Hutton, Sarah. Anne Conway: A Woman Philosopher.
Tkacz, Catherine Brown
HUTTON, Sarah. Anne Conway: A Woman Philosopher. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2004. viii + 271 pp. Cloth, $75.00--In the
last twenty years Lady Anne Conway, nee Finch (1631-79), has gained
scholarly attention, as shown by recent encyclopedia entries on her. A
Cambridge Platonist, Lady Conway critiqued Descartes, Hobbes, and
Spinoza, as well as her former tutor and lifelong correspondent, Henry
More. Leibniz mentions her posthumous work positively, albeit briefly.
With an impressive command of documentary and philosophical sources,
Sarah Hutton contextualizes the Viscountess's thought and meets the
stated goal of showing that Conway's Principia philosophiae
antiquissimae and recentissimae expresses "the philosophical
concerns of a lifetime" (p. 12).
In an age when women were not formally admitted to Cambridge,
Conway was tutored by mail by Henry More, who had also taught her
half-brother John Finch. Her notebooks, now lost, were published
posthumously in 1690 in Latin translation by men who respected her and
who with self-effacement introduced her work without mentioning their
own names. Conway proposed replacing the doctrine of the Trinity with a
metaphysical metaphor in which God is the Creator, Christ is mediating
"Middle Nature," and the third element is Creation. Hobbes and
Spinoza she critiques for failing to distinguish between Creator and
creation. She also criticized the dualism of Descartes and of More,
developing instead a "vitalistic monism" (p. 87). More himself
had written of "Monad or Unite" in 1653 (p. 159).
Professor Hutton does an exemplary job of documenting the
influences upon Conway. One was pain. From the age of twelve, Conway
suffered, often enduring violent headaches lasting for days, even
months. This brought her into contact with numerous physicians and gave
her an interest in science, which in turn influenced her thought. For
instance, she derived her theory of change from Francis Mercury van
Helmont and studied the works of Robert Boyle. Her "ecumenical
Deism" led at last to her becoming a Quaker.
The volume lacks a chronological table of Conway's
philosophical letters, both the extant ones and those reliably attested,
with identification of the correspondents, including More, Finch, Knorr,
possibly Elizabeth of Bohemia, but not Leibniz or Margaret Cavendish.
Such a table would also have clarified just how many letters there are.
Similarly, although perceptive comments about Conway's Principia
are offered passim throughout the monograph, nowhere are the work's
full contents, structure, or length recounted. (In the 1690 duodecimo publication, Van Helmont's anonymous introduction was six pages and
the Latin text 144).
In her "reconstructive archaeology" of Conway's
thought (p. 10), Hutton gives a generally judicious presentation of what
may be reliably inferred from the evidence (for example, pp. 18, 93 n.
58, 138-9, 199). An admirable index gives access to the thematically
arranged contents. The final chapter discreetly corrects erroneous
assessments of Conway. It is disconcerting, however, that More's
dedicatory letter for Antidote against Atheism is cited both to show
that More presents Conway as an acceptably stereotypical woman (p. 29)
but also as evidence that he admired her particular intellectual gifts
(p. 39).
Unfortunately, Hutton's assessment of Conway's influence
is exaggerated. For instance, her influence upon More's philosophy
is said to be "significant, possibly formative" (p. 78), and
she is credited with "a far-reaching impact" on the thought of
Van Helmont (pp. 140, 152). The evidence offered, however, shows only
moderate influence. Conway is also credited with taking the lead,
"setting the agenda" of philosophical subjects in epistolary
exchanges with More and Finch (p. 9). Yet More, as Conway's tutor
(and social inferior?) asked Conway to propose questions and subjects
(pp. 73-4). Finch made the same request (pp. 99-100). That is, it has
not been shown that on her own initiative she "set the
agenda."
More seriously, Conway is repeatedly treated as collaborator or
author of works published by men (for example, p. 9). George Keith,
More, and Van Helmont were gathered with her at Ragley for philosophical
discussion, but this does not justify deeming her "the
director" of the debates or "co-author" of their works.
The fact that these men wrote dialogues does not certify that they
record her thought (pp. 203-6). A very few parallels in wording between
Conway and Van Helmont's Two Hundred Queries do not make her his
collaborator (p. 210).
It is instructive to reverse the sexes of the persons involved: Had
a man hosted philosophical dialogues involving three women and then each
woman had published treatises, the scholarly world would cry
"Foul!" if a modern critic were to assert that probably the
man was the author of these texts. Moreover, as Hutton makes clear, More
and Van Helmont edited Conway's Principia, annotated it, translated
it into Latin, wrote an introduction to it, and had it published.
Appropriately, she does not from these facts conclude that the men were
coauthors of Conway's Principia. Likewise it is inappropriate to
aggrandize Conway's work by deeming her the author of their
publications.--Catherine Brown Tkacz, Gonzaga University.