Capital and Wages: A Lakatosian History of the Wages Fund Doctrine.
Ekelund, Robert B., Jr.
Episodes in the history of economic thought are sometimes subjected
to radical evaluations from those who wish to analyze past theory and
theoretical developments from historiographic and methodological
perspectives. Much of what attempts to pass as "analysis"
revolves around the "paradigmatic" approach of Thomas Kuhn and
the "methodology of scientific research programs" (MSRP) of
Imre Lakatos. Unfortunately the application of this method has yielded
little in the way of understanding the nature of particular episodes in
the analysis of the "progress" of economics. This book on the
wages fund - one of the key theoretical underpinnings of classical
economics - and the "reasons" for Mill's ostensible "recantation of it" is only one of the most recent in the
genre. This comment is not meant to imply that Vint has not taken his
subject seriously, for he has. He seeks to apply the Lakatosian
"theory" to the wages fund alone and not to the classical
"paradigm" of which the wages fund theory was an inextricable part. And in his workmanlike "review of the troops" strewn throughout the book Vint shows considerable attention to detail.
Unfortunately Vint's discussion is adrift in the sea of relativism
that is part and parcel of attempts to apply such methodologies to the
development of economic theory. Vint's so-called discoveries simply
do not stand up to better and more cogent alternative explanations.
The central problem is the following. Lakatosian concepts, which Vint
adopts, include a hard core of theory (in this case wages fund theory),
a protective belt (which, due to lack of empirical testing, are factors
which protect the hard core) and "monsters" - mainly questions
that the theory cannot answer. Unfortunately, identification of the hard
core, the protective belt or "monsters" is totally vacuous
exercise with equally vacuous results. It uses selective
"facts" from history, selective historical interpretation and
(in this case) selective "rational reconstruction" of
classical wage theory as a research program [p. 29]. The exercise, in
short, is subject to severe selection bias (other scenarios are
reasonable and observationally equivalent). More importantly, such an
exercise contains far more bias than any theoretical or empirical test
in modern economics. The method, in effect, substitutes anarchical
interpretation for motivations based on self-interested explanations
founded on factors (some of them technological) internal to the
discipline. It leads Vint [pp. 29-30] to "argue that the Classical
economists were rational, in a Lakatosian sense, to subscribe to the
wages fund doctrine and long run wage theory, despite the fact that
these theories are regarded as erroneous in terms of modern
theory." Vint also argues that "Mill's recantation was
rational and so was the decision not to abandon the Classical wage
theory research programme until a potentially more progressive theory
came along. All of this is powerful evidence for MHRP" [methodology
of historiographical research programs of Lakatos].
After much sweat and toil to make good on this promise, the method
delivers little meaning and less insight. Vint concludes that the
classicals were rational (in a Lakatosian sense to be sure) to hold to
the wages fund idea. Further, he argues that Mill was rational to give
it up to the extent that he did, but that he was also rational to
maintain it as theory (he did not abandon it in the final edition of the
Principles). Finally, we are all supposed to be rational (from a
neoclassical perspective) to consider the wages fund an "erroneous
and false theory" [p. 249]. Unfortunately, on the path to these
"conclusions," logic and common sense take a holiday.
Vint finds himself in numerous logical pickles as a consequence of
his method. He argues [p. 177] that Mill "accepted" and
expanded upon the arguments of W. T. Thornton - that alleged idiot
savant on the theory of supply and demand - in order to abandon the
wages fund.(1) He then argues that "Mill was, in fact, very
reluctant to abandon the theory completely given the absence of a
superior alternative and this is very much in line with a Lakatosian
view." Unfortunately Vint's argument (using Lakatos) is
irrefutable. What if Mill had not been "reluctant" to give the
theory up? Would that have been out of line with "the"
Lakatosian view? Conceptually it could have meant that Mill was
defending the "hard core" from attack - an easy score for a
Lakatosian view. Such birds, stuffed with legerdemain, will not fly.
Vint apparently does not understand the interface between classical
microeconomics and macroeconomics vis-a-vis the wages fund despite the
homage he pays to Frank Taussig's masterful analysis of the
question [3]. In assuming a discontinuous production function (with
fixed production coefficients) for the economy as a whole, the short-run
fixity of the aggregate average wage rate is logically assured. Contrary
to Vint's supposed "explosion" of this view, the
transference of demands between capitalist consumables (luxuries) and
goods consumed by the laboring class does not matter as to the logic of
the fixity of the fund and, indeed, of all other parts of Gross Domestic
Product. That conclusion is driven by the assumption of a
point-input/point-output production function. As a logical macroeconomic proposition, the wages fund doctrine is made of far sterner stuff than
Vint imagines. From a microeconomic perspective, Mill did not fully
flesh out the applications of supply and demand to wages, but he did
understand that unemployment would clearly result from real wage rates
being temporarily above fully-anticipated and contractual equilibrium
either for the economy or for particular markets. This conclusion has
cogency even today and, to the best of my knowledge, there is no
well-executed empirical evidence that refutes it. That
"bargaining" takes place prior to contract (the point input)
or that the real wage (either macroeconomic or in a particular market)
is elastic over period analysis is quite irrelevant to the primary issue
(fixity of the fund) and its primary policy conclusion (non-equilibrium
wages create unemployment at points in time).
In the recantation Mill was as confused between real and money
versions of the fund as he was imbued with the "socialist
mentality" of addressing society's ills. He might not have
been led to this position had he not, as Marshall noted, put the cart
(the wages fund discussion) before the horse (the theory of markets) in
the Principles. Marshall was one neoclassical who did not believe
(contrary to Vint) that the wages fund was "false" when
correctly stated as either a macroeconomic or microeconomic proposition.
In fact, Marshall hit pay dirt in his keen analysis of the wages fund
and Mill's recantation of it in Appendix J of the Principles [2,
822-29]. As he emphasized, a large part of Mill's problem in the
"recantation" was that he did not make clear whether
statements referred "to immediate or ultimate effects" [or]
"to short or long periods" [2, 825]. Marshall also
appreciated, as Vint does not, that the wages fund doctrine, when
analyzed as a part of classical economics, was only another way of
asserting Say's Law. In short, to maintain that the doctrine was
somehow "rejected" as false in Lakatosian or any other terms
is nonsense. Contrary to Vint, the macroeconomic transmission mechanisms
involving labor, capital and production are very much retained in modern
macroeconomic theory. Marginal productivity theory, as clarified in
Marshall's account, now adds the essential supports to Mill's
theory of particular markets.
A book which presents a reasonable contrast in interpretations of the
wages fund is surely needed, but this book does not fill the bill. There
are glaring omissions of important material essential to a well-rounded
picture. The so-called "gap" of the middle period of writings
on the fund that Vint thinks he's filled was substantially covered
in omitted references [e.g., 1]. Mark Blaug suggests in his introduction
to this book [p. x] that this work might improve our understanding of
the "peculiar strengths" and "peculiar weaknesses"
of the Lakatosian approach. I suggest that such attempts amplify the
reasons why such jejune frameworks applied to the history of economic
doctrines should be abandoned altogether.
Robert B. Ekelund, Jr. Auburn University
1. Here Vint chides those who would use neoclassical theory to try to
interpret the likes of Thornton on supply and demand (Thornton used
preposterous and serpentine logic in an attempt to refute the
"laws"). But how are we to interpret anything - in
historiographically relative terms? Vint himself uses a so-called modern
"theory" of doctrinal change to explain the historical apogee
of the wages fund theory. His theory is, unfortunately, of such
elasticity that conclusions drawn therefrom are meaningless.
References
1. Breit, W., "Some Neglected Early Critics of the Wages Fund
Theory," Southwestern Social Science Quarterly 48, 1967, 53-60.
2. Marshall, A. Principles of Economics. 8th edition. London:
Macmillan, 1920.
3. Taussig, F. Wages and Capital. London: Macmillan, 1896.