首页    期刊浏览 2024年12月05日 星期四
登录注册

文章基本信息

  • 标题:An experimental investigation of moral hazard in costly investments.
  • 作者:Deck, Cary A. ; Reyes, Javier
  • 期刊名称:Southern Economic Journal
  • 印刷版ISSN:0038-4038
  • 出版年度:2008
  • 期号:January
  • 语种:English
  • 出版社:Southern Economic Association
  • 关键词:Book publishing;Business losses;Economic theory;Economics;Game theory;Investment management;Investments

An experimental investigation of moral hazard in costly investments.


Deck, Cary A. ; Reyes, Javier


1. Introduction

Frequently, parties make sequential decisions regarding investments for which the probability of success or failure is dependent on the amount of total investment. Depending on the circumstances, the second investment could function as a complement, enabling an endeavor to be successful that otherwise would not be. However, the investments could function as substitutes if the first investor, anticipating the actions of the second investor, invests less. For example, a private sector firm that provides financing and construction management for highways and other infrastructure may invest less money and effort knowing that the public sector acting as a debt guarantor will provide what is needed to complete the project or cover the costs of default in case the project fails. A boss may put less effort into a report, knowing that an underling will catch any errors. When parents allow an adult son or daughter to move back into their home, this can enable the son or daughter to regroup before returning to a self-reliant life, but it can also weaken the incentive for the son or daughter to regroup. In the academic realm, coauthorship can enable researchers to realize synergies in their work, but one coauthor might exert less effort with the expectation that her coauthor will pick up the slack.

The macroeconomic literature on catalytic finance provides another example of this investment problem. Recently a number of emerging economies have experienced crises requiring significant structural domestic adjustments to reestablish steady economic growth. The rescue packages led by the IMF (1) have been heavily criticized. (2) If the IMF's stamp of approval (i.e., bailout/support) enhances investors' perception about a good outcome in a crisis country and increases the probability of the successful implementation of reforms, that is, it has a catalytic effect, then the troubled economy will quickly regain access to international capital markets and will be allowed to refinance its short-term debt. However, IMF support to crisis or crisis-prone countries introduces moral hazard. A debtor country that can avoid or alleviate a crisis by implementing costly (political or economic) reforms may decide not to do so as long as they can be substituted by readily available IMF support packages.

This paper reports a series of laboratory experiments that investigate behavior in what we term a costly investment game. This game is similar to the ultimatum game in that, in equilibrium, a first mover can take advantage of her position to earn a higher share of the profit. However, the games differ in some key respects. As with the examples given above, the payoffs remain uncertain even after both investments have been made. Further, costly investments by the first mover cannot be recouped if the second mover effectively "rejects" an offer by not providing sufficient additional investment. The next section of the paper describes the game, which closely follows the catalytic finance model of Morris and Shin (2006). Separate sections provide the design and results of the experiments. A final section contains concluding remarks.

2. Costly Investment Game

Morris and Shin (2006) develop a model in which investors make sequential investment decisions. Specifically, in Morris and Shin (2006), a debtor country is faced with a solvency problem. Knowing the economic fundamentals, the debtor can engage in costly reforms after which the IMF can decide whether or not to extend support. Based on these decisions there is some probability that the country will be solvent, which is beneficial to both parties. (3) While Morris and Shin (2006) focus exclusively on the issue of catalytic finance, as described above, this appealing model can be applied to other settings as well. For example, consider two coauthors editing a paper. While both authors benefit from the paper being published, both may prefer to let the other shoulder the burden.

Our objective is to compare the theoretical predictions of Morris and Shin (2006) for the interaction of the first and second investors, which we term the costly investment game, with what we observe in the laboratory. (4) Thus, we present a brief description of their model, extracting only the essential conditions needed for our experimental analysis, and refer the reader to the original paper for details.

Structure of the Costly Investment Game

Two investors want to see a project succeed, meaning that it surpasses some threshold that could differ by investor. In the catalytic finance story this amounts to the economy being solvent, as determined by the demands of its creditors, and fundamentally sound. For the coauthors, this means that the paper is publishable perhaps by different level journals as determined by an editor. Both investors observe the initial state of the project, denoted by [phi]. For the catalytic finance story this represents the economic fundamentals of economy and for coauthors it represents the quality of the idea or the manuscript in its current state. The first investor can exert costly effort, e, to improve the project (reforms by the debtor country or other forgone research by the coauthor) at a cost of c(e) = [e.sup.2].

Based on the first investor's decision, the initial quality of the project, [theta], is drawn from a normal distribution with mean [phi] + e and variance l/[alpha]. With a normalization, the economy is considered to be sound or the paper publishable if [theta] [greater than or equal to] = 0. After observing both [theta] and e, but not the realization of [theta], the second investor can provide additional support, m at a cost of c(m) = bm. (5) This represents the IMF providing additional support or the second author revising the paper. For the economy to be solvent or the paper publishable at a better journal, it must be that [theta] + m exceeds a level 7. This threshold is a function of the opportunity cost of a third party given by L and their private signals of the true quality [theta]. (6) In the catalytic finance story, [gamma] is the percentage of creditors who roll over their debt, which is a function of their alternative investment opportunities and private information. In the coauthor story, [gamma] is the likelihood an editor will accept a paper, which is a function of the marginal paper at the journal and the private signals given by the reviewers. These private signals are assumed to be unbiased and normally distributed with a variance of 1/[beta].

Following Morris and Shin (2006), the payoffs to the first and second investors are given by Equations 1 and 2, respectively.

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], (1)

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]. (2)

Morris and Shin (2006) show that if [alpha]/[beta] [less than or equal to] [square root of 2 [pi]] then there is a unique critical realization of [theta], denoted by [[theta].sup.*], below which the project will not be successful. When [alpha] and [beta] [right arrow] [infinity] (i.e., there is very good information), it is possible to show that the optimal amount of second-investor support is dependent on the opportunity cost, [lambda], of the third party, which ultimately defines the threshold for success. Optimal support is given by

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]. (3)

That is, the second investor does not want to contribute additional resources if the project is hopeless or is already of sufficient quality. But the second investor will contribute just enough to take the project over the threshold if it is sound.

Given the optimal response of the second investor, the effort that maximizes the first investor's payoff is

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]. (4)

This means that the first investor wants to exert just enough effort to induce the second investor to complete the task. From Equation 3 the second investor will expend enough resources to meet the opportunity cost of the third party, who ultimately determines success. As [lambda] increases so does m. Based on Equation 4 as [phi] increases, meaning the project's initial state is greater, then the effort of the first investor is reduced since not as much effort is needed to induce the second investor to contribute.

If there were no second investor the optimal investment would be

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]. (5)

That is, the first investor would exert enough resources to reach the threshold on their own if it were possible to do so. As noted by Morris and Shin (2006), Equations 4 and 5 are the basis for the moral hazard problem since it is not possible to unambiguously rank the optimal levels of effort under these two different scenarios. If the fundamentals are such that -1 [less than or equal to] [phi] < - (1 [lambda]), then the second investor serves as a strategic complement enabling the project to be completed successfully. But when - (1 - [lambda] [less than or equal to] [phi] < [lambda], the second investor is a substitute for the first. In the first scenario the first investor cannot be successful alone, but in the second scenario she could be.

More generally, when there is not perfect information, the situation changes in two important ways. First, the probability of success differs for the first and second investors. Second, both parties will optimally expend more effort than under certainty, the magnitude of which depends on [alpha] and [beta]. Unfortunately, there is no closed form solution. Therefore, at this point we introduce the parameter values we consider in the experiments described below: [alpha] = 10, [beta] = 100. First we note that our values of [alpha] and [beta], while somewhat arbitrary, satisfy the sufficient condition for uniqueness of [[theta].sup.*]. The optimal amount (7) for the first investor is given in Equation 6,

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], (6)

and the optimal amount for the second investor is given by Equation 7,

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]. (7)

Therefore, one would expect to see the first overrespond to the underlying fundamentals of the project, leaving the second investor to worry about reaching the third party's threshold.

The experiment that follows evaluates how observed investments change as [phi] and [lambda] vary. Specifically we use values of [phi] [member of] {-0.05, -0.55} and [lambda] [member of] {0.6, 0.7}. Table 1 presents the theoretical predictions for each case. We introduce the notation C and S for strategic complements and substitutes, respectively, and use a subscript or a superscript [lambda] to denote its relative value. Appendix A contains the probability table for each investor associated with each condition.

Comparison of Investment and Ultimatum Games

The crux of the model is that the first investor will do just enough so that the second investor will opt to see the project to fruition. The equilibrium concept assumes that the investors are not concerned about how the gains from success are shared between the parties or that the investments are done in the most efficient way. However, previous experimental evidence has shown that decision makers do worry about things other than their own monetary payoff. One of the most studied games in the experimental literature is the ultimatum game. (8) Cox and Deck (2005) conduct experiments with a mini-ultimatum game in which the first mover can propose to keep $8, leaving $2 for the second mover, or the first mover can propose to split the money equally so that each would receive $5. The second mover could then decide to accept the proposal or reject it, in which case both people received $0. Standard self-interested theory as assumed by the model of Morris and Shin (2006) would suggest that the first mover keep $8, and that the second mover would accept it. Yet, Cox and Deck (2005) found that approximately 20% of unequal offers were rejected by second movers and 36% of first movers proposed the equal split.

The robustness of previous experimental results would seem to call into question the applicability of the equilibrium predictions of Morris and Shin (2006), but this game differs from a standard ultimatum game in several key ways. (9) In the costly investment game, there is a gain only when the two parties invest sufficiently. This is like framing the ultimatum game as a situation in which each party is given $10 if together they invest a total of $10. As an example, the first mover agrees to pay $2 and the second mover agrees to invest $8, then the payoffs to the first and second movers, respectively, would be $8 and $2. In the costly investment game, the first investor incurs the investment cost regardless of the decision of the second investor. In the example above, this would be equivalent to the first mover having to pay $2 regardless of whether or not the second mover subsequently invests $8. Another difference in the ultimatum and costly investment game is that while both parties receive the same nominal benefit from success, the distribution of income is determined by the relative costs of the investments, which differ by role. Counting the example, this would be a $X investment costing the first investor $[X.sup.2]/10 and a $Y investment costing the second mover $ Y/2.

The introduction of uncertainty also represents a divergence from the standard ultimatum game. In the costly investment game, the more that is invested, the (perhaps weakly) greater is the likelihood of the good outcome occurring. Finishing the example, this would be similar to each party receiving $10 with probability (X + Y)/20. Previous experimental evidence on risk attitudes suggests that behavior might not match the risk-neutral predictions of the model. While there is disagreement as to the level of risk aversion that people exhibit, studies typically find that most people are risk averse. (10) In general, the effect of risk attitude is unclear in this model. Increased risk aversion may make an investor less likely to invest, thus avoiding the risk altogether, or it might cause overinvesting so as to increase the likelihood of success. However, given the parameter values discussed in the preceding subsection and the discrete nature of the experiment discussed in the next section, moderate levels of risk aversion or risk-seeking behavior would not impact the optimal level of investments.

3. Experimental Design

To examine how the investments depend on the underlying parameters of the model, we conducted a series of laboratory experiments in a within-subjects 2 x 2 x 2 design. As described in the previous section, the first dimension is the level of the underlying fundamentals of the project, [phi], and the second dimension is the threshold, [lambda]. The third dimension is the existence of the second investor.

First we summarize the parameter choices discussed previously: [alpha] = 10, [beta] = 100, [phi] [member of] {-0.05, -0.55}, [lambda] [member of] {0.6, 0.7}, and, as suggested in Morris and Shin (2006), c(e) = [e.sup.2]. The other parameter of the model is the per-unit cost to the second investor, b, which we set equal to 0.5.

In the experiments, a success corresponded to receiving $10, and the bad outcome was receiving $0. This is a simple scaling of the payoffs and costs in Equations 1 and 2 by a factor of 10, and it also keeps the gains similar to those in the standard ultimatum game. Information on the probability of the good outcome was presented to both subjects through a pair of tables. (11) The column headings were the first investor's cost, row headings were the cost to the second investor, and each cell showed the probability of success. In the experiment, the first investor selected an investment level by clicking on the appropriate column in the upper table. This action highlighted the selected column in both tables and asked the subject to confirm the selection. Once the first investor confirmed the choice, it was revealed to the second investor, who could then select a level of support by clicking on a row in the lower table. Again, the selection was highlighted in both tables and the subject was asked to confirm the choice. At this point the first investor was informed of the second investor's decision, and the probabilities of success for each party were common information. In situations where there was no second investor, the investor observed only one table, which contained a single row. Still the column headings were the investment cost, the table entries were the probabilities associated with the good outcome, and subjects had to confirm their selection after making a decision.

The ultimate success of the project was determined by rolling two 10-sided dice. Each die had the integers from 0 to 9. The first die rolled determined the first digit and the second die determined the second digit. If the number rolled was less than the selected entry in the appropriate table, then the good outcome (payoff equals $10 minus cost) was realized, otherwise the bad outcome (payoff equals $0 minus cost) was realized. Rolling dice served two purposes. First, it is an easily understandable way to generate a random number, helping to ensure subject comprehension. Second, it provided credibility to the subjects, since the dice were rolled on a document camera in their presence with the live image projected on a large screen at the front of the lab. (12) To ensure that subjects could pay the cost associated with their actions even if the bad outcome was realized, each subject was endowed with $10. (13)

Six subjects participated in each session. After entering the lab, all subjects read a set of written directions explaining the decision task faced by both investors as well as the decision task faced by a single investor. (14) Each session included 20 investment games, some involving two investors and some involving a single investor. All six subjects made decisions in the solo investment games, but the same three randomly chosen subjects were second movers in every game with two investors. To control for reputation and repeated play effects, counterparts were randomly assigned before each game with two investors. To control for possible wealth effects over the course of the experiment, at the end of each session a volunteer was solicited from among the subjects. (15) This volunteer rolled a 20-sided die to determine which period's decision would actually count for the payoff. Subjects were informed of this procedure before the experiment began. At the conclusion of the experiment, subjects were paid privately by the experimenters and dismissed.

Subjects in each of the eight sessions played the same 20 costly investment games, but the order was different in an attempt to control sequencing effects. Table 2 gives the game order for each session. The first four games in each session involved single-player games against nature, thus giving the subjects experience with the interface and providing us with information regarding their degree of risk aversion. Games five through eight involved simple two-investor games and were designed to give the subjects experience in their respective roles as the first decision maker or the second decision maker prior to making decisions in the games of interest. (16) The last 12 games involved the games of interest, along with two other games based on different parameter values of [alpha], [beta], [phi], and [lambda], which were included so that that the exact treatment effects would not be transparent to subjects. The subjects played these six games twice; once as a game with two investors and once as a game with a single investor. (17) Since a subject was not allowed to participate in multiple sessions, a total of 48 subjects completed the one hour experiment. The subjects were recruited from undergraduate business classes at the University of Arkansas. For many this was their first experiment, but some had previously participated in other unrelated experiments. In addition to salient payment, which averaged $12.54, subjects received a $5 show-up fee. Subjects received this $5 before beginning the experiment so that it was transparent to the subjects that the $10 endowment in the experiment did not include the show-up fee.

[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]

4. Behavioral Results

The results are presented as a series of findings. The first finding investigates the impact of the existence of a second investor on the decision of the initial investor.

FINDING 1. The change in initial investments due to the presence of a second investor is consistent with the predictions of Morris and Shin (2006).

EVIDENCE: Figure 1 plots the within-subject difference in investment when there is and when there is not a second investor. (18) In games [S.sup.[lambda]] and [S.sub.[lambda]], the first investor is predicted to invest less when there is the possibility of a subsequent investment by someone else, and that is what we clearly observe. For games [C.sup.[lambda]] and [C.sub.[lambda]], the second investor is predicted to serve as a strategic complement to the first investor, and again we observe the predicted outcome. For quantitative support we rely on a nonparametric sign test, with the unit of observation being the eight-session level average within-subject differences. This controls for the fact that the decisions from subjects in the same session are not independent. The null hypothesis of no second-investor effect can be rejected in favor of the one-sided alternative suggested by the theory at the 95% confidence level for [S.sup.[lambda]] (p = 0.0352), for [S.sub.[lambda]] (p = 0.0039), and for [C.sub.[lambda]] (p = 0.0039). (19)

[FIGURE 2 OMITTED]

The games in which investments are strategic substitutes are such that a sole investor's optimal choice is on the interior of the action space. However, this is not the case for complements. In part this is a feature of the base model. For the investments to be complementary, it has to be the case that an investor cannot be successful on her own and thus the investor prefers to not invest if there is no possibility of subsequent support. It is fair to ask whether this behavior is an artifact of the extreme nature of being complements. Without going into the details of the games, based on behavior observed in games five through eight with other probabilities tables, the answer appears to be no.

Having established that the general behavioral patterns conform to the model, the analysis now turns to the model's specific predictions. In all games in which there was a second investor, 12.5% of the pairs reached the equilibrium predictions. Forty-seven percent of behavior in the single-investor games was consistent with the equilibrium prediction. It is worth noting that there were 112 possible outcomes in the two-investor games as compared with only 11 possible outcomes in the single-investor game.

Figures 2 through 5 plot the frequency of the outcomes by subject pairs in the games of interest. The gray shaded areas indicate regions where theoretically the first investor invested an insufficient amount to make it worthwhile for the second investor to invest anything. Black shaded areas indicate that the first investor has invested sufficiently so that there is no reason for the second investor to contribute anything. The outlined cells indicate the best response (optimal reaction) curve of the second investor to an initial investment in the intermediate range. The bolded outline indicates the subgame perfect Nash equilibrium of the game. Recall from Equation 7 that the optimal response for the second investor is [lambda] - ([phi] + e - 0.15) in the case that e [greater than or equal to] -[phi] + 0.15. That is, additional investment by the first player is exactly offset by a reduction in the investment of the second player. But, when 0 < [phi] + e < 0.15, the optimal level for the second investor is to just reach the threshold value, [lambda].

[FIGURE 3 OMITTED]

The most striking feature of these figures is the degree to which the second-investor behavior conforms to the theoretical predictions of Morris and Shin (2006). In every single case where the first investor's decision is predicted to induce zero investment by the second player (the gray and black shaded areas), that is exactly what we observe. Further, in only three instances where the second investor is predicted to invest did we observe investment levels differing from the predicted levels by more than one unit. Finding 2 evaluates the consistency of the second investor's behavior with the theoretical prediction.

FINDING 2. Statistically, second-investor choices increase one for one with increases in threshold level for success. Further, the second investor provides the optimal amount of additional support, exactly absorbing excess initial investment.

EVIDENCE: Support for this finding is based on estimating the mixed-effects model [m.sub.ijg] = [[beta].sub.0] + [[beta].sub.1] x [Lambda.sub.g] + [[beta].sub.2] X [Net.sub.g] + [[beta].sub.3] X [NetP.sub.g] + [[epsilon].sub.i] + [[zeta].sub.ij] + [u.sub.ijg], where [[epsilon].sub.i] ~ N(0, [sigma]21), [zeta] [i.sub.ij] ~N(0, [sigma]22), [u.sub.ijg] ~ N(0, [sigma]23). This repeated measures model estimates a fixed effect for each treatment game g while allowing each session i and each subject j within a session to have a random effect. Lambda is a dummy variable that takes the value of 1 if [lambda] = 0.7 and 0 if [lambda] = 0.6 for the observation. Net is the value of [phi] + e - 0.15, to which the second investor is responding. NetP is a dummy variable that takes on the value of 1 if [phi] + e < 0.15 and 0 otherwise; that is, it indicates that the initial investment was below the optimal level. The estimation is restricted to the subset of data in which the optimal response of the second investor is to provide positive support for the project. Note that second investors always provided zero support when it was optimal to do so, as shown in Figures 2-5. Table 3 provides the estimation results, which, for brevity, do not include the random effects. The coefficient on the dummy variable Lambda is 0.07715, which is not significantly different than 0.1 (p = 0.4235 in the two-tailed test). Thus, [lambda] increasing by 0.1 leads to a 0.1 increase in support as predicted. That is, the second investor increases her investment to match increases in the success threshold. The baseline case, where the threshold, [lambda], is equal to 0.6 and the initial investment is set to e = -[phi] + 0.15 so that NetP = 0 and therefore the optimal second investment is m = 0.6, yields the hypothesis [[beta].sub.0] = 0.6, which cannot be rejected at standard levels of significance (p = 0.3622 in two-tailed test). When the first investor overinvests, e > -[phi] + 0.15, the second investor responds by decreasing her own investment, m, one for one as predicted.

[FIGURE 4 OMITTED]

This is evidenced by the fact that [[beta].sub.2] = - 1 (p = 0.4097 in the two-tailed test). In the case that initial investment is too low, the second investment should equal [lambda]. Given the discrete nature of the game, the only possible effort in this category is e = -[phi] + 0.05, which is 0.1 below the optimal. The estimated change in the second investment in this position is [[beta].sub.2] x (-0.1) + [[beta].sub.3]. Assuming that [[beta].sub.2] = - 1, [[beta].sub.3] should equal -0.1. This null hypothesis cannot be rejected (p = 0.8630 in the two-tailed test).

The observed behavior of the second investor differs from what is typically found in ultimatum games. (20) In the strategic substitutes games shown in Figures 4 and 5, investments of $1.60 or less by the first investor force the second investor to invest at least $2.00 for the good payoff to be achieved. This is analogous to the decision of a first mover in a mini-ultimatum game to opt for the $8-$2 split instead of the $5-$5 split. Cox and Deck (2005) find that 20% of such "greedy" proposals are rejected, but we find that 0 of 15 greedy choices are rejected in one case and only 1 of 8 greedy choices is rejected in the other. One explanation given for the typical ultimatum game behavior is a desire for equality motivated by "fairness" and, therefore, it is worth noting what a comparable behavior would be in the costly investment game. Consider the situation in which costs are borne (nearly) equally by both investors. Graphically, such outcomes form a downward sloping path, from the top left to the bottom right, in Figures 2 through 5. Casual inspection of these figures suggests that this is not how second movers are responding. An alternative consideration could be efficiency, which would mean maximizing the total expected payout of the investors. Second movers motivated by efficiency would respond in the same way as the theoretical predictions presented above for initial investments at or above the optimal level. However, second investors motivated in this way would increase their investments even as the first mover underinvested. Graphically this would be a downward continuation of the diagonal path, from top left to bottom right, in Figures 2-5, which is not consistent with the pattern we observe.

Even though the second investor responds optimally, the first investors do not seem to anticipate this behavior. Based on the theoretical model, the first investor should choose to invest e = -[phi] + 0.15. However, from the 11 instances in Figures 2 and 3 where no investment is undertaken when investments are complements, it is apparent that many first players do not trust that the second player will provide sufficient help to warrant investing. But, from Figures 4 and 5, it is apparent that first investors tend to overinvest in the case of strategic substitutes. Finding 3 compares first-investor behavior with the theoretical predictions.

[FIGURE 5 OMITTED]

FINDING 3. As the underlying fundamentals, [phi], increase, the first investors respond by investing less. This shift is in the direction predicted, but the magnitude is smaller than expected. In contrast with the theoretical predictions, the success threshold, [lambda], does affect the behavior of the first investors.

SUPPORT: The quantitative evidence is based on the estimation of a mixed-effects model, [e.sub.ijg] = [[gamma].sub.0] + [[gamma].sub.1] X [Phi.sub.g] + [[gamma].sub.2] x [Lambda.sub.g] + [[gamma].sub.3] X [(Phi X Lambda).sub.g] + [[epsilon].sub.i] + [[zeta].sub.ij] [u.sub.ijg], where Phi is a dummy variable that takes the value of 1 if [phi] = -0.05 and 0 if [phi] = -0.55 for the observation, Phi X Lambda is an interaction between Lambda and Phi, and the other terms are as before. Table 4 provides the estimation results. As predicted, an increase in fundamentals, [phi], leads to lower initial investments, but not at the one-for-one rate predicted as [[gamma].sub.1] [not equal] 0.5 (p < 0.001 in the two-tailed test). It is important to keep in mind that this model examines the average effect. For many of the subjects, those that did not invest at all in the case of strategic complements where [phi] is low, investments actually increased with [phi]. This counteracts the investment reduction for subjects who behaved according to the theory and trusted the second investor to contribute in the substitutes games. Given the large number of subjects who did not invest in the complements scenario, it is not surprising that the average investment in the baseline case, [phi] = -0.55 and [lambda] = 0.6, is below the theoretical prediction. Note that in the baseline case, investment should be -[phi] + 0.15 = 0.7. Thus the null hypothesis is that [[gamma].sub.0] = 0.7, which can be rejected at standard significance levels (p < 0.001 in the two-tailed test). The fact that the first investors respond to [gamma] is evidenced by the fact that [[gamma].sub.2] [not equal to] 0 (p = 0.0482 in a two-tailed test). In fact, it appears that increasing [lambda] by 0.1 leads to a 0.1 increase in initial investments. This is also consistent with the first investor not being willing to rely on the second investor. The lack of an interaction effect, [[gamma].sub.3] = 0 (p = 0.1845 in a two-tailed test), is consistent with the theory.

First-investor overinvestment in the case of strategic substitutes is not too surprising given previous ultimatum game results. Thirty-seven percent of first movers invested more than $1.60 in [S.sub.[lambda]]. This is similar to the 36% of first movers making an equal split proposal in the mini-ultimatum game of Cox and Deck (2005). As the threshold [lambda] increases between [S.sub.[lambda]] and [S.sup.[lambda]], meaning that the second investor should invest more conditional on e, fewer of the first investors exploit their first mover advantage, meaning they bear part of the additional burden. What is surprising is how many (38%) of the first movers actually opted to undertake the majority of the investment themselves. It is tempting to speculate that this pattern suggests that first movers are likely to take responsibility for their own situation, but given the neutral framing of the decision task it seems more reasonable that this is further evidence of a lack of trust in second-mover responses. (21)

Throughout this paper, theoretical predictions are based on an assumption of risk neutrality. It is reasonable to ask how sensitive these predictions are to issues of risk aversion. Given the parameters selected and the discrete nature of the experiment, people with risk attitudes similar to what has been reported previously (see Holt and Laury 2002; Deck, Lee, and Reyes, in press; and references therein) would make similar choices. (22) However, we do note that we find substantial risk-loving behavior. (23) In the fourth game of the experiment, subjects had to choose between paying $5 of their $10 endowment for a 49% chance of winning $10 and simply keeping the $10 endowment. Twenty-seven of the 48 subjects (56%) opted for the risky option, indicating at least a modest degree of risk-loving behavior. This could be further evidence that the mechanism for measuring risk attitudes can affect the observed level of risk aversion (see Isaac and James 2000; Berg, Dickhaut, and McCabe 2005). In our experiments, we did not observe any extreme risk aversion. No subject was consistent with a constant relative risk aversion parameter greater (more risk averse) than 0.38, and only one subject was consistent with a risk parameter greater than 0.28.

5. Conclusions

In many situations, the investments of multiple parties impact the probability of a successful outcome. This enables success in cases in which a single investor could not be successful alone but can also lead to moral hazard problems if the first mover can rely on a subsequent investor to bail her out. A key challenge for second movers in setting policies, either the IMF providing support to a debtor country or a coauthor deciding to exert effort in a research project, is trying to determine into which category a problem falls. The model of Morris and Shin (2006) provides a straightforward theoretical framework for this problem. Our paper reports a series of experiments largely confirming their theoretical predictions. The existence of a second investor influences the first investor in the direction predicted. In general we find that second investors are best responding to the first investors, but first investors deviate from the theoretical predictions in intuitive ways.

The case of strategic substitutes is similar to the standard ultimatum game. In the ultimatum game a first mover proposes an allocation of a fixed amount of money, which a second mover can accept or reject. Typically, only a small percentage of first movers propose an allocation that is overwhelmingly in their own favor in an attempt to keep (nearly) everything. This is similar to what we observed in the costly investment game. In the ultimatum game it is not uncommon to see such unequal offers rejected by second movers in favor of both parties receiving nothing. But we see very few "rejections" by second investors. To be fair, there are some key differences between the two games, any of which could explain the difference. For example, perhaps the fact that investors have to forgo investment costs irrespective of the ultimate success of the project causes first investors to invest less given the uncertainty of how second investors will react and second investors understand this and therefore are more willing to accept low initial investments. Regardless of the cause of this difference, our work joins Salmon and Wilson (2006) in calling into question the degree to which ultimatum game behavior is robust to different institutional settings. (24)

The ability of the model to categorize behavior suggests some policy implications. For example, as it is currently implemented, the support of the IMF can serve as an alternative to costly reforms/efforts that the debtor should undertake. The behavioral observations suggest that the burden could be shifted to the first investor by laying out the specific conditions under which the second investor would provide support. But for such a policy to work it would have to be the case that the IMF could credibly commit to it and therefore allow a country to default. Of course, in the case of coauthors it is not necessarily clear who "should be" responsible for the investments. Returning to the parent and adult child example of the introduction, this policy would require the parent to lay out specific conditions under which support would be provided. Short of enacting such policies, second investors will continue to be taken advantage of when their support is not catalytic.

As with any empirical study, one must be careful in extrapolating to the more general problem of interest. For example, one criticism often raised in laboratory experiments is that the subjects in the lab are not as "sophisticated" as the population of interest. However, it is difficult to imagine any group's behavior in the second-investor role (including the IMF or PhD researchers) being more consistent with the theoretical predications. But more sophisticated first investors who believed that the second investor would provide support might have been more willing to push responsibility onto the second investors. The implications of this would presumably be even greater coordination when the two parties are in complementary roles since more initial investors would be willing to take the risk and even less initial investment when the second investor provides a strategic substitute.

Appendix A: Probability Tables by Treatment

The following are screenshots. In each pair, the top table is for the first investor and the lower table is for the second investor.

[ILLUSTRATIONS OMITTED]

Appendix B: Experiment Directions

You are participating in a research experiment through Interactive Decision Experiments at Arkansas (IDEA). At the end of the experiment you will be paid your earnings in cash. Therefore, it is important that you understand the directions completely before beginning the experiment. If at any point you have a question, please raise your hand and a lab monitor will approach you. Otherwise, you should not communicate with others (please turn off all cel phones pagers, etc.).

In today's experiment you will start with an initial $10 (in addition to your $5 show-up fee) and you will have to make a series of decisions. You will have to make one decision each round. You do not know how many decision rounds there will be, but at the end of the experiment one decision round will be randomly selected and your earnings in that round will be added to your initial $10. What happens in one round does not have any impact on what happens in another round. In some rounds you will make the only decision that affects your payoff and your decision will not affect anyone else's payoff. In some rounds you will be randomly assigned a counterpart from the other participants in the experiment. In this case your payoff and your counterpart's payoff will depend on the decision made by you and the decision made by your counterpart.

So what kind of decision are you going to have to make? Each period there is a chance that you will earn an additional $10. The probability of earning the $10 depends on your action (and your counterpart's action, if applicable). However, each action has a cost associated with it. This cost must be paid regardless of whether or not you earn the additional $10.

Let's look at an example. Here are the screens for two randomly assigned counterparts. The dollar amounts on the top row are the costs associated with each of the first decision maker's choices. The costs in the first column are the costs associated with each of the second decision maker's choices. The entries in the table are probabilities of earning the additional $10. Notice that the top table on both screens gives the probability of the first decision maker earning the $10 and the bottom table gives the probability of the second decision maker earning the $10. Also notice that the probabilities can differ between the two tables.

[ILLUSTRATIONS OMITTED]

In this case the person on the left will make a decision first. This person has three choices (columns in the table): the first costing $3, the second costing $6, and the third costing $9. To make a choice this person simply clicks the mouse on a column in the top table.

Once the first decision maker selects a column, that column is highlighted in blue and a button appears that says "Send Decision." A decision is not final until this button is pressed. So at this point the decision maker can change the selected action by clicking on another column. Once this button is pressed the decision cannot be changed.

[ILLUSTRATION OMITTED]

After the first decision maker presses "Send Decision," the second decision maker can make one of two choices (one costing $2 and the other costing $7) by clicking on a row in the lower table. Notice that the first decision maker's choice is highlighted in yellow on the second decision maker's screen. Again, a decision is not final until the "Send Decision" button is pressed. So at this point the decision maker can change the selected action by clicking on another row. Once this button is pressed the decision cannot be changed.

[ILLUSTRATION OMITTED]

Now that both people have made a choice, the probability that each participant gains $10 can be determined. It is the probability in the table for the selected column and row. In this example, the first decision maker selected the $6 column and the second decision maker selected the $7 row. Therefore, the probability that the first decision maker gains $10 is 0.5 and the probability that the second decision maker gains $10 is 0.4.

So do they get the additional $10 or not? To determine this, two 10-sided dice will be rolled. You are free to inspect each die and will be able to watch the dice being rolled. The roll of the dice could be anything from 0.00, 0.01, 0.02, to 0.98, 0.99, with every number equally likely. Thus, there are 100 equally likely outcomes. The first die rolled will give the first digit and the second die will give the second digit. If the probability from your table is greater than the number rolled, you will earn the additional $10. Otherwise, you will not earn the additional $10.

In our example, decision maker 1 will earn the additional $10 if the number rolled is 0.00, 0.01, 0.02, ..... 0.48, 0.49. Notice that out of the total 100 outcomes there are 50 outcomes for which decision maker 1 will earn the $10. Decision maker 2 will earn the additional $10 if the number rolled is 0.00, 0.01, 0.01,....,0.38 0.39. Out of the total 100 outcomes there are 40 outcomes for which decision maker 2 will earn the $10.

In our example, decision maker 1 expects to receive $5. If we were to roll the dice many, many times, sometimes decision maker 1 would earn $10 and sometimes decision maker 1 would earn $0, but if we took the average earnings across all of the rolls it would be $5. This can be calculated as the probability, which is 0.5 x $10 = $5. Similarly, decision maker 2 expects to receive 0.4 x 10 = $4.

Suppose the first die rolled landed on 4 while the second die landed on 5. The rolled number would be 0.45. This is less than 0.5, so the first decision maker would earn the additional $10. However, the rolled number is greater than 0.4, so the second decision maker would not earn the additional $10. In this case the screens of the two decision makers would look like the following.

[ILLUSTRATIONS OMITTED]

Notice that the period earnings are recorded at the bottom of the screen and that each person has to pay the cost associated with their action, regardless of the outcome. The period earnings do not include the initial $10. If this round is randomly selected at the end of the experiment, the first decision maker would be paid the initial $10 plus an additional $10 minus the cost of $6 ($10 + $10 - $6) = $14 in addition to the $5 show-up fee. The second decision maker would be paid the initial $10 minus the cost of $7 ($10 - $7) = $3 in addition to the $5 show-up fee.

It is not always the case that one decision maker earns the additional $10 and the other does not. It is possible for both decision makers to earn an additional $10 each. It is also possible for neither decision maker to earn the additional $10. Had the number rolled been less than 0.4 in the example, then each decision maker would have earned the additional $10. Had the number rolled been greater than (or equal to) 0.5 in the example, neither decision maker would have earned the additional $10.

Remember that only one round will be randomly selected at the end of the experiment to calculate your actual cash payoff.

The previous example involved two randomly assigned counterparts. In some rounds you will not have a randomly selected counterpart. In this case the probability that you earn the additional $10 will only depend on your own action and your action will not impact anyone else's probability of earning the additional $10. The following example shows such a case.

[ILLUSTRATION OMITTED]

Notice that there is only one table and that it has only one row that does not have a cost associated with it. In this example, the decision maker has six choices (columns). The selected column is again highlighted in blue. Recall that a decision is not final until the "Send Decision" button is pressed. So at this point the decision maker can change the selected action by clicking on another column. Once this button is pressed the decision cannot be changed.

Suppose that this decision maker presses "Send Decision" and then a 0.40 is rolled on the two dice. Since 0.40 is not less than 0.40, this decision maker does not earn the additional $10. The period earnings are thus $0 minus the $5 cost = -$5, the amount that shows up at the bottom of the screen for the second period.

If the second period was randomly selected at the end of the experiment, this person would be paid the initial $10 plus the period earnings of -$5 = $5 in addition to the $5 show-up fee.

If you have any questions, please raise your hand and a lab monitor will approach you. Otherwise, please wait quietly for further directions from the experimenter. The experiment will not begin until everyone participating in the experiment has completed the directions, so please wait patiently.

Decision Maker's Screen

[ILLUSTRATION OMITTED]

Received July 2006; accepted January 2007.

References

Berg, Joyce, John Dickhaut, and Kevin McCabe. 2005. Risk preference instability across institutions: A dilemma. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 102:4209-14.

Berg, Joyce, John Dickhaut, and Thomas A. Rietz. 2005. Preference reversals: The impact of truth-revealing incentives. SSRN Working Paper. Accessed July 2005. Available http://ssrn.com/abstract=887775

Bird, Graham, Antonella Mori, and Dane Rowlands. 2000. Do the multilaterals catalyze other capital flows? What does the case study evidence tell us? Third Worm Quarterly 21:483-503.

Bulir, Ales, Atish R. Ghosh, Javier Hamman, Timothy Lane, Alexandros T. Mourmouras, and Marianne Schulze-Ghattas. 2002. IMF-supported programs in capital account crises: Design and experience. IMF Occasional Paper No. 210.

Camerer, Colin, and Richard Thaler. 1995. Ultimatums, dictators and manners. Journal of Economic Perspectives 9:209-19.

Carlsson, Hans, and Eric van Damme. 1993. Global games and equilibrium selection. Econometrica 61:989-1018.

Cox, James, and Cary Deck. 2005. On the nature of reciprocal motives. Economic Inquiry 43:623-35.

Deck, Cary, Jungmin Lee, and Javier Reyes. In press. Risk attitudes in large stake gambles: Evidence from a game show. Applied Economics.

Frankel, David M., Stephen Morris, and Ady Pauzner. 2003. Equilibrium selection in global games with strategic complementarities. Journal of Economic Theory 1:1-44.

Haldane, Andy. 1999. Private sector involvement in financial crises: Analytics and public policy approaches. Financial Stability Review. November 184-202.

Heinemann, Frank, Rosemarie Nagel, and Peter Ockenfels. 2004. The theory of global games on test: Experimental analysis of coordination games with public and private information. Econometrica 72:1583-99.

Holt, Charles, and Susan Laury. 2002. Risk aversion and incentive effects. American Economic Review 92:1644-55.

Isaac R. Mark, and Duncan James. 2000. Just who are you calling risk averse? Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 20:177-87.

Kagel, John, and Alvin Roth. 1995. The handbook of experimental economics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Morris, Stephen E., and Hyun Song Shin. 2003. Global games: Theory and applications. In Advances in Economics and Econometrics. Proceedings of the Eighth World Congress of the Econometric Society, edited by M. Dewatripont, U Hansen, and S. Turnovsky. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, pp. 56-114.

Morris, Stephen E., and Hyun Song Shin. 2006. Catalytic finance: When does it work? Journal of International Economics 70:161-77.

Rodrik, Dani. 1995. Why is there multilateral lending? NBER Working Paper No. W5160.

Salmon, Timothy C., and Bart J. Wilson. 2006. Second chance offers vs. sequential auctions: Theory and behavior. Economic Theory. In press.

(1) Including those for Argentina, Brazil, Ecuador, Indonesia, Korea, Mexico, Russia, and Thailand, among others.

(2) See Rodrik (1995); Haldane (1999); Bird, Mori, and Rowlands (2000); and Bulir et al. (2002).

(3) They use the framework of global games to solve the endogeneity problem present between the decisions of debtor countries, the IMF, and private creditors. Based on experimental evidence, Heinemann, Nagel, and Ockenfels (2004) conclude that "the global game solution is an important reference point and provides correct predictions for comparative statics" (p. 1584). Therefore, our costly investment game assumes the resulting equilibrium behavior of the creditors to derive the probability of success. The interested reader is directed to Carlsson and van Damme (1993); Frankel, Morris, and Pauzner (2003); and Morris and Shin (2003) for a more general discussion of global games.

(4) While Morris and Shin (2006) include the role of a third party, the creditors, our focus is on the moral hazard present between the first and second investors.

(5) The cost structure was designed for the catalytic finance story where reforms might be increasingly difficult politically for the home government. The same could be true of two coauthors if, for example, one was about to go up for tenure whereas the other held a chaired position.

(6) The third party is assumed to receive a payoff of 1 > [lambda] if the project is successful and 0 if it is not, but success ultimately depends on a cumulative decision of independent third parties (creditors in catalytic finance and referees in coauthorship).

(7) The optimal investments in Equations 6 and 7 also incorporate the discrete nature of the decision task faced by the subjects as described later in the paper.

(8) See Camerer and Thaler (1995) and Kagel and Roth (1995) for a review of the literature on ultimatum games.

(9) A priori we did not expect these differences to matter, but, as will be shown in the results, behavior does differ between the costly investment game and the ultimatum game.

l0 See, for example, Isaac and James (2000); Holt and Laury (2002); and Deck, Lee, and Reyes (in press). However, this is not always true; see, for example, Berg, Dickhaut, and Rietz (2005).

(11) As discussed in the Structure of the Costly Investment Game section, given that [alpha] < [infinity], the probability of success differed by role. Subjects had complete information regarding the probability tables for both roles while making decisions. Appendix A contains the probability tables for the four treatments of interest.

(12) Subjects were given the opportunity to inspect the dice before the experiment began to ensure credibility.

(13) Since it is not possible to force subjects to pay losses out of their own pockets, the experimenter loses control of the subject's motivation if earnings are negative.

(14) The experiments used neutral language so as not to bias subjects. A copy of the directions is included in Appendix B.

(15) Wealth effects refer to the possibility that behavior could be dependent on current wealth. A person who has just earned $10 may be willing to take a risk that she would not be willing to take if she had lost $10.

(16) The probability tables for investment games not shown in Appendix A are available from the authors on request. Two of these games were examples of strategic complements and strategic substitutes; to satisfy intellectual curiosity, the other two were sequential public goods games with marginal per capita (probability) returns of 0.06 and 0.08. In these games a dollar spent increased the probability of earning $10 by either 0.06 or 0.08, up to a maximum of one. Consistent with previous results, the higher per capita return increased investment by the first movers, but interestingly we only observed two instances of complete free riding by second movers.

(17) For the single-investor version of [C.sup.[lambda]], the probability table would contain only zeros. In its place we substituted the single-investor version of the complements/substitutes game from periods 5-8. In a pilot study several subjects expressed frustration with the all-zeros game. It is worth noting that all of the subjects in the pilot chose to make zero investment in that game as predicted.

(18) The sole investment decisions made in the games of interest by subjects who were in the role of the second investor in the two-investor games are omitted from this discussion.

(19) As noted in footnote 17, there was no one-player version of [C.sup.[lambda]] in the actual experiments since subjects in a pilot experiment overwhelmingly expressed frustration at making a decision when every probability entry was zero. Assuming that these subjects would have behaved identically to those in the pilot and exerted zero effort in the one-player version of [C.sup.[lambda]], the sign test would result in p = 0.0039.

(20) Ultimatum game experiments are typically one shot, meaning that the subjects do not have the opportunity to learn over the course of the experiment. We do not see any improvements in second-investor behavior in the sense of converging to the theoretical predictions over the course of the games of interest. However, learning may be a factor due to experience in the first eight games.

(21) In another series of experiments reported in Cox and Deck (2005), approximately half of the subjects are found to exhibit trust.

(22) Holt and Laury (2002) estimate risk attitudes in the laboratory, while Deck, Lee, and Reyes (in press) use naturally occurring data from a game show. The lack of responsiveness claim is based on the assumption of constant relative risk aversion and is due in part to the large changes in probability in the model associated with 0.1 increment changes in e and m about their optimal levels. Our choice of increments was designed to keep the number of table entries manageable and simultaneously allow us to present subjects with the same cost choices in all four treatments. Games 5-8 exhibit far more gradual changes in probability, but the general pattern was similar to what is reported here, though there was somewhat greater variation, which could be due to the probabilities or subject experience.

(23) Previous studies on risk attitudes often find evidence that at least some of the subjects are risk seeking. See, for example, Holt and Laury (2002); Berg, Dickhaut, and Rietz (2005); and Deck, Lee, and Reyes (in press), among others.

(24) Salmon and Wilson (2006) consider an auction environment with second chance offers where the seller can make a take it or leave it offer to the party losing the auction. They find that the sellers' attempt to capture most of the surplus in this secondary market and the bidders are agreeable to this allocation.

Cary A. Deck * and Javier Reyes ([dagger])

* University of Arkansas, Department of Economics, Sam M. Walton College of Business, WCOB 402, Fayetteville, AR 72701, USA; E-mail [email protected].

([dagger]) University of Arkansas, Department of Economics, Sam M. Walton College of Business, WCOB 402, Fayetteville, AR 72701, USA; E-mail [email protected]; corresponding author.

For helpful comments we thank Christopher P. Ball, Fabio Mendez, three anonymous referees, and participants at the Missouri Economic Conference. Remaining errors are our own. We gratefully acknowledge support from the National Science Foundation (SES 0350709).
Table 1. Theoretical Predictions for Given Parameter Values

 Optimal e with
 No Second
Condition [phi] [lambda] Investor

[S.sub.[lambda]] -0.05 0.6 0.7
[S.sup.[lambda]] -0.05 0.7 0.8
[C.sub.[lambda]] -0.55 0.6 0.0
[C.sup.[lambda]] -0.55 0.7 0.0

 Optimal e
 with Second Relationship
Condition Investor of e and m Optimal m

[S.sub.[lambda]] 0.2 Substitutes 0.8 - e
[S.sup.[lambda]] 0.2 Substitutes 0.9 - e
[C.sub.[lambda]] 0.7 Complements 1.3 - e
[C.sup.[lambda]] 0.7 Complements 1.4 - e

Optimal second investment, m, is conditional on assumption that the
first investor is providing a level of at least -[phi] + 0.15, but
not so much as to complete the project alone.

Table 2. Sequence of Games by Session

 Games 1-4, Games 5-8,
Session One Investor Two Investors

1 [R.sub.1], [R.sub.2], [PG.sub.8], C,
 [R.sub.3], [R.sub.4] [PG.sub.6], S
2 [R.sub.1], [R.sub.2], [PG.sub.8], C,
 [R.sub.3], [R.sub.4] [PG.sub.6], S
3 [R.sub.1], [R.sub.2], S, [PG.sub.6],
 [R.sub.3], [R.sub.4] C, [PG.sub.8]
4 [R.sub.1], [R.sub.2], S, [PG.sub.6],
 [R.sub.3], [R.sub.4] C, [PG.sub.8]
5 [R.sub.1], [R.sub.2], S, [PG.sub.6],
 [R.sub.3], [R.sub.4] C, [PG.sub.8]
6 [R.sub.1], [R.sub.2], S, [PG.sub.6],
 [R.sub.3], [R.sub.4] C, [PG.sub.8]
7 [R.sub.1], [R.sub.2], [PG.sub.8], C,
 [R.sub.3], [R.sub.4] [PG.sub.6], S
8 [R.sub.1], [R.sub.2], [PG.sub.8], C,
 [R.sub.3], [R.sub.4] [PG.sub.6], S

 Games with
 Two
Session Games 9-14and 15-20 Investors

1 [S.sup.[lambda]], [C.sup.[lambda]], [D.sub.1], Games 15-20
 [D.sub.2], [S.sub.[lambda]], [C.sup.[lambda]]
2 [C.sub.[lambda]], [S.sup.[lambda]], [D.sub.1], Games 15-20
 [D.sub.2], [C.sup.[lambda]], [S.sup.[lambda]]
3 [S.sub.[lambda]], [C.sub.[lambda]], [D.sub.2], Games 15-20
 [D.sub.1], [S.sup.[lambda]], [C.sup.[lambda]]
4 [C.sup.[lambda]], [S.sup.[lambda]], [D.sub.2], Games 15-20
 [D.sub.1], [C.sub.[lambda]], [S.sub.[lambda]]
5 [S.sup.[lambda]], [C.sup.[lambda]], [D.sub.1], Games 9-14
 [D.sub.2], [S.sub.[lambda]], [C.sub.[lambda]]
6 [C.sub.[lambda]], [S.sub.[lambda]], [D.sub.1], Games 9-14
 [D.sub.2], [C.sup.[lambda]], [S.sup.[lambda]]
7 [S.sub.[lambda]], [C.sub.[lambda]], [D.sub.2], Games 9-14
 [D.sub.1], [S.sup.[lambda]], [C.sup.[lambda]]
8 [C.sup.[lambda]], [S.sup.[lambda]], [D.sub.2], Games 9-14
 [D.sub.1], [C.sub.[lambda]], [S.sub.[lambda]]

[R.sub.1], [R.sub.2], [R.sub.3], and [R.sub.4] denote single-investor
games used to assess risk attitudes. [PG.sub.8] and [PG.sub.6] denote
sequential public goods games with marginal per capita (probability)
returns of 0.08 and 0.06, respectively. C and S refer to complement
and substitute games, and [D.sub.1] and [D.sub.2] refer to games
derived from other parameter values in the model of Morris and Shin
(2006). The single-investor version of C/S was substituted for the
single-investor version of [C.sup.[lambda]], as described in footnote
17.

Table 3. Mixed-Effects Estimation for Second Investor

 Standard
 Value Error d.f. t p

[[beta].sub.0] 0.57498 0.0272 48 21.123 -0.0001
[[beta].sub.1] 0.07715 0.0283 48 2.725 0.0089
[[beta].sub.2] -0.93157 0.0823 48 -11.317 -0.0001
[[beta].sub.3] -0.09195 0.0464 48 -1.982 0.0532

Table 4. Mixed-Effects Estimation for First Investor

 Standard
 Value Error d.f. t p

[[gamma].sub.0] 0.5388 0.0437 69 12.337 <0.0001
[[gamma].sub.1] -0.1335 0.0448 69 -2.982 0.0040
[[gamma].sub.2] 0.0900 0.0448 69 2.011 0.0482
[[gamma].sub.3] -0.0849 0.0633 69 -1.341 0.1845


联系我们|关于我们|网站声明
国家哲学社会科学文献中心版权所有