A note on two erroneous ways of defending the pure time preference theory of interest.
Topan, Mihai Vladimir ; Paun, Cristian
INTRODUCTION
The aim of the present paper is specific and narrow. Nevertheless,
the issue it tackles is one which should be of general interest both
from a narrower, technical perspective and a liberal arts educational
perspective. The complex world in which we live is hardly intelligible
without sound economic theories in general, and at least some view on
the problem of interest. As interest rates are among the key elements
for a proper understanding of the crisis in which the world has found
itself in the last few years, this is probably a good moment to pause
and contemplate anew that fundamental phenomenon. But, as Mises says
somewhere, there are no shortcuts to wisdom. Understanding a phenomenon
of reality usually implies the readiness to go through the painstaking process of following theoretical debates, some wider, some narrower. And
of following arguments--some straightforward, some more cumbersome--for
and against one theory or another. A bit of this is proposed below.
Although the authors consider the pure time-preference theory of
interest (PTPTI) to be the valid theory of interest, the focus here will
be on two arguments in favor of it that we consider problematic. After a
brief restatement of PTPTI, we will proceed to analyze the first
argument: namely, that by performing a reduction ad absurdum on the
time-preference principle we obtain the unacceptable result that man
must never act or consume, or, which is the same, man must always prefer
the future (other things equal). After critiquing this argument and
offering a possible modified correct version of it, we will proceed to
the second (problematic, in our view) argument in favor of
PTPTI--namely, that thinking in terms of money succeeds in isolating
pure (time-preference determined) interest. After offering a criticism
of this view also, we conclude.
One last point for this introduction: even though the contribution
of this paper--if indeed there is one--is mainly negative, we are
confident that it can help more forcefully restating PTPTI and defending
it against its critics. Nevertheless, we think that task should be
relegated to a future article.
THE TIME PREFERENCE PRINCIPLE AND THE PURE TIME PREFERENCE THEORY
OF INTEREST, IN BRIEF
The pure time preference theory of interest is one of the core
elements of Austrian economics. One can say it is almost a signature of
this way of doing economic analysis. It is also implied to a great
extent in sub-domains such as capital theory, the analysis of the
structure of production or the theory of the business cycle. It is,
therefore, rather difficult to overestimate its importance.
Nevertheless, it has constantly spurred controversy both at the time of
its first more systematic exposition at the hands of Bohm-Bawerk (1) and
more recently. (2) While one cannot do justice to it in a few
paragraphs, we must nevertheless attempt a brief presentation for the
purpose of establishing the theoretical context of the arguments
discussed. We take as canonical the Mises-Rothbard version of PTPTI, (3)
as it can be found in their two major works, namely Human Action and
Man, Economy, and State. We proceed in two steps, first presenting their
concept of time-preference and then its immediate result, interest.
Thus, pertaining to time-preference itself, for Mises: "Other
things being equal, satisfaction in a nearer period of the future is
preferred to satisfaction in a more distant period; disutility is seen
in waiting" (2008, p. 480). And, "Satisfaction of a want in
the nearer future is, other things being equal, preferred to that in the
farther distant future. Present goods are more valuable than future
goods" (2008, pp. 480-481).
Likewise, for Rothbard:
A fundamental and constant truth about human action is that man
prefers his ends to be achieved in the shortest possible time.
Given the specific satisfaction, the sooner it arrives, the better.
This results from the fact that time is always scarce, and a means
to be economized. The sooner any end is attained, the better. Thus,
with any given end to be attained, the shorter the period of
action, i.e., production, the more preferable for the actor. This
is the universal fact of time preference. At any point of time, and
for any action, the actor most prefers to have his end attained in
the immediate present. Next best for him is the immediate future,
and the further in the future the attainment of the end appears to
be, the less preferable it is. The less waiting time, the more
preferable it is for him (2009, p. 15; italics in original).
Time preference may be called the preference for present
satisfaction over future satisfaction or present good over future
good, provided it is remembered that it is the same satisfaction
(or "good") that is being compared over the periods of time (2009,
p. 15, n. 15; italics in the original).
For Mises and Rothbard, there is no question that the immediate
(and somehow obvious or self-evident) consequence of time-preference is
the existence of (originary) interest. Thus, Mises says:
Time preference manifests itself in the phenomenon of originary
interest, i.e., the discount of future goods as against present
goods (2008, p. 521).
Interest is a homogeneous phenomenon. There are no different
sources of interest. Interest on durable goods and interest on
consumption-credit are like other kinds of interest an outgrowth of
the higher valuation of present goods as against future goods
(2008, p. 523).
Originary interest is the ratio of the value assigned to
want-satisfaction in the immediate future and the value assigned to
want-satisfaction in remote periods of the future. It manifests
itself in the market economy in the discount of future goods as
against present goods. It is a ratio of commodity prices, not a
price in itself. There prevails a tendency toward the equalization
of this ratio for all commodities. In the imaginary construction of
the evenly rotating economy the rate of originary interest is the
same for all commodities (2008, p. 523).
And for Rothbard, again:
It is this time element, the result of various individuals' time
preferences, and not the alleged independent productivity of
capital goods, from which the interest rate and interest income
arise (2009, p. 352; italics in original).
... the interest rate ... is the agio, or discount on future goods
as compared with present goods, i.e., the premium commanded by
presents goods over future goods.... [T]his exchange rate between
present goods and future goods is not only uniform in the
production process, but throughout the entire market system. It is
the "social rate of time preference." It is the "price of time" on
the market as a resultant of all the individual valuations of that
good (2009, p. 353).
The interest rates discussed here are simply hypothetical
schedules, and they indicate and reveal the time-preference
schedules of each individual. In the aggregate ... the interaction
of the time preferences and hence the supply-demand schedules of
individuals on the time market determine the pure rate of interest
on the market. They do so in the same way that individual
valuations determine aggregate supply and demand schedules for
goods, which in turn determine market prices. And once again, it is
utilities and utilities alone, here in the form of time-preferences,
that determine the market result; the explanation does not lie in
some sort of "mutually determining process" of preferences and
market consequences (2009, p. 382).
This pure rate of interest, then, is determined solely by the time
preferences of the individuals in the society, and by no other
factor (2009, p. 389; italics in the original).
We have here in brief, the essence of the pure time-preference
theory of interest. Apart from the fact that it has many important
general implications (that interest is a price or price-ratio, or a
market phenomenon not some fiat or convention; that it is not the price
of money; that it is not the fruit of exploitation but of
inter-temporal, mutually beneficial, exchange; that it cannot therefore
be abolished, or manipulated without suffering the natural consequences;
or that it cannot be conceived as falling, in real terms, below zero)
this theory of interest has also some more technical consequences which
are, again, very important in the Austrian paradigm. Thus, the
disentangling of profit from interest is dependent (so far, at least) on
this way of seeing interest; this in turn opens up the way of
understanding profit, entrepreneurship and the firm. But probably the
most spectacular implication of the time-preference theory of interest
is the Austrian business cycle theory which is, mainly, a theory of the
inter-temporal dis-coordination of the structure of production caused by
the manipulation of interest rates by governments. Loaded with
consequences, PTPTI is neither an easy thing to swallow, nor some chaff to be dusted off one's analytical toolbox. That is why debate is
crucial. Let us now proceed to the two arguments in favor of PTPTI and
their critique.
THE FIRST ERRONEOUS DEFENSE OR THE PROBLEM OF THE LOGICAL OPPOSITE
(THE NEGATION) OF TIME PREFERENCE
One of the most forceful and elegant arguments in favor of PTPTI is
the--we think we can say famous--Misesian reductio ad absurdum. Mises
delivers it in Human Action (in the chapter preceding the one dedicated
to interest proper):
Time preference is a categorical requisite of human action. No mode
of action can be thought of in which satisfaction within a nearer
period of the future is not--other things being equal--preferred to
that in a later period. The very act of gratifying a desire implies
that gratification at the present instant is preferred to that at a
later instant. He who consumes a nonperishable good instead of
postponing consumption for an indefinite later moment thereby
reveals a higher valuation of present satisfaction as compared with
later satisfaction. If he were not to prefer satisfaction in a
nearer period of the future to that in a remoter period, he would
never consume and so satisfy wants. He would always accumulate, he
would never consume and enjoy. He would not consume today, but he
would not consume tomorrow either, as the morrow would confront him
with the same alternative (2008, p. 481; italics ours)
We must conceive that a man who does not prefer satisfaction within
a nearer period of the future to that in a remoter period would
never achieve consumption and enjoyment at all (2008, p. 483).
If acting man, other conditions being equal, were not to prefer,
without exception, consumption in a nearer future to that in the
remoter future, he would always save, never consume. What restricts
the amount of saving and investment is time preference (2008, p.
487).
The main idea of the above selections is that trying to negate the
principle of time preference, gets one to an absurdity. And this
absurdity is the "indefinite" postponement of consumption: man
"would never consume and so satisfy wants."
Two observations are in order here. First, Mises frames his
expositions of the time-preference principle mostly in terms of
consumption, even though it can also be put in (more general) terms of
action, as we will see below that other Austrian authors do. So, one
could say there is room for clarifications: is time preference grounded
in consumption--a particular type of action, as not all actions are acts
of consumption--or in action in general? Even though this might not be
inconsequential, it does not affect our argument.
Second, what Mises does is logically peculiar. He negates a general
statement--man always prefers satisfaction/consumption sooner--and
arrives at a general statement--man always prefers future
satisfaction/consumption (which equals never to consume/ enjoy the
satisfaction)--which he finds, justifiably, absurd. But from the general
principles of logic and reasoning we know that the negation of a general
statement must be a particular one. Therefore Mises must have made a
mistaken reductio ad absurdum. (4) What would be, then, the right way of
negating the time preference principle? Before turning to this question
let us see a few more instances where Austrian authors reason like
Mises.
Rothbard more or less restates the Misesian argument:
If man, other things being equal, did not prefer satisfaction in
the present to satisfaction in the future, he would never consume;
he would invest all his time and labor in increasing the production
of future goods. But "never consuming" is an absurdity, since
consuming is the end of all production (2009, p. 51).
Huerta de Soto also employs the same argumentative turn, albeit
doing it in terms of action rather than consumption:
[I]t is impossible to imagine a human action to which the principle
of time preference does not apply. A world without time preference
is inconceivable and would be absurd: it would mean people always
preferred the future to the present, and objectives would be
postponed, one after the other, just before they were reached, and
therefore no end would ever be achieved and human action would be
senseless (2009, pp. 271-272).
Professor Block gives what I would probably choose as the canonical
version of this argument (especially the last phrase):
If this were not so [time preference], we could never act in the
present, for every action done now could have been done in the
future. The fact that we choose to act in the present, when we
could have waited, shows that we prefer the present; that we enjoy
goods, the sooner, the better. But the future will present the same
alternatives: action and non action. Future action will thus also
imply time preference for the present, paradoxically. By acting in
the immediate future, instead of waiting for the even more distant
future, we also show ourselves as present oriented. The only way to
illustrate a lack of preference for the present is never to act at
all--a manifest impossibility for human beings (1990, p. 199;
underlining ours; italics in original).
One more thing before we proceed further to what we consider to be
the proper way of negating time preference. If above, where we presented
the PTPTI in brief, we were able to provide quotes both about the
time-preference principle as such and its crucial
consequence/manifestation (originary interest), we should be able to
contemplate the implications of negating time-preference in terms of
interest (not only action, or consumption). Otherwise put, if negating
time-preference leads to absurdities in terms of action, it should at
the same time lead to absurdities (or at least just oddities) in terms
of interest. And indeed one can find in Mises passages which can be
interpreted in this way, such as the following:
[T]he fading away of originary interest would mean that people do
not care at all for want-satisfaction in nearer periods of the
future. It would mean that they prefer to an apple available today,
tomorrow, in one year or in ten years, two apples available in a
thousand or ten thousand years (2008, p.524).
We cannot even think of a world in which originary interest would
not exist as an inexorable element in every kind of action (2008,
p. 524).
Originary interest cannot disappear as long there is scarcity and
therefore action (2008, p.525).
If there were no originary interest, capital goods would not be
devoted to immediate consumption and capital would not be consumed.
On the contrary, under such an unthinkable an unimaginable state of
affairs there would be no consumption at all, but only saving,
accumulation of capital, and investment (2008, p. 529).
The disappearance of originary interest would be tantamount to the
disappearance of consumption. The increase of originary interest
beyond all measure would be tantamount to the disappearance of
saving and any provision for the future (2008, p. 530).
A quick observation: in the quotes above, the second and the third
imply that (positive) originary interest cannot disappear unless
together with all action and scarcity, while the first, fourth and fifth
state that its disappearance would be equivalent to the disappearance of
consumption (but not all action, as saving, investment, and accumulation
would somehow continue, albeit absurdly). There we have again that
(seeming) ambiguity of the Misesian conception of time-preference and
interest: is it in terms of consumption, or more general, in terms of
action?
Arguably, the spirit of the reductio ad absurdum argument is kept
in these statements in terms of interest. Both a world without
time-preference (as stated by Mises) and a world without
interest--unsurprisingly--imply the disappearance of consumption or
action altogether. And this can fairly be accepted as absurd.
Nevertheless, the flaw of the previous arguments remains: the negation
of a general proposition is conceived as another general one, which is
incorrect.
Now let us turn to the question we suggested above. What would be
the negation or logical opposite of the time-preference principle? We
already hinted that it has to be a particular proposition, not a general
one. That is the negation of "all p are q" ("all swans
are white"; "man always prefers the present") must take
the form "there is (at least) one p which is not q"
("there is one swan which is not white"). Applying this
insight to time-preference, the proper negation should sound somewhat
like this: "man sometimes (at least once) prefers the future"
(other things equal, of course). If one feels at this point that
"this cannot be!", that is precisely the point of contention:
why can this not be? While the idea that man always prefers the future
is more readily and immediately rejected as ridiculous, the one that he
might now and then prefer the future does not immediately strike one as
absurd. (5) After all, do we not continually make plans for the more or
less remote future, which intuitively demonstrates a preference to do
some things sometime in the future, rather than right now (at the moment
of planning)? (6)
Here, the Mises-Rothbard Austrian time-preference theory of
interest has its (valid, in our opinion) answers. When one seems to
prefer the future, there is one of the two: (1) other things are not
equal (in most places one cannot or does not want to plan a ski vacation
in July, or an outdoor swimming one in December); or (2) if the
postponed enjoyment seems to be readily and identically (except for the
time element) available at the moment of planning, one probably has more
urgent or important enjoyments to satisfy (or other urgent future
enjoyments to prepare) in the meantime, and there is the proper place to
look for the impact of time-preference, which is still present.
We are now in a strange position. The theoretical, reductio ad
absurdum, justification for time-preference as stated by Austrian
authors is inadequate, while every seeming counter-example to it can,
arguably, be squared with. In our opinion, the way out is to think
through this idea that man could, other things equal, prefer sometimes
the present, sometimes the future (at least once). Properly understood,
it is absurd, because it implies--and this would be the crux of our
argument--the contradictory concept of conscious non-action.
The opposite of time-preference would have to be manifested by man
in a peculiar state. Contemplating the drinking of a glass of wine half
an hour from now, man would have to be conscious, as preferring
otherwise than the time-preference principle stipulates is a preference
nevertheless. But this state could not be an action because if man would
act in the meantime, we would have to shift our focus to that action,
which could very well be driven by time preference. And the situation
could not be considered a counterexample for time-preference (or an
instance of the manifestation of the opposite of time preference).
Therefore, to negate the principle of time-preference as theorized
by Mises and Rothbard, one would have to think through the concept of
conscious non-action, and would have to be able to illustrate it with
realistic examples.
Can there be such a thing as conscious non-action? The short answer
to this is no, as Mises defines action as purposeful, conscious
behavior. So, conscious non-action is a contradiction in terms, an
absurdity. And there we have it--the proper way to defend by reduction
to the absurd the principle of time-preference: if man were not to
always prefer (ceteris paribus) the present, he would have to exhibit
moments or short periods of conscious non-action, which is
contradictory, therefore absurd.
The long answer implies a more thorough investigation of
Mises's view on this, together with highlighting the implications
of accepting the possibility of conscious non-action for praxeology and
economics. We will try to sketch the main lines of this in the following
four points.
First, Mises defines action as purposeful or conscious (he seems to
equate these two) behavior:
Human action is purposeful behavior ... a person's conscious
adjustment to the state of the universe that determines his life ...
the definition itself is adequate and does not need complement or
commentary.
Conscious or purposeful behavior is in sharp contrast to
unconscious behavior, i.e., the reflexes and the involuntary
responses of the body's cells and nerves to stimuli (2008, p. 11).
Second, he seems, sometimes, to allow for the existence of
conscious moments (short intervals) of non-action:
Action is not simply giving preference. Man also shows preference
in situations in which things and events are unavoidable or are
believed to be so. Thus, a man may prefer sunshine to rain and may
wish that the sun would dispel the clouds. He who only wishes and
hopes does not interfere actively with the course of events and
with the shaping of his own destiny. But acting man chooses,
determines, and tries to reach an end. Of two things both of which
he cannot have together he selects one and gives up the other.
Action is therefore always involves both taking and renunciation
(2008, pp. 12-13).
The absence of action is not only the result of full satisfaction;
it can no less be the corollary of the inability to render things
more satisfactory. It can mean hopelessness as well as contentment
(2008, p. 416).
Action is preceded by thinking. Thinking is to deliberate
beforehand over future action and to reflect afterward upon past
action. Thinking and acting are inseparable (2008, p. 177).
Yet, thirdly, Mises suggests strongly that man always acts (while
conscious):
Praxeology consequently does not distinguish between "active" or
energetic and "passive" or indolent man. The vigorous man
industriously striving for the improvement of his condition acts
neither more nor less than the lethargic man who sluggishly takes
things as they come. For to do nothing and to be idle are also
action, they too determine the course of events. Wherever the
conditions for human interference are present, man acts no matter
whether he interferes or refrains from interfering. He who endures
what he could change acts no less than he who interferes in order
to attain another result. A man who abstains from influencing the
operation of physiological and instinctive factors which he could
influence also acts. Action is not only doing but no less omitting
to do what possibly could be done (2008, p. 13).
Indulgence in a routine which possibly could be changed is action
(2008, p. 47).
Fourth, Rothbard emphatically says that man must always act:
Before analyzing the range of alternative choices further, it is
necessary to emphasize that man must always act. Since he is always
in a position to improve his lot, even "doing nothing" is a form of
acting. "Doing nothing"--or spending all of his time in leisure--is
a choice that will affect his supply of consumers' goods.
Therefore, man must always be engaged in choosing and action (2009,
p. 71).
One additional reason for considering that the Misesian
praxeological paradigm cannot accommodate conscious non-action is
provided by the tremendous, systemic, reconfigurations at the
theoretical level that this concept would imply. If conscious
non-actions are relevant for price formation, then an economist would
have to study the more general category of phenomena which might be
called human behavior (both action and conscious non-action), and not
only action. So much for praxeology.
We have thus arrived at the conclusion of the first part of our
article. We have, hopefully, showed the inadequacy of an usual argument
in support of time preference and PTPTI--namely, that not to always
prefer the present (other things equal) would mean to always prefer the
future (which would mean either of the two absurd things: never to
consume or, more general, never to act)--as it constructs the negation
of a universal proposition likewise as a general proposition, which is
incorrect. The way of escape from this is to reframe the reduction to
the absurd as a particular proposition, namely, that to not always
prefer the present would mean to sometimes (at least once) prefer the
future. But this would be equivalent to engaging in what could be called
conscious non-action, a concept we have argued is contradictory,
therefore absurd. These being said, let us proceed to the second
(erroneous) argument.
THE SECOND ERRONEOUS DEFENSE
Recently, Professor Herbener (2011) has given us an important
scholarly instrument in our (always difficult) pursuits into the theory
of interest. There, in his great introduction, he gives us a
crystallized version of the second argument in favor of PTPTI that we
want to tackle here. The gist of it is that the answer to an entire
group of arguments against PTPTI (what is the interest rate in a barter economy, where heterogeneous goods enter into inter-temporal exchanges?
Is time-preference referring to goods, or satisfactions? Is it referring
to the same goods/satisfactions now versus later, or to similar
goods/satisfactions but at different points in time etc.) could come by
thinking interest in terms of money. And that by doing this, the
pure-time preference determination of interest is somehow isolated or
pinned down. Thus, Herbener writes:
This discount of future money relative to present money is interest
and determines the pure, or time preference, rate of interest
(2011, p. 15).
The rate of interest, reflecting pure time preference, emerges in
the exchange of present money for future money (2011, p.36).
And one of the main reasons for the success of this theoretical
strategy stems from the fact that money does not suffer from what
Professor Herbener--along the lines of Fetter--calls the "timing
problem." (7) Thus,
Unlike all other goods, the timing of holding a unit of money does
not affect its usefulness as a means to the end to which it is put,
i.e., as a medium of exchange (2011, p. 53).
Because the moment in time that a unit of money is held does not
affect its usefulness, money serves as a common denominator in
inter-temporal, as well as present, exchanges. The exchange of
present money for future money, therefore, isolates the time
discount or pure time preference factor and permits the emergence
of a pure rate of interest (2011, p. 53).
To elaborate a bit, the above is tantamount to saying two things:
(1) that non-monetary goods always suffer from the timing problem (8)
while (2) money never suffers from the same.
Let us further look into this, especially the second aspect, which
is also the crucial one. Why is it that money does not suffer from the
timing problem? The specific argument advanced by Professor Herbener is
the inter-temporally homogeneous role of facilitating exchange. Money
has a peculiar role which is preserved through time. Two things come to
mind here: first, is the intuition that one needs money at certain
moments for certain payments completely absurd? Contemplating the
birthdays of our children or wives, we feel that money (and the
facilitation of exchanges) should best become available in the temporal
vicinity of the events. So timing might matter even for the monetary
good's evaluation. And, second, can we not apply the argument from
the "peculiar use" to all goods? For instance, we could say
that the use of water to "quench thirst" remains the same
through time. Therefore, based on this, we could analogously argue that
water does not suffer from the timing problem.
Backtracking to point (1) above--that non-monetary goods always
suffer from the timing problem--we could here too question whether this
is not asserted too strongly. It seems to us that if we push this idea
to its extreme, it blows into pieces an indispensable element of acting
man's framework--namely, what Professor Salerno has aptly called,
after Mises, the "real present" or "praxeological
time" (1993, p. 119). Man's life is not a series of actions
and choices (some inter-temporal) anymore, but some strange
kaleidoscopic behavior in which the consumption or use of every
(non-monetary) good is timed-in quasi-automatically.
There is another problem, though, with this second argument in
favor of PTPTI that renders it problematic. Even though Professor
Herbener seems to think he has avoided such a trap, the above
argument--at least a certain version of it--might imply circular
reasoning.
It is true that real prices are money prices. Market rates of
interest are money prices too, therefore. But, as we know from
Mises's important real persons versus catallactic functions
distinction, all market (money) prices are composites. Pure incomes can
be disentangled from these composite/gross sums only by a process of
thought which already presupposes a theory of such disentanglement and
of the nature of each particular share of income. Therefore, dealing
with the real world gross (money) interest rates is not the beginning,
but the end of interest theory. Let us provide some supporting Mises
quotes:
In the changing economy interest stipulated in loan contracts is
always a gross magnitude out of which the pure rate of originary
interest must be computed by a particular process of computation
and analytical repartition. It has been shown already that in every
act of lending, even apart from the problem of changes in the
monetary unit's purchasing power, there is an element of
entrepreneurial venture. The granting of credit is necessarily
always an entrepreneurial speculation which can possibly result in
failure and the loss of a part or of the total amount lent. Every
interest stipulated and paid in loans includes not only originary
interest but also entrepreneurial profit (2008, p. 533).
Originary interest can therefore in the changing economy never
appear in a pure unalloyed form (2008, p. 531).
Like entrepreneurial profit and loss, interest is not a price, but
a magnitude which is to be disengaged by a particular mode of
computation from the price of the products of successful business
operations. The gross difference between the price at which a
commodity is sold and the costs expended in its production
(exclusive of interest on the capital invested) was called profit
in the terminology of British classical economics. Modern economics
conceives this magnitude as a complex of catallactically disparate
items (2008, p. 532).
The only route left--and probably the intended one--for such an
argument (that with money time-preference can be isolated) to proceed is
to claim that the issue can be squared with in thought (or, to put it
otherwise, a priori). By joining in thought interest and money we can
somehow arrive--by means of this particular reasoning itself--to the
idea that money interest is purely time-preference determined. But the
problems of this route--a couple of them, at least--have been shown
above to be significant.
CONCLUSION
We have tried to contribute to the defense of the pure
time-preference theory of interest not by adding bullets, but by
selecting or polishing some of them. Thus, the famous Misesian reduction
to the absurd, according to which the negation of time preference is
tantamount to the disappearance of consumption or action altogether, has
been found inadequate in that it uses a general proposition to negate a
general one, when it should have used a particular. The way out has been
proposed to be the absurd concept of conscious non-action to which
negating time-preference must lead. Secondly, the idea that reasoning in
terms of money permits the isolation of pure time-preference determined
interest has also been found unsatisfactory due, especially, to the
difficulties involved in defending two implied theses: that money never
suffers from the timing problem; and that non-money goods always do. In
the hope of having done more than just adding to the noise, we conclude
with the thought that correct theories must be defended by correct
arguments.
REFERENCES
Block, Walter. 1990. "The DMVP-MVP Controversy: A Note,"
Review of Austrian Economics 4, no. 1: pp. 199-207.
Bohm-Bawerk, Eugen von. 1959. Capital and Interest (3 vols.). South
Holland, Ill.: Libertarian Press.
Cwik, Paul. 2003. A Defense of the Traditional Austrian Theory of
Interest, available at http://mises.org/journals/scholar/cwik.pdf.
De Soto, Jesus Huerta. 2009. Money, Bank Credit, and Economic
Cycles (Second English Edition). Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises
Institute.
Gunning, J. Patrick. 2005. "Interest: In Defense of
Mises," Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 8, no. 3: 81-91.
Herbener, Jeffrey M., ed., 2011. The Pure Time-Preference Theory of
Interest. Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute.
Hulsmann, Jorg Guido. 2002. "A Theory of Interest,"
Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 5, no. 4: 77-110.
Latham, Kyle. 2012. "Dr. Hulsmann and the Pure Time Preference
Theory of Interest," presented at the Austrian Student Scholars
Conference 2012 (available at http://www2.gcc.edu/dept/econ/ASSC/
Papers%202012/latham_interesttheory.pdf)
Mises, Ludwig von. 2008. Human Action. A Treatise on Economics
(Scholar's Edition). Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute.
Murphy, Robert P. 2003. Unanticipated Intertemporal Change in
Theories of Interest. Ph.D. Dissertation, New York University.
Pellengahr, Ingo. 1996. The Austrian Subjectivist Theory of
Interest. An Investigation into the History of Thought. Frankfurt am
Main: Peter Lang.
Rothbard, Murray N. 2008. The Mystery of Banking (Second Edition).
Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute.
Rothbard, Murray N. 2009. Man, Economy, and State with Power and
Market (Second Scholar's Edition). Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises
Institute.
Salerno, Joseph T. 1993. "Mises and Hayek Dehomogenized,"
Review of Austrian Economics 6, no. 2: 113-146.
(1) The locus classicus is Eugen von Bohm-Bawerk. 1959. Capital and
Interest (3 vols.). South Holland, Ill.: Libertarian Press.
(2) See, for instance: Pellengahr (1996), Hulsmann (2002), Murphy
(2003), Cwik (2003), Gunning (2005), Herbener (2011) or Latham (2012).
(3) We are aware of the opinions which consider that there are
significant differences even between Mises and Rothbard in the way they
present PTPTI (Pellenghar, 1996). We consider those differences to be
significantly less important than usually considered, but for the
purpose of analyzing the two arguments which constitute the focus of the
present paper there is no need to settle this issue.
(4) We owe this point to Flaviu Iepure.
(5) We should always be interpreted as saying ceteris paribus. We
leave it out sometimes not to make the discussion more cumbersome than
it already is.
(6) Seeing things this way has an additional appeal as it would
unite Austrians with other authors, such as Irving Fisher, making them
less "parochial/isolated" and severed from the mainstream.
(7) Time raises not only the time-preference problem, but also the
timing problem. This appears when the moment itself of
consumption/action or satisfaction is an essential part of a good. A
cake on the birthday date is different from a cake in a usual day. Or,
with the words of Herbener discussing Fetter, "different
circumstances can arise at different moments in time for using a good as
a means and therefore, the value of the end satisfied by the means can
differ at different moments in time" (Herbener, 2011, p. 47)
(8) This is necessary, otherwise inter-temporal exchanges in terms
of other goods (which might not always suffer from the timing problem)
could presumably also isolate pure (time-preference determined)
interest. And this undermines the case for the peculiar role of money in
this respect.
An analogy can be here suggested with the frequency of payment
problem discussed by Rothbard in The Mystery of Banking, pp. 60-63. If
the timing problem can be reframed in terms of the demand for money--in
the sense that money not suffering from timing implies that the demand
for money will not increase around winter holidays, let us say--it would
be odd to accept that frequency of payment affects money (the demand for
it, therefore its value or purchasing power) but timing does not. Or
that the problem of frequency of payment is wholly reducible to problems
of time-preference (and not at all to problems of timing).
The authors would like to thank the Mises Institute for the
opportunity to present a draft of this paper at the Austrian Scholars
Conference 2012. They would also like to thank the participants to the
Mises Seminar in Bucharest, in the midst of whom they had the
opportunity to time and again present and test their ideas. The
remaining errors are, of course, our own.
Mihai Vladimir Topan is president of the Ludwig von Mises Institute-Romania. He is also assistant professor at the Department of
International Business and Economics, Bucharest University of Economic
Sciences. The present paper is supported by the research project CNCSIS TE no. 38/03.08.2010.
Cristian Paun is Executive Director of Romanian Society for
Economics and associate professor of International Finance at the
Department of International Business and Economics from Bucharest
University of Economic Sciences.