Dynamics 13 (April):
350-78.
Gross, David B., and Nicholas S. Souleles. 2002. "An Empirical
Analysis of Personal Bankruptcy and Delinquency." Review of
Financial Studies 15 (1): 319-47.
Gul, Faruk. 1991. "A Theory of Disappointment Aversion."
Econometrica 59 (May): 667-86.
Gul, Faruk, and Wolfgang Pesendorfer. 2001. "Temptation and
Self-Control." Econometrica 69 (November): 1,403-35.
Guvenen, Fatih. 2007. "Learning Your Earning: Are Labor Income
Shocks Really Very Persistent?" American Economic Review 97 (June):
687-712.
Guvenen, Fatih, and Anthony A. Smith, Jr. 2009. "Inferring
Labor Income Risk from Economic Choices: An Indirect Inference
Approach." Mimeo, University of Minnesota and Yale University.
Hansen, Lars Peter, and Thomas J. Sargent. 2007. Robustness.
Princeton, N. J.: Princeton University Press.
Hryshko, Dmytro. 2008. "RIP to HIP: The Data Reject
Heterogeneous Labor Income Profiles." Mimeo, University of Alberta.
Hubbard, R. Glenn, Jonathan Skinner, and Stephen P. Zeldes. 1994.
"The Importance of Precautionary Motives in Explaining Individual
and Aggregate Saving." Carnegie-Rochester Conference Series on
Public Policy 40 (June): 59-126.
Huggett, Mark, Gustavo Ventura, and Amir Yaron. 2011. "Sources
of Lifetime Inequality." American Economic Review 101 (December):
2,923-54.
Jackson, Thomas H. 2001. The Logic and Limits of Bankruptcy Law.
Hopkins, Minn.: Beard Books.
Karahan, Fatih, and Serdar Ozkan. 2009. "On the Persistence of
Income Shocks over the Life Cycle: Evidence and Implications." Penn
Institute for Economic Research PIER Working Paper 09-05 (December).
Klibanoff, Peter, Massimo Marinacci, and Sujoy Mukerji. 2009.
"Recursive Smooth Ambiguity Preferences." Journal of Economic
Theory 144 (May): 930-76.
Krueger, Dirk, and Harald Uhlig. 2006. "Competitive Risk
Sharing Contracts with One-Sided Commitment." Journal of Monetary
Economics 53 (October): 1,661-91.
Laibson, David A. 1997. "Golden Eggs and Hyperbolic
Discounting." Quarterly Journal of Economics 112 (May): 443-77.
Li, Wenli, and Pierre-Daniel Sarte. 2006. "U.S. Consumer
Bankruptcy Choice: The Importance of General Equilibrium Effects."
Journal of Monetary Economics 53 (April): 613-31.
Livshits, Igor, James MacGee, and Michele Tertilt. 2011.
"Costly Contracts and Consumer Credit." Working Paper 17448.
Cambridge, Mass.: National Bureau of Economic Research (September).
Ljungqvist, Lars, and Thomas J. Sargent. 2004. Recursive
Macroeconomic Theory. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Livshits, Igor, James MacGee, and Michele Tertilt. 2007.
"Consumer Bankruptcy: A Fresh Start." American Economic Review
97 (March): 402-18.
Livshits, Igor, James MacGee, and Michele Tertilt. 2008.
"Costly Contracts and Consumer Credit." Mimeo, University of
Western Ontario and Stanford University.
Lucas, Robert E., Jr. 1987. Models of Business Cycles. Oxford:
Basil-Blackwell Ltd.
Mateos-Planas, Xavier, and Giulio Seccia. 2006. "Welfare
Implications of Endogenous Credit Limits with Bankruptcy." Journal
of Economic Dynamics and Control 30 (November): 2,081-115.
Miao, Jianjun, and Neng Wang. 2009. "Risk, Uncertainty, and
Option Exercise." Manuscript, Boston University and Columbia
University.
Nakajima, Makoto. 2012. "Rising Indebtedness and Temptation: A
Welfare Analysis." Quantitative Economics 3 (July): 257-88.
Obiols-Homs, Francesc. 2011. "On Borrowing Limits and
Welfare." Review of Economic Dynamics 14 (April): 279-94.
Pemberton, James. 1998. "Income Catastrophes and Precautionary
Saving." Mimeo, University of Reading.
Routledge, Bryan R., and Stanley E. Zin. 2009. "Model
Uncertainty and Liquidity." Review of Economic Dynamics 12
(October): 543-66.
Routledge, Bryan R., and Stanley E. Zin. 2010. "Generalized
Disappointment Aversion and Asset Prices." Journal of Finance 65
(August): 1,303-32.
Sullivan, Teresa A., Elizabeth Warren, and Jay Lawrence Westbrook.
2000. The Fragile Middle Class: Americans in Debt. New Haven, Conn.:
Yale University Press.
Tam, Xuan S. 2009. "Long-Term Contracts in Unsecured Credit
Markets." Mimeo, University of Virginia.
(1.) See, e.g., Ljungqvist and Sargent (2004, p. 577)
(2.) Miao and Wang (2009) study the decision to exercise an option
under ambiguity. Due to the presence of fixed costs, bankruptcy has
option value. We focus on a related setting but are interested in the
quantitative aspects associated with household consumption smoothing.
(3.) These preferences are a special case of the more general
ambiguity-averse preferences axiomatized by Klibanoff, Marinacci, and
Mukerji (2009).
(4.) Denoting by [y.sub.min] > 0 the lowest realization of
potential labor income and r the risk-free interest rate on debt, the
natural borrowing limit for an infinitely lived agent is given by
[[b.bar].sub.nat] [equivalent to] [y.sub.min]/r, a function that
asymptotes to--(infinity) as interest rates go to zero. Assuming a
credit card interest rate of 14 percent (the modal interest rate in
Survey of Consumer Finances data in 1983 adjusted for a measure of
realized inflation), the natural debt limit moves roughly seven times as
much as the minimum income level. For good borrowers, for whom interest
rate discounts have recently appeared (Furletti 2003; Livshits, MacGee,
and Tertilt 2008), the natural debt limit will be even more sensitive.
(5.) In our previous work we introduce a class of
"special" agents who hold large amounts of capital for the
purpose of endogenously obtaining a low, risk-free rate in the presence
of low asset holdings for the median agent. Here we ignore the general
equilibrium determination of returns and thus drop the special
households from the model because their presence is irrelevant to the
question at hand.
(6.) We approximate both e and v with finite-state Markov chains.
This approximation has the convenient property that income is bounded.
(7.) See Sullivan, Warren, and Westbrook (2000).
(8.) That is, exclusion from credit markets beyond the initial
period is not sustainable as a punishment.
(9.) We assume any savings of households who die is taxed at 100
percent and used to fund wasteful government spending.
(10.) Chatterjee et al. (2007) calibrate their model to match the
wealth distribution in the United States in a dynastic setting. As we
have argued, life-cycle considerations are important for assessing the
welfare effects of bankruptcy.
(11.) The average interest rate on credit card balances is
high--currently 14 percent--relative to more secured forms of debt. As
Evans and Schmalensee (2005) have pointed out, however, it is
straightforward to account for the interest rate after funding costs,
transactions costs, and, most crucially, default costs are taken into
account, without relying on market power distortions.
(12.) Most dynamic contracting models of limited borrower
commitment, for example, currently use implicit or explicit appeals to
public institutions with commitment to punish, in order to motivate
penalties for the value of autarky. In recent work, Krueger and Uhlig
(2006) show that the inability of the supply side of the credit market
to commit to punishments can have severe implications for the existence
of the market itself. In the "normal" case, Krueger and Uhlig
(2006) show that competition in fact collapses credit and insurance
markets completely even without informational frictions.
(13.) We want to be clear that what we call "penalties"
differs from the usage in Ausubel and Dawsey (2008), where rates imposed
after late or missed payments are labeled punitive. They attribute the
high values of such rates to a common agency problem. Modeling the
bilateral contracting problem that would arise in the presence of
noncompetitive intermediation is well beyond the goals for this article.
We are pursuing the endogenous determination of interest rate hikes for
delinquent borrowers in other work.
(14.) Similar results would obtain if the government could impose
"shame" on households by choosing values for [lambda],
provided it could make [lambda] large enough to guarantee zero default
on the equilibrium path. In our model, the Inada condition on
consumption implies that such a [lambda] always exists.
(15.) Specifically, we set v = 0.35, Y = 0.2, [empty set] = 0.03,
[DELTA] = 0.03, [xi] = 0.95, [[sigma].sub.n, [member of].sup.2] = 0.033,
[[sigma].sub.n, v.sup.2] = 0.04, [[sigma].sub.h, [member of].sup.2] =
0.025, [[sigma].sub.h, v.sup.2] = 0.021, [[sigma].sub.c, [member
of].sup.2] = 0.016, and [[sigma].sub.c, v.sup.2] = 0.014.
(16.) Consider an attempt to improve the model's prediction
for the measure of borrowers by increasing [beta]. Holding all other
parameters constant, this reduces default rates and debt-to-income
ratios for all types (and these variables are generally already too
small). To counteract this effect, one might then move [lambda] for each
type and each state. Consider first increasing both
[[lambda].sub.i.sup.H] and [[lambda].sub.i.sup.L] for one type i. While
this change would increase the default rate--default becomes less
costly--it would via a supply-side effect tend to reduce debt levels
(see Athreya [2004]). By contrast, suppose we increase
[[lambda].sub.i.sup.H] and decrease [[lambda].sub.i.sup.L]; this change
has countervailing effects on both default rates and debt levels and
default rates could rise because it becomes cheaper for H types, but
fall as it becomes more expensive for L types. A similar tension exists
for debt-to-income ratios--driving it up for one type tends to drive it
down for the other.
(17.) In the real world, "stigma" may also be a function
of aggregate default rates (an agent cares less about default if
everyone else is defaulting), in which case this invariance may break.
To analyze this case would be of interest, but it poses some challenges
with respect to calibration. We therefore defer it to future work.
(18.) The figures are drawn for the aggregate, since the results
are the same for each type qualitatively. Figures decomposed by type are
available from the authors upon request.
(19.) Our model satisfies the conditions noted in Chatterjee et al.
(2007) that imply default occurs only if current debt cannot be rolled
over: If d ([member of]', v', [lambda]') > 0 for some
[member of]', v', [lambda]', then there does not exist b
such that a + y - q (b, Y)b > 0 for total income Y.
(20.) There are connections between ambiguity aversion and the
concept of Knightian uncertainty from Bewley (2002), although the latter
concept does not permit preferences to be represented by a utility
function and is therefore hard to analyze quantitatively. There are also
connections between ambiguity aversion and robust decisionmaking as
defined by Hansen and Sargent (2007).
(21.) Athreya, Tam, and Young (2009) are primarily concerned with
the role of income variance in models of default.
(22). From the perspective of a newborn, the measure of borrowers
of a given age equals the probability of the newborn borrowing at that
age.
(23.) We do not require that the household assume that the
probabilities of the independent events are independent in every
distribution that is considered. That is, the household may be concerned
that the independence property is misspecified and therefore select a
worst-case distribution in which the events are correlated.
(24.) Hansen and Sargent (2007) provide an interpretation of P in
terms of detection probabilities.
(25.) The exposition is simpler if we refer to the expectations of
the households facing ambiguity as coinciding with the choice of p,
because the ambiguity-averse agents act as if those probabilities were
the objective ones. Of course, if one were to ask ambiguity-averse
agents about their forecasts of future income, they would use the true
objective probabilities; they just do not use these probabilities for
decisions. The proper phrasing of our statement "ambiguity-averse
agents expect low future income" would be the more cumbersome
"ambiguity-averse agents act as if they expect low future
income." We abuse the notion of expectation slightly as a result,
and beg for the reader's indulgence on this matter.
(26.) The median e has the pricing functions crossing, so that
agents who face ambiguity are more likely to default on small debts but
less likely to default on large ones.
(27.) Since this learning is not Bayesian, it can be quite
difficult to write recursively, and, in any case, learning about
discrete processes generally involves a large number of states.
Campanale (2008) investigates non-Bayesian learning in a two-state model
where the approach taken introduces only one additional state.
(28.) Nakajima (2009) finds that increasing borrowing constraints
in a model with quasi-geometric discounting is not always
welfare-improving, similar to Obiols-Homs (2011).
(29.) Households with high income realizations do not want to pay
the stigma cost (which is proportionally higher for them) even if they
are currently carrying a large amount of debt (which is very rare due to
persistence). Thus, our model does not predict any "strategic"
default, which can arise in models that rely on exclusion as a
punishment for bankruptcy.