首页    期刊浏览 2024年12月02日 星期一
登录注册

文章基本信息

  • 标题:John Powell Clayton: Religions, Reasons and Gods: Essays in Cross-Cultural Philosophy of Religion.
  • 作者:Walter, Gregory A.
  • 期刊名称:Philosophy in Review
  • 印刷版ISSN:1206-5269
  • 出版年度:2008
  • 期号:August
  • 语种:English
  • 出版社:University of Victoria
  • 摘要:Religions, Reasons and Gods: Essays in Cross-Cultural Philosophy of Religion.

John Powell Clayton: Religions, Reasons and Gods: Essays in Cross-Cultural Philosophy of Religion.


Walter, Gregory A.


John Powell Clayton

Religions, Reasons and Gods: Essays in Cross-Cultural Philosophy of Religion.

New York: Cambridge University Press 2006.

Pp. 291.

CDN$115.95/US$100.00

(cloth ISBN-13: 978-0-521-42104-1).

Theistic arguments not only have many uses specific to religions, traditions, and intellectuals, but also seem to have no success in their pre-modern use in providing unimpeachable and universal reasons for the existence of divinity. This observation drove much of Clayton's contributions to the philosophy of religion, here collected in his final work before his death in 2003. He argued that failure to attend to the purposes and contexts in which religious intellectuals use theistic arguments prevents a fulsome appreciation of their significance and possible truth. When one vaults prematurely over these purposes or situations in order to evaluate the truth of such arguments, one has neglected important matters. This volume collects many of his essays on this subject, together with adaptations of his Stanton Lectures. Philosophers of religion, comparative religion, and other interested readers should consider this book.

Analysis of religious arguments and their uses appropriately begins the book. Clayton's purpose emerges from his consideration of the uses to which thinkers put theistic arguments. His many analyses, ranging from Sankara to Thomas Jefferson, from Anselm of Canterbury to Immanuel Kant, all support the idea that theistic arguments have wide-ranging uses. Almost none of them, in Clayton's view, offer universal reasons that would convince any rational person. Even the Enlightenment thinkers whom Clayton engages--and this includes Kant--demonstrate sensitivity for uses of these arguments that serve to do more than convince. In short, Clayton thinks that theistic arguments have and still serve many purposes beyond offering unimpeachable proof of God's existence.

Even though it seems that Kant closed the door to any use of theistic proof to create conviction, Clayton notes that many of the pre-modern uses of the proofs survive his critical turn. Though stripped of its power to command conviction, the ontological proof still offers a purified form of the concept of God. It shows what is at stake. Many religious intellectuals scorn Kant's evaluation of God's existence as a postulate of practical reason, but according to Clayton in doing so Kant merely used theistic proof as many pre-modern thinkers did. Al-Ghazali presented proofs in order to educate faithful Muslims. On Clayton's reading, no pre-modern, not even Anselm it seems, ever sought to fashion reasons that would survive the immediate use to which it was put. These writers perhaps thought that the context in which they fashioned their argument would extend beyond their own day, but never to all times and places. Clayton identifies several uses for theistic arguments: hermeneutical, edificatory, apologetic, and polemical. These all are directed to specific situations where a range of reasons justify their use that could not apply in other situations. Thus, for instance, Anselm's famous argument does not do what Kant thought it does but, in fact, is an attempt to interpret the Bible and make sense of why the fool can deny God's existence (as is frequently stated in the Book of Psalms). Only subsequent thinkers in modernity excavated the argument to do different work.

These observations require Clayton to step back and develop his method and approach to reasons in religious traditions. He first distinguishes between giving reasons in three situations: within traditions, between religious traditions, and extra religiously. In each of these situations, Clayton urges philosophers of religion sensitively to distinguish further between these several situations. Some arguments for God's existence operate within a space shared between two traditions; others can fit only within the bounds of the religious tradition in which they are offered.

Clayton justifies these distinctions by appealing to what he called a 'maxim of reticence', that is, a sort of pragmatic version of Edmund Husserl's epoche or bracketing. However, he does not advocate these three distinctions as permanent boundaries, as some followers of Wittgenstein have done. If that sort of incommensurability between communities held, the question of the truth of any religious claim would be forever deferred, or would be significant only within each tradition, and would be arcane to the other situations, publics, and arenas of interrelation. All religious communities would be incommensurable to each other.

In place of the search for common ground or mutual commensurability, Clayton advocates that each community seek defensible differences. He follows the example of medieval Indo-Tibetan vada traditions, in which intellectuals of many religious schools disputed in public. Of course, participants wanted to 'win' such debates but, Clayton claims, the actual result was a further clarification of the logic and position proper to each school. Positions that survived became worthy darsannas, schools that can stand in public. Disputants tested each other's claims relative to the merits of their own or other positions. This approach differs considerably from the demand to test religious claims from the perspective of universal reason. One does not give up one's convictions unilaterally but only in the context of a back-and-forth engagement with another intellectual tradition. There is no completely neutral space; the price of entry into Clayton's view of public conversation is conviction, not neutrality, and one must bring a willingness to have one's convictions contested.

Clayton's chapter on Anselm merits close attention. Originally published separately, this article brings together Clayton's method of reasoning and his attention to the goal, use or purpose of proof. He proposes, first of all, that in shaping a judgment about a conclusion, one attend to the argument's use. In Anselm's case it turns out that the purpose of the argument is edificatory and hermeneutical. This, he tells us, circumscribes the scope of Anselm's claims and alters the grounds on which his argument is evaluated by philosophers of religion.

As indicated by the editors in a marginal note, all of this directs Clayton more towards the orbit of pragmatic views about religion than views involving the correspondence theory of truth or what some philosophers of religion call 'critical realism'. Clayton states in a shorthand note completed by the editors: 'Not committed to holding that correspondence theory of truth is adequate in rel(igious) contexts, pragmatic theory may be more appropriate. Not everyone will be happy with this. Not even all pragmatists, some of whom deny that prag(matisim) offers a "theory" of truth' (3). It lies now to others to develop his maxim of reticence and defend it in ways that follow through on this note. Clayton's approach to making sense of religious claims and inter-religious dialogue requires Clifford Geertz's 'thick descriptions' of not just culture but argumentation, and it requires a more pragmatic approach. This approach merits further investigation and attention. Clayton seems to have attempted a middle position between modern foundational reason and sectarian non-foundational reason.

Anne M. Blackburn and Thomas D. Carroll prepared this posthumous volume, some of the papers of which Clayton had already published. In all but a few sections, Clayton speaks for himself. Blackburn and Carroll in many cases completed the scholarly documentation of the text. They describe the history of the texts and introduce each section of essays. The resulting volume is widely accessible for undergraduates and interested general readers, and is highly recommended for all scholars.

Gregory A. Walter

St. Olaf College
联系我们|关于我们|网站声明
国家哲学社会科学文献中心版权所有