Platon: Sophistes.
Miller, J. Philip
This volume contains the text of a lecture course Heidegger
presented in Marburg in the winter semester of 1924/25, just a year
before completing his work on the manuscript for Being and Time. A
lengthy introductory section examines the concept of truth in
Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics and Metaphysics. The "Main
Section" presents a detailed commentary on the Greek text of
Plato's Sophist. Part I deals with the various attempts made at the
beginning of the dialogue (219a-236c) to define "the factical
existence of the sophist." Part 2 is devoted to the ontological
discussion which arises out of these attempts (236e-264b).
Heidegger refers frequently to the Aristotelian definition of the
human being as zoon logon echon. The term logos he takes to mean
"discourse," course," especially discourse that is made
public and shared with others; thus Aristotle's definition is
understood to identify speech as a central human phenomenon. According
to Heidegger, however, Aristotle also recognizes another human
possibility, closely related to discourse yet distinct. More basic than
speech is the human capacity for "seeing" the things
themselves, for making present what our speech is about. Everyday human
existence is dominated by obscurity and by "empty talk"
(Gerede), in which the capacity for seeing is not fully activated. There
is always a possibility, however, of moving from obscurity and emptiness
to authentic presence. As the lecture makes clear, it is this basic
phenomenological contrast that underlies Heidegger's interpretation
of the Greek concept of truth as a-letheia, as an
"un-coveredness" of the things themselves (p. 16).
Heidegger calls attention to Aristotle's use of the verb
aletheuein. He takes Aristotle to be saying that human beings are
essentially "in the truth," that truth is "an essential
characteristic of human existence itself (p. 23). One manifestation of
the tendency toward truth is phronesis, a capacity for disclosing the
human situations in which action takes place and one's own being is
at issue. Although he does not fully develop the idea, Heidegger does
identify some ways in which the truth of phronesis is contrasted with
corresponding forms of concealment. The allegedly higher truth of
sophia, "authentic understanding," also represents a contrast
with concealment. As Heidegger points out, Aristotle clarifies sophia by
showing how ft emerges from the relative obscurity of experience, art,
and science. Each of these reflects a kind of partial exercise of the
capacity for truth: something is "seen" in each, even though
the archai or "starting points" remain obscure.
This introductory discussion of Aristotle is relevant because the
Sophist turns out, on Heidegger's reading, to revolve around an
understanding of discourse and truth. The dialogue's various
attempts to characterize the sophist have a common thread: all imply
that logos is what somehow defines the sophist's mode of existence.
This is most obviously true of the last two definitions, in which the
sophist appears as a disputer who repeatedly opposes one opinion to
another and as an imitator who uses words to paint false and misleading
pictures of things. But it also applies to the earlier attempts. In
each, "the basic phenomenon of legein becomes decisive" (p.
303).
To shed light on Plato's concept of discourse, Heidegger
examines the Phaedrus, the dialogue which in his view "forms the
center, so to speak, for all questions of Platonic philosophy" (p.
321). Here he shows that Plato also works with a distinction between a
speaker who has only hearsay acquaintance with the subject of his
discourse and a speaker who has actually "seen" what he speaks
about "in its unconcealment" (p. 323). Plato's skepticism
about the written word is to be understood in this context: far from
making people wiser, trust in written discourse (or in any discourse
that has been taken over from another) actually fosters lethe,
"forgetting" or "covering up," in that it leaves the
reader or hearer unconcerned about the presence of the things
themselves. The philosopher's dialectical art, on the other hand,
is meant to lead to a genuine seeing; it is not a matter of making
sterile divisions, but rather the Me" by Which speakers can go back
"through" (dia) what is ordinarily said to an authentic
uncovering, an original appropriation, of that which is spoken about.
Heidegger believes that this phenomenological understanding of
discourse and truth plays an important role in the Sophist. Implicit in the is the thesis that the sophist's medium is
"uprooted," "free-floating" floating" speech,
empty discourse not anchored in genuine disclosure. The sophist creates
an image or appearance instead of allowing the thing itself to be seen
and appropriated. Where the philosopher's dialectical art seeks to
uncover the things themselves, the sophist aims only at speaking well.
On Heidegger's interpretation, even the ontological section of
the dialogue makes use of this phenomonological understanding of
discourse and truth. Here Plato's Eleatic stranger proposes to
modify the received Parmedenidian ontology, since its absolute
repudiation of non-being makes impossible any understanding of false
discourse, and hence of sophist's mode of existence. Heidegger
finds the root of the problem in Parmenides' interpretation of
being as sheer, undifferentiated "presence." Since this
ontological Position leads inevitably to a denial of non-being,
Plato's stranger must somehow move beyond Parmenides. No Greek was
able to transcend the ontology of presences, which arises naturally from
ordinary ways of thinking about the world. But the stranger does
introduce an important modification.
Heidegger suggests that Plato's ontology differs from that
Parmenides ides in that it is based on a careful study of the structure
of discourse. Plato saw that logos is more than mere naming, that is
always involves saying something "of" something else. By the
same token, what the authentic speaker apprehends is not just the thing
spoken about, but something that is present "as" something
else. The presence that underlies authentic discourse is always the
articulated presence of something-as-something, not the sheer,
undifferentiated presence envisioned by Parmenides. It always involves a
certain koinonia or "togetherness." What is decisive for
Platonic ontology is thus an understanding of being as the
"possibility of togetherness," dunamis koinonias (p. 479), the
potential for being present together with something else for an
authentic speaker.
This ontological advance underlies the stranger's solution to
the problem of the being of non-being. Once he has defined being in
terms of koinonia, the stranger goes on to show that
"otherness" comes together with everything that is. And since
otherness is a kind of non-being, the being of non-being is established,
and the definition of the sophist in terms of false discourse is
secured.
The lecture provides striking evidence of the degree to which
Heidegger was absorbed in both phenomenology and Greek philosophy at the
time he composed Being and Time. Phenomenological distinctions like that
between authentic and inauthentic discourse pointed him toward a
dramatically new way of understanding the Greek philosophers; understood
in this way, the Greeks in turn suggested new approaches to a wide range
of philosophical issues. The two perspectives are so fused in
Heidegger's lecture that it is often difficult to distinguish his
own voice from the voices of those whose works he comments on. Some will
find this fusion of perspectives unsettling and disturbing, but
phenomenologically oriented philosophers can look to the work for a
wealth of provocative insights and suggestive interpretations.