THOMAS AQUINAS ON THE DEVELOPMENT OF DOCTRINE.
KACZOR, CHRISTOPHER
SELDOM IS THE NAME Thomas Aquinas associated with doctrinal
development. I would like to propose that, contrary to the views of
some, Thomistic theology is in fact compatible with development of
doctrine and further that Aquinas himself provided resources for
understanding development. Thomas's teaching on development as
logical deduction, organic assimilation, and historically situated is to
be found in no single place and must be gleaned, if it is to be known at
all, from various passages in the Thomistic corpus. This article
describes and systematizes Aquinas's obiter dicta remarks
pertaining to the development of doctrine which he always understood as
the unfolding of implicit teaching into more explicit formulation and
reflects on the importance of the Thomistic account for contemporary
thinking on development.
Of course, everyone recognizes that Aquinas developed Christian
wisdom in significant ways, and as Bernard Lonergan and Jean Pierre
Torrell pointed out,(1) Aquinas's own organization and presentation
of this wisdom changed in the course of his career. The autograph
manuscripts show that Aquinas constantly revised and edited his work.
Historical studies have indicated the development of Aquinas's
views from his early commentary on Lombard to his mature Summa
theologiae.(2)
However, doctrinal development understood as a consideration of how
Christian teaching changes and develops over time is usually thought to
have arisen in the 19th century with Johann Adam Mohler and most
especially John Henry Newman's Essay on the Development of
Christian Doctrine and to have been reconsidered in the 20th century
through the work of Karl Rahner, Edward Schillebeeckx, and Avery Dulles.
In fact, this focus on history and development in Christian teaching is
often understood in opposition to medieval approaches since this
attention seems to presuppose an historical consciousness arising in the
19th century.(3) The consensus of many distinguished scholars including
Jan Hendrik Walgrave,(4) Per Erik Persson,(5) Henri de Lubac,(6) and
Avery Dulles(7) is that Aquinas had no account of development.
Though I do not share their view, their position is a reasonable
one. Clearly, Thomas did not consider development of doctrine as an
explicit theme of theological reflection as do contemporary theologians.
There are no questions expressly devoted to the subject found in the
Summa theologiae or elsewhere in the corpus thomisticum. Development
simply was not a locus of medieval discourse. Moreover, a fundamental
aspect of Thomistic theology has led some scholars to conclude that
indeed Aquinas could not have had resources for a theory of development,
namely Aquinas's understanding of theology as rooted in the literal
sense of Scripture. How would this exclude development of doctrine?
As Avery Dulles has pointed out,(8) Aquinas's view of theology
as based in the literal sense of Scripture and of revelation as
propositional limits the developments that can take place within
Thomistic theology. Aquinas believed that public revelation ended after
the death of the last apostle and that nothing may be added or taken
away from this definitive revelation to them.(9) Aquinas held that
knowledge of the holy mysteries of God increased throughout time in
preparation for Christ but "at last, at the consummate time, the
perfect teaching of Christ [was] set forth on earth.(10) With Christ
comes the fullness of revelation and not even the apostles themselves
may deliver another faith than that given by Christ.(11) The apostles
had the fullness of truth as those who were closest to Christ:
"those who first handed on the faith most perfectly understood it
since the Apostles were most fully instructed concerning the mysteries
of faith."(12) This revelation is transmitted to us in a definitive
way through Holy Scripture the essential points of which are summarized
in the Apostle's Creed.(13) The teaching of Christ and the Apostles
is sufficiently explicated and transmitted in the creed of Nicea.(14)
For Dulles, Aquinas's account of a definitive revelation written
down in a definitive form does not leave room for development of
doctrine.
On the other hand, these considerations must also be tempered with
what Aquinas said elsewhere. Aquinas clearly asserted that the
Church's understanding of the truths of faith grows deeper over
time. Later Fathers of the Church had a more explicit knowledge of the
articles of the faith than earlier Fathers and the creeds of the Church
grew longer and more detailed. This development of faith the Angelic
Doctor viewed as essential: "it was necessary to promulgate confessions of faith which in no way differ, save that in one it is more
fully explicated which in another is contained implicitly."(15) The
accent for Aquinas is characteristically on continuity, but the
recognition of development is clear. The problem of development arises
in reconciling this assertion with his account of the special
understanding of the apostles. How can more explicit, later expositions
of the creed be reconciled with the apostles having the fullness of
knowledge? Can a more implicit knowledge be a more full knowledge? If
the later Fathers of the Church teach more explicitly what the earlier
Fathers taught implicitly, why should the Sacred Page be of greater
importance than the writings of the Church Fathers, which have only
probable authority according to Aquinas? There are a number of possible
ways to answer these questions along with corresponding difficulties for
each. These questions and others have led to various models of how
doctrine develops.
Avery Dulles in his book The Resilient Church describes three
prominent models of development. In the logical model, revelation is
understood propositionally and further developments must arise through
logical deductions from previous teaching. This version of doctrinal
development Dulles attributes to Marin-Sola as well as earlier thinkers
such as Bishop Bossuet, Luis de Molina and Gabriel Vasquez.(16) In the
early 20th century, M. M. Tuyaerts, O.P., and Charles Boyer, S.J.,
exemplified the logical approach.(17) Although the logical approach
enabled theologians to illustrate a tight connection between apostolic
teaching and the contemporary doctrine of the Church in the development
of some dogmas (i.e. that Mary is the Mother of God), it had
difficulties showing that the Immaculate Conception and Assumption were
logically entailed from anything in the ancient apostolic tradition. An
organic approach to development exemplified by John Henry Newman and
Johann Adam Mohler of Tubingen argued that more than mere logical
analysis leads to the development of the Church's understanding of
revelation. Various theories are given as to what constitutes this
"more." Karl Rahner, for example, suggested that we abandon
the propositional account of revelation and consider revelation a
self-communication of the divine that the faithful understand through a
kind of global intuition. Finally, there is the historically situated
approach to development advocated by Dulles and Lindbeck which views
development of doctrine as reformulations of church teaching in each age
to reflect the needs, concerns, and outlooks of each age. Lindbeck
writes: "The Church's doctrines are thought of as the products
of a dialogue in history between God and his people and as the
historically conditioned and relative responses, interpretations and
testimonies to the Word addressing man through the scriptural
witnesses."(18) The needs of the Church in the moment and the
concrete situation dictate the course of the unfolding doctrinal change.
Unlike the previous two accounts, this model of development, in some
versions at least, explicitly allows for "reversals" or
"contradictions" of earlier teaching in later periods when the
prior formulations no longer adequately respond to current needs. This
model also characteristically rejects the propositional account of
revelation.
Aquinas's treatment of development, when recognized at all, is
usually characterized by admirers and detractors alike as merely
deductive. Though Aquinas did not portend the three models in every
particular, careful reading of Thomas may discern elements of all three
non-mutually exclusive approaches to development, which Thomas
understood as an unfolding from implicit teaching to explicit teaching.
DEVELOPMENT OF DOCTRINE AS LOGICAL DEDUCTION
Interestingly, although Aquinas did recognize that development of
doctrine could come about through logical deduction, sometimes it is
thought that he recognized no other way in which our understanding of
revelation could advance.(19) Indeed, though a few neo-Scholastics
argued that logical deduction was the only way to preserve continuity
with apostolic teaching, even most neo-Scholastic writers had a richer
notion of development.(20) Nevertheless, logical deduction is one aspect
of the unfolding from implicit to explicit teaching, an aspect Aquinas
did not overlook. Aquinas gave a prime example of this use in the Prima
pars:
For regularly in sacred Scripture it should be held that what is
said concerning the Father, should be understood concerning the Son,
even if the exclusive speech is added, save only in those things in
which the Father and the Son in opposite relations are distinguished.
For since the Lord, in Matt. 11, says: No one knows the Son save the
Father, it is not excluded that the Son knows himself. Therefore, when
it is said that the Holy Spirit proceeds from the Father, even if it
were to be added that he proceeds only from the Father, the Son in this
way is not excluded because in this respect, that which is the principle
of the Holy Spirit, Father and Son are not opposed, but only concerning
this, that the former is the Father and the latter is the Son.(21)
Here we have a teaching that follows logically from what has been
previously accepted. As Aquinas noted earlier in the passage, the
logically posterior teaching is implicit in the prior, explicit
teaching: "We ought not to say about God anything which is not
found in Holy Scripture either explicitly or implicitly. But although we
do not find it verbally expressed in Holy Scripture that the Holy Ghost proceeds from the Son, still we do find it in the sense of
Scripture.(22) As Aquinas commented next, whatever predication applies
to the Father, applies to the Son, except those predications that
distinguish Father from Son. The procession of the Holy Spirit applies
to the Father and is not a predication that distinguishes Father from
Son. Thus the procession of the Spirit can be predicated of Father and
Son. Another example of this type of inference may be seen in the
declaration of Mary as Mother of God. From the prior teachings,
"Mary is the mother of Jesus" and "Jesus is God,"
comes the now explicit teaching "Mary is the Mother of God."
Aquinas uses a deductive method in his treatment of Christ's will.
As Stephen Brown notes: "From the premises that Christ is God and
man, for example, he deduced the truth that Christ has two wills, by
adding the premise that every intellectual nature has its proper
will.(23) Clearly, in Aquinas's writing, the move from implicit to
explicit teaching sometimes has this clear, deductive, logical meaning.
However unlike some advocates of the logical model of development,
for Aquinas the notion of the "implicit" is much more rich
than the notion one finds in certain neo-Scholastic authors who demand
that doctrinal developments be logically implicit in prior statements,
much in the way that "unmarried" is logically implicit or
analytically contained in "bachelor." For Aquinas, the death
and Resurrection of Christ is contained implicitly in the existence and
especially the providence of God.(24) Indeed, all the articles of faith
are implicit in the belief in God and God's providence.(25)
Clearly, his notion of implicit must involve more than mere logical
derivation. Aquinas would retain the idea that doctrine can be developed
by logical analysis, but would want to enrich the movement from
"implicit" teaching to "explicit" teaching to
include much more than mere logical analyticity.
THE ORGANIC APPROACH TO DEVELOPMENT
In the organic approach, doctrine develops through the assimilation
and incorporation of "foreign" elements as well as what Newman
called "the growth of ideas" which lead to a deeper
understanding and explanation of the Gospel message. Although the
apostles had greater understanding of faith because of special graces
received, in particular that of proximity to Christ, later Church
Fathers developed what was implicit in apostolic teaching in a more
differentiated theology because of (1) the growth of philosophy, (2) the
emendation of the liturgy, and (3) the evolution of language. The Church
incorporates these elements over time leading to deeper understandings
and fuller expressions of sacra doctrina.
In Aquinas's account of theology, philosophical reason enters
into this science by demonstrating the truth of the preambles of faith,
by removing objections to the faith by showing them to be erroneous or
at least unnecessary, by providing useful analogies to clarify what is
difficult to understand, and by proving the truth of doubted articles of
faith from undoubted ones.(26) The science of theology does not depend
on other sciences for its first principles but uses other sciences as
aids.(27) In this, theology imitates Scripture itself that employs
secular traditions of wisdom. Aquinas remarks on passages in Paul's
letter to Titus, in First Corinthians, and in Acts which quote the words
of pagans Epimenides, Menander, and Aratus.(28) Clearly, philosophy aids
theology, which in turn aids in the formulation of doctrine. The truths
of the faith cannot be understood completely without the work of reason.
"Reason sees immediately certain things, which are per se nota, in
which are contained implicitly certain other things which it is not
possible to understand save through the work of reason, by explaining
those things which are contained implicitly in the principles."(29)
As Aquinas noted the deficiency of the human mind, and not of the
divinely revealed truth, leads theology to draw on other sciences to
clarify its teaching and aid in human assent to this truth.(30)
Aquinas clearly recognized that philosophic knowledge might grow
over time. There is progress in understanding from the presocratics, to
Socrates and Aristotle, and from them to Avicenna and Averroes.(31) As
Aquinas wrote in his Commentary on the Ethics:
If someone should busy himself investigating the truth for a
period, he will be aided in the discovery of truth by the passage of
time. This is true in the case of the same person who will understand
subsequently what he had not understood before, and also for different
persons, as in the case of a man who learns the things discovered by his
predecessors and adds something himself. In this way improvements have
been made in the arts, in which a small discovery was made first and
afterwards notable advances were made by the efforts of various men,
each looking upon it as a duty to supply what is lacking in the
knowledge of his predecessors.(32)
There is no reason to think that this process of growth cannot
continue indefinitely. Thus we can say safely that theology, in so far
as it uses philosophy or any other science in the ways mentioned
earlier, may also increase in precision and clarity over time. And in so
far as theology develops, our understanding of doctrine itself may
become more complete. Progress in philosophy may continually open new
horizons; so the process of development cannot, in this life, ever be
said to be closed or complete.
Secondly, doctrine may also develop for Aquinas through the
liturgy. Although sometimes theology informs liturgical practice,(33)
other times liturgical practice informs theology. Aquinas frequently
uses the practice of the Church in worship as a sed contra
authority.(34) For example, in considering the question of whether the
Mother of Jesus was sanctified before birth, Aquinas wrote: "The
Church celebrates the feast of our Lady's Nativity. Now the Church
does not celebrate feasts except of those who are holy. Therefore even
in her birth the Blessed Virgin was holy. Therefore she was sanctified
in the womb."(35) The liturgy guided Aquinas's theological
reflection, especially on the sacraments.
Aquinas was historically aware enough to realize that the liturgy
develops over time.(36) Walter H. Principe in "Tradition in Thomas
Aquinas's Scripture Commentaries," noted that ecclesiastical
traditions are authoritative but not so authoritative as the Gospel
itself by which these traditions are to be judged.(37) And yet as
Principe pointed out, the early tradition of the Church establishes the
form of the sacrament of the Eucharist, though this form is variously
expressed in Paul, Matthew, and Luke. As Aquinas remarked: "For the
Evangelists intended to recite the words of the Lord in so far as they
pertain to history, not in so far as they are ordained to the
consecration of the sacraments, which took place in secret in the early
Church on account of the infidels."(38) For Aquinas, the liturgy of
the Church understood here as an aspect of the tradition coming from the
Apostles and developed in the living ecclesial practice informs the
reading of Scripture and establishes liturgical practices that are
aspects of reflection and indeed loci of authority for theology.
Thirdly, Aquinas was cognizant of the way in which language shapes
the formulations of the articles of faith. In various passages, Aquinas
understood "implicite" in terms of figures of speech and
signs. The move from implicit to explicit is, in this instance, a move
from figurative speech to literal speech. He wrote:
Divine things ought not be revealed to man save according to their
capacity: otherwise an occasion of a fall is given to them, for they
condemn those things which they do not understand. And for this reason
it was useful that divine mysteries be handed on to an unsophisticated
people under a kind of veil of figures so that thus they might know
these things at least implicitly while by these figures they were
devoted to the honor of God.(39)
Aquinas understood the meaning of implicit in terms of being known
"under a veil of figures."(40) He characterized the use of
these figures, here and elsewhere, as a pedagogic tool for instructing
the unlearned.(41)
In the passages just mentioned, Aquinas referred to the development
from the understanding of God accessible to Old Testament figures to a
clearer revelation of God's triune nature in the New Testament.
Yet, the development occasioned by language occurs not merely before but
also after the apostles. Of this, Aquinas was aware, and, indeed, he was
a prime contributor to this shift. The shift is from true but
undifferentiated language about God to language that is more exact and
precise. Church Councils before him introduced non-scriptural terms such
as homoousion, Theotokos, and Trinitas in order to clarify the meaning
of Scriptural passages vis-a-vis rival interpretations. Aquinas
continued this tradition appropriating in so many places Aristotelian
terms, or terms such as transubstantiation that arise from Aristotelian
roots, to clarify and differentiate positions that truly accord with
Scripture and Church teaching from those that do not.(42) G. Geenan,
O.P., notes that Aquinas: "felt duty bound to show that, as a
matter of fact, these new words [not of Biblical origin] corresponded in
their own way to the words of Scripture."(43) Aquinas was well
aware of his extraliteral usage. Geenan continues:
"Tradition" has a real place in the theology of Aquinas,
since at times it is due to Tradition alone that we can arrive at an
understanding of the Scriptures and that we can demonstrate that, even
Scriptural texts, which at first sight and secundum litteram seem to
affirm the contrary of revealed doctrine, express in fact this revealed
doctrine such as it is taught by the Church. The "Filioque" a
formula of extra-scriptural origin, contains "expressly" and
explicitly what was not found in Scripture except "per
sensum."(44)
The shift from implicit to explicit is first the shift from
figurative Old Testament language to literal New Testament proclamation
and then the move from literal but less differentiated language to a
more precise language that works to exclude rival interpretations of
Holy Scripture. Thus, precision of language aids the development of
doctrine.
In contrast to certain organic accounts of development, for Aquinas
theology must always remain based in the literal sense of Scripture
which reveals to us certain propositional truths. Unlike the Apostles,
most of us do not have an experience of direct self-communication with
the Divine, but rather our communal cognitive understanding of what God
has said and done for us comes to us through the mediation of Scripture
and tradition. The apostles experienced first hand the risen Christ and
proclaimed, through their preaching, this experience to others. Though
Aquinas would share with the organic model the insight that the
understanding of this revelation in the Church is ongoing through the
direction of the Holy Spirit, he believed that revelation is given to
those who are not Apostles propositionally unlike some advocates of the
organic account of development.
DEVELOPMENT AS HISTORICALLY SITUATED
Sacred doctrine proceeds from a revelation from God that is for the
salvation of humanity.(45) For Aquinas, sacred doctrine is a science
that treats primarily God and creatures in so far as they are related to
God, who is their efficient and final cause.(46) The articles of faith
(articuli fidei) which are given by a higher science, the very wisdom of
God, articulate the first principles of theology.(47) These articles
(the Creed) express those things in the content of Sacred Scripture that
are necessary for our belief.(48) It is important to note that this
science, this wisdom of sacra doctrina is for a purpose: "I respond
it should be said that what was needed for human salvation is a certain
teaching concerning divine relevation beyond the natural knowledge
investigated by human reason."(49) If sacred doctrine is to save
the individual, it must be proportioned to the individual, for according
to the Thomistic axiom everything received is received in the manner of
the receiver. Revelation is intended to save singular, distinct persons
living in diverse contexts, with various intellectual presuppositions.
The expression of sacred doctrine must therefore change so that it can
save people in contexts that differ from the context of the apostles.
Theology thus becomes an act of evangelizare in the medieval sense.
Hence, what is implicit in our conception, exposition, and formulation
of sacred doctrine must develop in history and become explicit if sacred
doctrine is to achieve its purpose.
Perhaps the most powerful historical influence on the formation of
doctrine, for Aquinas are the heretici. It is often human weakness,
misunderstanding, or doubt that prompts doctrinal development.(50)
Aquinas followed Augustine in describing the way in which heretics
challenging the faith furnish an opportunity for the Church to clarify
teachings and make explicit what was previously covert.(51) Aquinas
echoed this understanding in a number of places. In the Secunda secundae
he argued: "since perverse men pervert apostolic teaching and the
Scriptures to their own damnation, as it is written in Second Peter 16;
therefore there is need with the passage of time of an explanation of
the faith against arising errors."(52) Doctrinal development is for
Aquinas, as for Augustine, an "explanatio fidei contra insurgentes
errores" which means in effect that heresy influences the
formulation of doctrine not merely as an occasion for reflection but
also by substantial contribution, albeit a dialectical one.(53) Thus,
doctrine develops in reference to highly specific and historically
emergent circumstances.
Aquinas also recognized the influence of historical context on the
shaping of doctrine.(54) Though it would be anachronistic to portray
Aquinas as having the "historical consciousness" associated
with Hegel, Darwin, or Newman, a failure to recognize elements of these
insights in the Thomistic corpus would also be mistaken.(55) Aquinas
took into account how the historical situation of the Church influenced
formulation of the Nicene and the Apostolic creeds:
The creed of the Fathers is declarative of the Apostles'
Creed, and was also fashioned when the faith was manifest and the Church
at peace, for this reason it is sung publicly at Mass. However, the
Apostles' Creed, which was drawn up at a time of persecution, when
the faith was not yet public, is said privately in Prime and Compline,
as if against the darkness of past and future errors.(56)
The Church, having peace at a later time, declares more publicly
its credo (which explains, perhaps, its greater length) which during a
time of persecution retained a greater brevity. Aquinas also suggested
that the temporal conditions of the Church influence the way in which
the liturgy is performed and therefore doctrine presented.(57)
The Prooemium of the Contra errores Graecorum exemplifies both
Aquinas's understanding of historical context and the effect heresy
has on doctrine. Having been asked by Urban IV for an expert opinion of
a Libellus de processione Spiritus Sancti et de fide trinitatis contra
errores Graecorum published by Nicholas of Durazzo the bishop of
Catrone, Aquinas replied in his own work also entitled, Contra errores
Graecorum.(58) Aquinas noted that expressions that sound orthodox in
Greek often do not sound orthodox in Latin. Though the Greeks and Latins
share the same beliefs, they do not share the same language in which
those beliefs are expressed. One must then, in translating, preserve the
meaning, but change the words or mode of speaking.(59) In other words,
as the faith is put into the words of various cultures, its linguistic
form may change. In addition, the context and audience of remarks must
be taken into account in order to understand charitably the true
intention of the author. In the preface to Contra errores Graecorum he
wrote:
Since errors arising concerning the faith gave an occasion to the
doctors of the Church that matters of faith might be passed on with
greater care for the elimination of arising errors; it is clear that
holy teachers who were before Arius did not so speak concerning the
unity of the divine essence as teachers who followed. And similarly it
happens concerning other errors, not only among diverse teachers but
even in that most excellent of teachers Augustine, it appears clearly.
For in the works that he composed after the heresy of the Pelagians
arose, he spoke more cautiously concerning the freedom of the will than
he had in the books which he composed before the aforementioned heresy
arose. In those books in which he defends the freedom of the will
against the Manicheans, he said certain things which the Pelagians,
opponents of divine grace, took up in defense of their errors. And so it
is no wonder, after the rise of various errors, if modern teachers of
the faith speak more cautiously and seemingly perfectly concerning the
doctrine of faith so that all heresy might be avoided. Hence, if some
things in the writings of ancient teachers is found which is not said
with as much caution as maintained by moderns, they are not to be
condemned or cast aside; but it is not necessary to embrace these
things, but interpret them reverently.
Errors are the occasion of handing on the teaching of the Church
regarding a certain matter with greater care (majori circumspectione).
This care results in a difference in expression between those teachers
writing before heresy versus those after the heresy. Aquinas cited the
example of the Fathers before and after Arius regarding the unity of the
Divinity. Aquinas noted that that this event occasioned a new article of
the creed to emerge: "For Arius believed in the omnipotent and
eternal Father: but he did not believe in the equality and
consubstantiality of the Son with the Father; and therefore it was
necessary to add an article concerning the person of the Son in order to
settle this matter."(60) Of course, prior to Arius there was, so to
speak, no matter to be settled. The clarified and developed teaching
only emerges out of an historically contingent moment--the arrival of
Arian teaching.
Aquinas saw these shifts in presentation not only with respect to
the Church's teaching as a whole but also in respect to individual
Fathers of the Church. The teaching of those earlier Fathers that seem
erroneous from a later perspective is not to be rejected, but
interpreted reverently (reverenter). Aquinas repeated this injunction in
his Commentary on John: "Now although what is said here by these
holy men is orthodox, care must be taken to avoid the reproach which
some receive for this. For the early doctors and saints were so intent
upon refuting the emerging errors concerning the faith that they seemed
meanwhile to fall into the opposite ones. For example, Augustine
speaking against the Manicheans, who destroyed the freedom of the will,
disputed in such terms that he seemed to have fallen into the heresy of
Pelagius."(61) Augustine's teachings about the will shifted
when the encroaching heresy was Pelagianism rather than Manicheanism.
Historical context makes a difference both in understanding past
teaching and in presenting present teaching.
For Aquinas, these developments were entirely appropriate for even
the Scriptures themselves are partially in response to heretical errors
arising in the early Church. Aquinas showed an awareness that the
Johannine Gospel responds to a particular crisis of Christian faith. In
the prologue to his commentary he wrote:
For while the other Evangelists treat principally of the mysteries
of the humanity of Christ, John, especially and above all, makes known
the divinity of Christ in his Gospel.... He did this because, after the
other Evangelists had written their Gospels, heresies had arisen
concerning the divinity of Christ, to the effect that Christ was purely
and simply a man, as Ebion and Cerinthus falsely thought. And so John
the Evangelist, who had drawn the truth about the divinity of the Word
from the very fountain-head of the divine breast, wrote this Gospel at
the request of the faithful. And in it he gives us the doctrine of the
divinity of Christ and refutes all heresies.(62)
Thus, as long as false understandings of revelation occur, there
will be a stimulus for understanding more deeply revealed truths.
"And these errors, for all that, exercised the talents of the
faithful toward a more diligent penetration and understanding of divine
truth, just as the evils which occur in creatures are ordered by God to
some good.(63)
Although Aquinas recognized that historically contingent
circumstances influence the liturgical and doctrinal life of the Church,
unlike Lindbeck's account of development, for Aquinas, a council in
restating and reformulating Church teaching does not and cannot reverse
or contradict earlier teaching but rather fulfills and makes explicit
what was earlier implicit.
It should be said that in any council whatsoever some creed was
instituted on account of some error that is condemned in the council.
Hence a later council was not making another creed than the first, but
that which is implicitly contained in the first creed is explained
against the existing heresy through certain additions. Hence in the
judgment of the synod of Chalcedon it was said that those who were
gathered in the Council of Constantinople handed down the teaching on
the Holy Spirit, not insinuating that there was anything lacking in
their predecessors who had gathered together at Nicaea, but declaring
their understanding of the Holy Spirit against heretics. What therefore
in the time of ancient councils was not yet necessary is posited here
explicitly. But later it was expressed, with the rising error of certain
people, in a Council gathered in the West by the authority of the Roman
pontiff, by whose authority the ancient councils were also gathered and
confirmed. It was contained nevertheless implicitly when it was said
that Holy Spirit proceeds from the Father.(64)
Those Fathers of later councils hand down determinations which were
"not implying that there was anything wanting in the doctrine of
their predecessors who had gathered together at Nicaea, but explaining
what those Fathers had understood of the matter." The implicit is
the unstated intention of those authors; the explicit is what the later
councils, guided by the Spirit, judge the earlier councils would have
said had they been confronted with the historical situation. The Church
judges the new teaching either a valid interpretation of Scripture or an
earlier creed or a heresy in respect of these in light of previous
precedent as determined by the authority of the pope.(65) For Aquinas,
though the particulars of history and the situation occasion the
development of doctrine, true developments never involve a rejection of
previous teaching. In this, he would have agreed with John Henry Newman
who characterized one note of authentic development in his Essay on
Development as that which "illustrates, not obscures, corroborates,
not corrects, the body of thought from which it proceeds."(66)
A POSSIBLE RESPONSE TO DULLES'S OBJECTION
How might one respond to the objection that arises from
Dulles's proper recognition that Thomas thought apostolic teaching
was sufficient for our instruction? Does this exclude doctrinal
development? For Aquinas, the first principles of theology are the
articles of the creed and the creed in turn summarizes what is found in
Scripture. Like other medieval theologians, the Angelic Doctor
recognized many senses of Scripture. Aquinas rooted his account of
theology in the literal sense of Scripture, and what the author intends
to communicate constitutes the literal sense.(67) Since God is the
author of Scripture, Aquinas following Augustine held that there might
be multiplicity of true meanings intended by God in the literal sense of
Scripture.(68) Divine authorship of Scripture leads the text to have a
profound depth of meaning unlike any other.
When combined with other Thomistic theses, namely God's
perfect simplicity and the inability of any human being to comprehend
God's essence, it follows that a complete understanding of the many
true meanings of the literal sense is and will always remain elusive.
God's incomprehensible essence is one with God's
understanding, will, and intention. As God is beyond comprehension, so
the Word of God is beyond comprehension. Scripture therefore must always
remain mysterious in a way no other text is. Thus, even brief phrases of
Scripture are filled with deep meaning. For example, in commenting on
the passage factus ex muliere in his commentary on Galatians, c.4,
lesson 2, Thomas unpacks deep christological significance out of this
one phrase arguing that it excludes both Nestorianism and Valentinianism
as well as shows that Mary is the Mother of God.(69) Examples could be
multiplied indicating Thomas's confidence in the pregnant meaning
of the literal sense, a meaning that even the human author may not fully
appreciate. In the words of Aquinas: "since the prophet's mind
is a defective instrument, as stated above, even true prophets know not
all that the Holy Ghost means by the things they see, or speak, or even
do."(70) Aquinas's account of Scripture's divine
authorship ensures that we could never have a definitive understanding
of the text, for a human being could never fully comprehend the divine
intention which is nothing else than the divine essence.
In addition, there is always need of an explanation of Scripture.
"The purpose of Scripture," wrote Aquinas, "is the
instruction of people; however this instruction of the people by the
Scriptures cannot take place save through the exposition of the
saintS."(71) There is no new public revelation but there will
frequently be need for a fresh explanation of revelation situated in a
new time and place and tailored for a specific audience. This needed
explanation (interpretatio sermonum) by the saints is a gift of the Holy
Spirit.(72) Aquinas noted elsewhere in terms of understanding this
revelation, "the faith is able to be better explained in this
respect each day and was made more explicit through the study of the
saints."(73) Given the ever changing audience, the telos of
Scripture cannot be reached without an ever adapting interpretation or
development. Therefore, it is not just that the nature and the purpose
of Scripture for Aquinas allow for doctrinal developments, but rather
that the nature and purpose of Scripture invite such development.
RELEVANCE OF AQUINAS'S ACCOUNT OF DEVELOPMENT
The question of development of doctrine is arguably the most
important question facing the contemporary Church. How does one
simultaneously be faithful to the original kerygma while at the same
time adapting to existing needs and circumstances? How can one adhere to tradition but not be stymied by it? Which changes faithfully develop
previous teaching and which changes undermine what was taught in the
past? Omnipresent in the background of particular matters of dispute in
the contemporary Church is the issue of doctrinal development.
How does Aquinas fit into this discussion? A number of Catholic
thinkers have an inclination to "freeze" theology as if no or
only the most minimal development is possible, and this petrifaction sometimes finds a Thomistic justification. In the words of Avery Dulles:
"In the past few centuries it began to appear as though the
positions of Thomas Aquinas on most points were destined to become the
positions of the Church for the rest of time. With its high degree of
systematization and its tenacity in adhering to the patristic and
medieval tradition, Catholicism became par excellence the Church of
historical continuity. ..."(74) A resistance to development may be
linked with a harkening back to Thomas Aquinas, a recommendation one
finds often in magisterial pronouncements from Leo XIII through John
Paul II. The Second Vatican Council decree on priestly formation writes:
"[B]y way of making the mysteries of salvation known as thoroughly
as they can be, students should learn to penetrate them more deeply with
the help of the speculative reason exercised under the tutelage of St.
Thomas."(75) In Fides et Ratio, John Paul II adds that: "the
Church has been justified in consistently proposing Saint Thomas as a
master of thought and a model of the right way to do theology."(76)
But some have seemed to equate following Thomas with a strict adherence
to 13th century formulations and theologies. However, if Thomas himself
has some account of development, then in vain may Thomas be appealed to
in rejecting development per se. Thus, a link between Thomas or Thomism
and a petrified theology would not be a historically justifiable one. To
be faithful to Thomas is to be open to development.
On the other hand, the allegedly rigid Thomistic system that
attracts some Catholic intellectuals repels many others. Some
theologians may have rejected the Thomistic approach on the assumption
that it lacks any historical awareness, is closed as such to new
insights, and cannot in principle respond to the chief theological
challenges of contemporary times. That Thomas Aquinas no longer enjoys
the status he once did, especially in Catholic departments of theology,
is evident. This shift away from the Thomistic approach among many
contemporary theologians, though not as prevalent among moral
theologians, resulted from a number of factors but may be partially
based on an presupposition that Aquinas simply cannot contribute to
renewal.(77) However, if Aquinas does indeed have some account of
development and if the Thomistic method can make use of contemporary
historical resources, then the Thomistic approach in theology may be,
after all, a legitimate contemporary model and not merely a chapter in
historical theology. Theologians of the 21st century when turning to the
findings of contemporary archeologists, biblicists, and hermeneuticists
or when considering possible developments of doctrine are not thereby
committed to abandoning the Thomistic conception of theology.
This Thomistic approach opens up new avenues in the discussion of
development of doctrine itself in at least two ways. First, certain
organic and historically situated accounts of development of doctrine
are sometimes accused of roaming very far from the ancient sources,
especially Sacred Scripture. Such perceived distancing from some of the
chief sources of Christian wisdom can cause not just ecumenical strains
but also seem to belittle the definitive importance of the Scripture for
theology. In the words of Vatican II's Dei Verbum: "Sacred
theology rests on the written word of God, together with sacred
tradition, as its primary and perpetual foundation. By scrutinizing in
the light of faith all truth stored up in the mystery of Christ,
theology is most powerfully strengthened and constantly rejuvenated by
that word. For the Sacred Scriptures contain the word of God and since
they are inspired really are the word of God; and so the study of the
sacred page is, as it were, the soul of sacred theology."(78)
Doubtless contemporary readings of Scripture would often conflict with
Thomas's, but the role Scripture plays in Thomistic theology is
profound. Thomas's theology arises from ancient creeds that are
nothing else than summaries and interpretations of the Scriptures. His
approach to development, linked as it is with Scripture, provides the
flexibility needed to account for the historical record of Christian
teaching without losing unity with the ancient sources.
Secondly, it is characteristically assumed that the propositional
account of revelation must be linked to the logical account of
development and that in order to adopt the organic or historically
situated model of development the propositional account of revelation
must be abandoned. Although it may not be entirely adequate to say that
Thomas had a "propositional" account of revelation,
Aquinas's account of development suggests that one need not abandon
the propositional model of revelation in order to have the organic or
even the historically situated account of development. Since Aquinas
viewed Scripture's literal sense as reflecting the intention not
just of the human author but of God, the literal sense ends up with a
plenitude of meaning that allows the flexibility needed for the organic
and historically situated accounts. In the end, the propositional
account of revelation may be found defective, but it cannot be found
defective on the ground that it excludes the full range of developmental
theories demanded by an honest appraisal of the historical record.
CONCLUSION
Aquinas in some sense had an account of the development of
doctrine, understood for him as the unfolding of implicit to a more
explicit teaching. Prima facie, there is a difficulty reconciling
Aquinas's belief that the Apostles have the most full knowledge of
the mysteries of faith and that earlier Fathers have a more implicit
faith than later Fathers of the Church. Aquinas acknowledged both
truths. The Apostles having intimate association with the Risen Christ
as well as special graces allowing them to fulfill their vocation know
Jesus in a privileged way. But reflection on the revelation recorded in
Scripture offers believers the chance for a participation in the
scientia of God, but this scientia is an imperfect participation.
The deep riches of Scripture, the primary source upon which
Aquinas's theology is based, both excludes reversals or denials of
the text as well as opens the possibility for ever deeper understanding
of the truths and the Truth therein contained. Aquinas, indeed,
foreshadowed aspects of the logical, organic, and historical approaches
to development of doctrine elaborated by later theologians. Unlike
Newman, Aquinas did not provide "notes" or other criteria for
distinguishing true developments from corruptions of doctrine. However,
like Newman, he recognized that theology and doctrine are open to
development. Although the substance of faith remains the same, the
number of articles, the faith's explicit formulation and
articulation, develops over time. Though it would be exaggerated to
suggest that Aquinas handled the theme with the same sophistication or
historical awareness as later authors such as Newman or Rahner, it would
also be exaggerated to suggest St. Thomas had no sense whatsoever of the
development of doctrine.(79)
(1) See, for example, Lonergan's doctoral dissertation Grace
and Freedom: Operative Grace in the Thought of St. Thomas Aquinas, ed.
J. Patout Burns, intro. Frederick E. Crowe (New York: Herder and Herder,
1971). Here Lonergan argued that on the question of operative grace
Aquinas changed his mind a number of times. Alternations are visible
sometimes even within one work as the manuscript evidence makes clear.
See Jean-Pierre Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas: The Person and His Work,
trans. Robert Royal (Washington: Catholic University of America, 1996)
101.
(2) See A. F. von Guten, "In Principio Erat Verbum: Une
evolution de saint Thomas en theologie trinitaire," in Ordo
sapientiae et amoris: Image et message de Saint Thomas d'Aquin, ed.
Carolos-Josaphat Pinto de Oliveira (Fribourg: Editions Universitaires,
1993) 119-41.
(3) See Avery Dulles, The Resilient Church (New York: Doubleday,
1976) 46.
(4) Jan Hendrik Walgrave, Unfolding Revelation: The Nature of
Doctrinal Development (Philadelphia: Westminister, 1972) 114.
(5) Per Erik Persson, Sacra Doctrina: Reason and Revelation in
Aquinas (Philadelphia: Fortress, 1970) 60, 81.
(6) Henri de Lubac, Theology in History (San Francisco: Ignatius,
1996) 258-59.
(7) Avery Dulles, The Resilient Church 46.
(8) Ibid.
(9) Thomas remarks on the completeness of revelation of Christ in
Scripture in ST 3, q. 64, a. 2 ad 3; In III. Sent. d. 25, q. 2, a. 2, 1
ad 5.
(10)Summa contra gentiles 4. 55 [12].
(11) ST 3, q. 64, a. 2, ad 3.
(12) ST 1-2, q. 1, a. 7, ad 4. Inexplicably, Walgrave does not cite
this article that poses the question "Utrum secundum successionem
temporum articuli fidei creverint," though he cites the following
reference. See also, Disputed Questions on Truth 2, q. 14, a. 12 ad 6.
(13) In III. Sent. d. 25, q. 1, a. 1, 3; ST 2-2, q. 1, a. 9, ad 1.
(14) In III. Sent. d. 25, q. 2, a. 2, 1, ad 5; De pot. 10, 4, ad
13.
(15) ST 1, q. 36, a. 2, ad 2. Translations of Latin are mine unless
noted otherwise.
(16) Dulles, The Resilient Church 47, 49.
(17) M. M. Tuyaerts, L'Evolution du dogme: Etude theologique
(Louvain: Editions Nova et Vetera, 1919); Charles Boyer, "Quest-ce
que la theologie? Reflexions sur une controverse," Gregorianum 21
(1940) 264-65.
(18) George A. Lindbeck, "Doctrinal Development and Protestant
Theology," in Man as Man and Believer, ed. Edward Schillebeeckx,
Concilium 21 (New York: Paulist, 1967) 138-39, as cited in Dulles, A
Resilient Church 51.
(19) See Thomas Rausch, "Doctrinal Development," in New
Dictionary of Theology, ed. Joseph Komonchak et al. (Wilmington: Michael
Glazier, 1989) 280-83, and Jan Walgrave, Unfolding Revelation: The
Nature of Doctrinal Development 114, and passim.
(20) As Henri de Lubac makes clear in his essay "The Problem
of the Development of Dogma" the approach to development as
involving logical deduction alone was never widely endorsed and had few
adherents. The vast majority of neo-Scholastic theologians agreed with
Newman that a more organic or "vitalistic" approach was
necessary. See de Lubac, Theology in History (San Francisco: Ignatius,
1996) 248-80.
(21) ST 1, q. 36, a. 2, ad 1.
(22) Ibid.
(23) Stephen Brown, "Declarative and Deductive Theology in the
Early Fourteenth Century," Miscellanea mediaevalia 26 (1998)
648-55, at 649. See also his "Peter of Candia's Hundred-Year
`History' of the Theologian's Role," Medieval Philosophy
and Theology 1 (1991) 156-74.
(24) ST 2-2, q. 2, a. 7, ad 3.
(25) ST 2-2, q. 1, a. 7.
(26) ST 1, q. 1, a. 8.
(27) ST 1, q. 1, a. 5, ad 2.
(28) Thomas Aquinas, De trinitate, q. 2, a. 3, sc1.
(29) Disputed Questions on Truth 2, q. 11, a. 1, ad 12.
(30) ST 1, q. 1, a. 8, ad 2; ST 1, q. 1, a. 5, ad 2. On this, see
too Mark Johnson, "God's Knowledge in Our Frail Mind: The
Thomistic Model of Theology," Angelicum 76 (1999) 25-46.
(31) ST 1, q. 44, a. 2. Thomas continues writing about the progress
of philosophy through Plato to Aristotle. See too, De sub. Sep. c. 9.
(32) Thomas Aquinas, Sententia libri ethicorum, b. 1, lectio 11,
133; Litzinger translation.
(33) ST 3, q. 83, a. 3, ad 6. "Formerly the priests did not
use golden but wooden chalices; but Pope Zephyrinus ordered the mass to
be said with glass patens; and subsequently Pope Urban had everything
made of silver." Afterwards it was decided that "the
Lord's chalice with the paten should be made entirely of gold, or
of silver or at least of tin. But it is not to be made of brass, or
copper, because the action of the wine thereon produces verdigris, and
provokes vomiting. But no one is to presume to sing mass with a chalice
of wood or of glass because as the wood is porous, the consecrated blood
would remain in it; while glass is brittle and there might arise danger
of breakage; and the same applies to stone. Consequently, out of
reverence for the sacrament, it was enacted that the chalice should be
made of the aforesaid materials." (Dominican Fathers'
translation.) Here the most ancient tradition is suppressed (drinking
from wooden chalice) and modern ones preferred based on papal authority
as well as the fittingness of having liturgical vessels that better take
into account the reverence due and the care one should take with the
sacred species.
(34) ST 3, q. 72, a. 4; q. 72, a. 12; q. 78, a. 6, etc. See also
Liam G. Walsh, "Liturgy in the Theology of St. Thomas," The
Thomist 38 (1974) 557-83 for numerous references as well as a treatment
of Thomas's understanding and uses of liturgy.
(35) ST 3, q. 27, a. 1, sed contra.
(36) See ST 3, q. 80, a. 10, ad 5 and ST 3, q. 80, a. 12 for
Aquinas's account of historical practices with respect to reception
of the Eucharist. See also Super primare epistolam ad Corinthios, chap.
11, v. 25, lect. 6.
(37) Walter H. Principe, C.S.B., "Tradition in Thomas
Aquinas's Scripture Commentaries," in The Quadrilog: Tradition
and the Future of Ecumenism: Essays in Honor of George H. Tavard, ed.
Kenneth Hagen (Collegeville: Liturgical, 1994) 43-60, at 49-50.
(38) Super primam epistolam ad Corinthios, chap. 11, v. 25, lect.
6.
(39) ST 1-2, q. 101, a. 2, ad 1.
(40) For other examples see: ST 1-2, q. 107, a. 3, ad 1; ST 2-2, q.
2, a. 8.
(41)ST 1-2, q. 2, a. 8
(42) See e.g. ST 3, qq. 73-81, on the Eucharist.
(43) G. Geenan, "The Place of Tradition in the Theology of St.
Thomas," The Thomist 15 (1952) 133.
(44) Ibid. 133-34.
(45) ST 1, q. 1, a. 1 sc.
(46) ST 1, q. 1, a. 3, ad 1.
(47) ST 1, q. 1, a. 8; ST 1, q. 1, a. 6, ad 1.
(48) ST 2-2, q. 1, a. 9, ad 1.
(49) ST 1, q. 1, a. 1, emphasis in the original.
(50) It should also be noted that doubt furnishes the occasion of
distinguishing articles (ST 2-2, q. 1, a. 6).
(51) Augustine in the Confessions wrote: "Improbatio quippe
haereticorum facit eminere quid ecclesia tua sentiat et quid habeat sana
doctrina" (VII, 19).
(52) ST 2-2, q. 1, a. 10, ad 1.
(53) A frequent theme in his treatment of this subject, Aquinas
repeated this elsewhere; see ST 2-2, q. 1, a. 10 ad 1.
(54) Pace, Walgrave for instance who writes: "[For medieval
theologians,] the `authorities' of antiquity were not viewed in
their historical setting and succession, but only as building blocks for
their dialectical constructions or doctrinal systems" (114).
(55) The topic of the existence or lack of an "historical
consciousness" among medieval intellectuals and common folk depends
in great part on what is meant by the term. A discussion of the possible
meanings of the term and its application or lack of application to
persons in the Middle Ages is beyond the scope of the present
discussion.
(56) ST 2-2, q. 1, a. 9 ad 6.
(57) See Super primam epistolam ad Corinthios, chap. 11, v. 25,
lect. 6.
(58) For contextualization and interpretation of this work, see
James A. Weisheipl, Friar Thomas d'Aquino, rev. ed. (Washington:
Catholic University, 1983) 389; and Mark D. Jordan, "Theological
Exegesis and Aquinas's Treatise `against the Greeks',"
Church History 56 (December 1987) 445-56; and Leo J. Elders,
"Thomas Aquinas and the Fathers of the Church" in The
Reception of the Church Fathers in the West, ed. Irena Backus (New York:
E. J. Brill, 1997).
(59) See prologue of Contra errores Graecorum 45-71.
(60) ST 2-2, q. 1, a. 8, ad 3. Arius enim credidit Patrem
omnipotentem, et aeternum: sed non credidit Filium coaequalem, et
consubstantialem Patri; et ideo necessarium fuit apponere articulum de
persona Filii, ad hoc determinandum.
(61) Thomas Aquinas, On Faith and Reason, ed. Stephen Brown
(Indianapolis: Hackett, 1999) 259. In Johannem, lecture 7, 174; trans.
J. A. Weisheipl and F. R. Archer.
(62) Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on the Gospel of St. John, Part I,
trans. J. A. Weisheipl and F. R. Larcher (Albany: Magi, 1980) 26.
(63) Summa contra gentiles 4, chap. 55 [9].
(64) ST 1, q. 36, a. 2, ad 2.
(65) ST 2-2, q. 1, a. 10; see also Yves M.-J. Congar, O. P.,
"Saint Thomas Aquinas and the Infallibility of the Papal
Magisterium," The Thomist 38 (1974) 81-105.
(66) John Henry Newman, Essay on the Development of Christian
Doctrine (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame, 1989) 200.
(67) ST 1, q. 1, a. 10; De potentia, q. 4, a. 1.
(68) ST 1, q. 1, a. 10.
(69) Throughout this section I am much indebted to Leo Elder's
article, "St. Thom as Aquinas and Holy Scripture" forthcoming
in a volume about Aquinas and his sources edited by Timothy Smith.
(70) ST 2-2, q. 173, a. 4, [English Dominican Province
translation].
(71) Quodlibet 12, q. 16, a. unicus [27].
(72) Ibid.; Summa contra gentiles 3, 154 [19]; In 1 Cor. 12, lect.
2.
(73) In III Sent. 25, 2, 2, 1, ad 5.
(74) Avery Dulles, The Survival of Dogma (New York: Image, 1973)
176.
(75) Optatam totius no. 16.
(76) Fides et ratio no. 43; see also the pope's address to the
International Pontificial Athenaeum Angelicum (17 November 1979) in
Insegnamenti II, 2 (1979) 1177-89; his address to the participants of
the Eighth International Thomistic Congress (13 September 1980) in
Insegnamenti III, 2 (1980) 604-15; address to the participants at the
International Congress of the Saint Thomas Society on the doctrine of
the soul in Saint Thomas (4 January 1986) in Insegnamenti IX, 1 (1986)
18-24. Also the Sacred Congregation for Catholic Education, Ratio
fundamentalis institutions sacerdotalis (6 January 1970) 70-75 in AAS
62.
(77) On the shift away from Thomistic thought in Catholic circles
and an evaluation of its rationale, see Ralph McInerny, Thomism in an
Age of Renewal (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame, 1968); and John
Paul II, Fides et ratio no. 61.
(78) Dei Verbum no. 24.
(79) Thanks to Thomas Rausch, S.J., John Jenkins, C.S.C., Matthew
Levering, James K. A. Smith, Mark Johnson, and Chris Curry who provided
helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper. Participants at the
Thomistic Institute on the Sources of Thomas Aquinas held at the
University of Notre Dame, made possible by the Saint Gerard Foundation
and the Strake Foundation, were also helpful in the course of its
revision. I can be consulted through my webpage: http://
hometown.aol.com/crkaczor.
CHRISTOPHER KACZOR received his Ph.D. from the University of Notre
Dame. He is currently assistant professor of philosophy at Loyola
Marymount University, Los Angeles. A specialist in medieval thought and
ethics, he has published articles in a number of journals including
International Philosophical Quarterly, Josephinum Journal of Theology,
The Thomist, and Theological Studies (1998). He edited Proportionalism
For and Against (Marquette University, 2000) and has authored
Proportionalism and the Natural Law Tradition (CUA Press, 2002).