Paul J. Zak, ed.: Moral Markets: The Critical Role of Values in the Economy.
Bishop, John Douglas
Paul J. Zak, ed.
Moral Markets: The Critical Role of Values in the Economy.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press 2008.
Pp. 386.
US$65.00 (cloth ISBN-13: 978-0-691-13522-9); US$26.95 (paper
ISBN-13: 978-0-691-13523-6).
The point of this book is to replace the common view that free
markets are a non-moral realm in which all participants pursue their
self-interest without regard to their moral obligations to others or to
the common good. The volume's contributors argue that moral rules
and an instinctive regard for the interests of other people are
fundamental to free markets and that markets cannot function without
morals.
The common view of the free market is that it is a self-regulating
mechanism in which every individual pursues only her own self-interest,
and from which, as though by an invisible hand, emerge enhancements to
the common good. The central assumption is that people act within
markets like homo economicus, a being who rationally pursues the
maximization of his own utility, has a well formed consistent utility
curve not influenced by other people, and is never altruistic except
when altruism pays dividends. Since free markets promote the common
good, homo economicus need never sacrifice his interests from moral
motives. Sometimes part of the common view is the idea that homo
economicus is the natural result of evolution, since self-interestedness
is the result of the evolutionary survival of the fittest.
The contributors to this book reject the common view from many
perspectives, both theoretical and empirical. The attack comes from many
disciplines, including economics, where institutional theory, behavioral
economics, game theory, and macro-economics have shown that (a) people
do not behave like homo economicus, (b) altruism and costly rule
following is common, (c) the invisible hand does not work well in real
markets, (d) free markets (even if self-regulating in some sense) are
not self-generating or self-restraining, and (e) the best outcome is
often the result of co-operation and co-ordination, not free market
competition. Our economy is full of prisoners' dilemmas.
Psychologists have contributed empirical data that make nonsense of homo
economicus's obsession with self-interest; people, they have shown,
are mostly trusting and trustworthy, honest, and deeply concerned about
others, plus we have an instinctive sense of fairness. Biologists have
pointed out that our closest evolutionary relatives (other primates)
share some of our altruism and sense of fairness, and that such
attributes are not only a possible outcome of evolution, but are a
probable outcome in many social species. Anthropologists have tried to
trace the cultural evolution of free markets, and have shown that trust
and trustworthiness necessarily accompanies such evolution. Sociologists
have collected further evidence on the role of trust in economic
exchanges. Philosophers have pitched in with theoretical constructions
and arguments, and they have claimed that philosophy has known all this
for centuries.
This book is a snapshot of current developments in all these
fields, and most of the contributors are leading scholars well able to
give an overview of what their discipline has to say relevant to
markets. The result of bringing these views into one book is a new
paradigm of morals and free markets. Key elements of this new view are
that markets require morality to function; that most human beings are
naturally moral even at the expense of their self-interest; that moral
instincts are buried deep in human emotions and that morality derives
from 'sensations' not 'reason'; that this natural
morality of fairness and co-operation is the result of evolutionary
forces; that there are many common moral instincts that exist across
most human cultures; and that free markets have culturally evolved in
ways consistent with natural human morality. None of these views are
original to this book, but it is nice to have such excellent accounts of
them brought together: the result is like a picture emerging as a jigsaw
puzzle is completed.
For philosophers, the picture painted in this book is of great
interest, but the book raises several more specific issues of
philosophical purport. First, bringing these contributors together made
them realize that key words had radically different meanings in
different disciplines. De Waal comments on this directly with respect to
'altruism' and 'selfishness'. For a primatologist,
'altruism' refers to any behavior with results that benefit
others, and 'selfishness' refers to behavior with results that
benefit the actor; intentions, motives, reasons, and feelings are not
considered. But, of course, most of the other disciplines deal with what
the primatologist exquisitely ignores. This is not just scientists
leaving love to the poets. At stake is the nature and structure of
acceptable explanations. An evolutionary explanation of altruism has to
explain altruism in terms of survival benefits, which by definition
makes altruism selfish. The sensations and feelings that Solomon claims
underlie morality do not enter the biologist's picture--or rather,
the philosopher is left wondering how they enter it. The methodological
questions of explaining and doing ethics are intriguing.
If levels of explanation are to be kept clear, it is helpful to be
clear on whether the morality being studied concerns altruism,
co-operation, rule following, or mechanism design. Oliver Goodenough has
contributed an excellent article specifically on this issue. I wish the
other contributors had positioned their ideas more clearly with respect
to his conceptual structure. I recommend that Goodenough's
contribution be read first; and I recommend his discussion be required
reading for anyone who thinks game theory has implications for ethics.
The main contribution of a philosopher to the volume comes from
Robert Solomon, who examines how the Scottish moral sense school
anticipated much of what is now being said by other disciplines. The key
point is that most of the contributors believe that morality is the
result of feelings or sensations, not rational principle. They seem to
think that this view is entailed by their claim that morality is the
result of human evolution; rational principles are the result of
cultural evolution. The empirical evidence is thus deciding the
eighteenth century debate between moral reason and moral sense in favor
of the latter. I am not convinced. Unfortunately, this issue runs as a
theme through many contributions; no single author tackles it directly.
Reading this book is like looking at a still from a film; all the
contributors' disciplines are expanding explosively and several of
these disciplines are very young. This book should be read by everyone
interested in current views on morality and its role in how free markets
function. This includes anyone interested in moral failure within our
economy, a most important topic at the moment. However, I am afraid that
this book will date very quickly. A revised edition in 10 years, even in
5 years, will show a vastly different picture.
John Douglas Bishop
Trent University