首页    期刊浏览 2024年12月05日 星期四
登录注册

文章基本信息

  • 标题:Three Discourses.
  • 作者:Clark, Paul
  • 期刊名称:The Review of Metaphysics
  • 印刷版ISSN:0034-6632
  • 出版年度:1999
  • 期号:March
  • 语种:English
  • 出版社:Philosophy Education Society, Inc.
  • 摘要:HOBBES, Thomas. Three Discourses. Edited by Noel Reynolds and Arlene Saxonhouse. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997. ix + 181 pp. Paper, $12.95--The three discourses collected in this volume are from a collection of twelve essays published anonymously in 1620, which were associated with the Cavendish family--the family that served as patron and employer of Hobbes for many years. It was not until Leo Strauss discovered a manuscript version of these essays in Hobbes's own hand that it began to be suspected that the essays might have been the work of a young Hobbes. Computer analysis of the text, comparing the various word patterns of a work of questionable authorship with that of known authors, has established that three of the twelve essays match the later work of Hobbes and hence can be attributed to him.
  • 关键词:Book reviews;Books

Three Discourses.


Clark, Paul


HOBBES, Thomas. Three Discourses. Edited by Noel Reynolds and Arlene Saxonhouse. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997. ix + 181 pp. Paper, $12.95--The three discourses collected in this volume are from a collection of twelve essays published anonymously in 1620, which were associated with the Cavendish family--the family that served as patron and employer of Hobbes for many years. It was not until Leo Strauss discovered a manuscript version of these essays in Hobbes's own hand that it began to be suspected that the essays might have been the work of a young Hobbes. Computer analysis of the text, comparing the various word patterns of a work of questionable authorship with that of known authors, has established that three of the twelve essays match the later work of Hobbes and hence can be attributed to him.

As Hobbes is famous for having taken up writing late in life, it is hoped that the discovery of these texts will shed some light on the intellectual development of Hobbes. Unfortunately, given that we know almost nothing about how these essays came to be written, it is impossible to conclude anything with certainty. Was Hobbes "ghostwriting" or writing these essays under the direction of his patron? Are the ideas in these three essays Hobbes's own thought, or do some of them belong to his coauthor? While these early discourses show little of the originality of thought found in Hobbes's mature writings, it is certainly a fascinating exercise for Hobbes scholars to look back on these early treatises and attempt to pick out the seeds of his later thought.

The longest of the three discourses is "A Discourse Upon the Beginning of Tacitus." It is an obvious attempt to emulate Machiavelli, and of the three discourses it is the most "Hobbesian" both in style and content. The Discourse on Tacitus is largely concerned with the subject of civil war--what causes it and how to prevent it. Hobbes says that "civil war is the worst thing that can happen to a state" (p. 37) and the thing which brought an end to civil war in Rome was the rise of a powerful emperor. Augustus tamed the warring multitudes according to Hobbes's analysis in that "first, he did beat and weary them; next . showed them hope of ease" (p. 45). Already we see the basic passions of hope and fear as that which is used to control the multitude. This discussion clearly shows that Hobbes's concern with civil war, which is so central to all of his writings, predated the English Civil War itself.

Other parts of the Discourse on Tacitus are very un-Hobbesian. For example, in discussing when wars should be fought he writes: "Wars are necessary only where they are just, and just only in the case of defense. First, of our lives, secondly of our right, and lastly of our honor." In his later works it is clear Hobbes has no "just war" theory, and fighting over honor he condemns as a cause of unnecessary conflict.

The second discourse is "On Rome" and while it bears marks of Hobbes's style, in content it is thoroughly traditional and it is almost totally contrary to his later writings. While mostly a description of the city of Rome, it does contain discussions of a number of philosophical issues. Hobbes in this discourse praises all of the traditional virtues which the Romans possessed--courage, discipline, and honor--which he would later call into question as causes of conflict. He even praises "Cicero, Seneca, ... Cato, and many more, whose virtue, more than their greatness made them famous" (p. 81). Yet when we turn to the opening of Hobbes's De Cive, we find he shows only contempt for these men and their seditious opinions.

Other statements at odds with Hobbes's later writings include his criticism of pagan philosophers for not having a proper understanding of the immortality of the soul (p. 83), and his criticism of those who would pretend to hold views contrary to their religion in order to avoid punishment (p. 101).

The third discourse is a short one entitled "Of Laws." Again this discourse is for the most part extremely traditional and seems to borrow significantly from Fortesque's "In Praise of the Laws of England." In contrast to Fortesque, however, the overall tone is very pessimistic. While Fortesque believed that society is a harmonious association which does not need a powerful government, Hobbes says that "Laws be the only sinews of contracting people together" (p. 107). While Fortesque thought there were tyrannies worse than any lack of government, Hobbes, as in his later works, considers that anarchy is the greatest evil and that the worst tyranny is still better than anarchy.

Most of the things that might be considered untraditional in this treatise are more a matter of tone than of outright contradiction. For example, Hobbes acknowledges the existence of Natural Law, in the traditional sense, and says that human law is derived from it, but then he says that "we derive more benefit from [human] Laws, in this kind, than from Nature" because Natural Law lacks an enforcement mechanism (p. 110). Also, while he acknowledges the teaching of Fortesque and other medieval philosophers that customs of the people have the force of law, he says that "the force and power of [the sovereign's] Law does easily dissolve an ill custom, though it have been of long continuance" (p. 111). Even these positions could be defended from a medieval viewpoint, however.

While the uncertainties around the composition of the three Discourses make them unlikely to settle any of the many serious disputes in the interpretation of Hobbes's overall work, this volume has certainly added grist to the mill of Hobbes scholarship, and in that sense it is a welcome addition.

--Paul Clark, Washington, D.C.

联系我们|关于我们|网站声明
国家哲学社会科学文献中心版权所有