Introduction: Luis de Molina, S.J.: life, studies, and teaching.
Camacho, Francisco Gomez
Luis de Molina was born in Cuenca (Spain) in 1535 and died in
Madrid on October 12, 1600. He entered the Society of Jesus at Alcala at
the age of eighteen and was sent to Coimbra (Portugal) to finish his
novitiate. He studied his philosophical and theological courses at
Coimbra and was so successful in his studies that he was named professor
of philosophy at this University in 1563, where he remained until 1567.
By August of 1568, Molina had been transferred to Evora (Portugal) to
teach theology. He expounded with great success Saint Thomas's
Summa Theologica for twenty years, and in 1591 he retired to his native
city of Cuenca to devote himself exclusively to writing and preparing
for print the results of his long studies. Two years later, however, the
Society of Jesus opened the Imperial College at Madrid and Molina was
called to teach moral philosophy in the newly established institution.
He died while still in Cuenca, before he had held his new chair in
Madrid. Luis de Molina was no less eminent as a jurist than as a
speculative philosopher and theologian. A proof is his work De iustitia
et iure, which appeared complete only after his death.
In the sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries, a fairly small
group of theologians and jurists centered in Spain attempted to
synthesize the Roman legal texts with Aristotelian and Thomist moral
philosophy. Molina and Lugo reorganized Roman law in its vast detail and
presented it as a commentary on the Aristotelian and Thomistic virtue of
justice in their treatise On Justice and Law (De iustitia et iure). The
traditions of Roman law and Greek philosophy became intertwined more
closely than they ever had been before or were to be again. (1)
Molina's chief contribution to the science of theology was his
Concordia, on which he spent thirty years of the most assiduous labor.
The full title of the now famous work is Concordia liberi arbitrii cum
gratiae donis, divina praescientia, providentia, praedestinatione et
reprobatione (Lisbon, 1588). As the title indicates, the work is
primarily concerned with the difficult problem of reconciling God's
praescientia and human free will. In view of its purpose and principal
content, the work may also be regarded by the economist as a scientific
vindication of the doctrine of the permanence of human free will under
perfect information, and so could be interpreted, for instance, by
authors such as Oskard Morgenstern, (2) J. Robinson, (3) and J. Hicks.
(4) These references to the problem of predestination by such economists
may be sufficient reason to think that Molina would have felt at home
trying to solve problems posed in our day by the economist with the
theoretical hypothesis of perfect information and human freedom.
Molina's varied interests amaze the modern reader, and
Vansteenberge (5) remarks that the multitude of applications Molina
makes of his principles is such that with the sole aid of his books a
broad but accurate picture of the social and economic conditions of his
time could be drawn. So, for example, in the Treatise on Money, Argument
408, (6) we find the following description of different kinds of
businessmen.
Economic Context
Three main classes of businessmen developed in Europe in the
sixteenth and seventeenth centuries: merchants, money changers, and
bankers. The merchant kept in close touch with his counterpart and had
his "factors" in every corner of the world. In Seville, the
merchant was an imposing figure, having in his hands "the greatest
trade of Christendom," and even in Barbary. To Flanders he sent
wool, olive oil, and wines in exchange for cloth, carpets, and books,
and to Florence cochineal and leather against gold brocade and silks. He
imported linen from Flanders and Italy and had a hand in the lucrative
salve trade of Cape Verde. So great were the mixed cargoes he sent to
all parts of the Indies in exchange for gold, silver, pearls, cochineal,
and leather that "not Seville nor twenty Sevilles" would
suffice to insure them, and he had to call upon the resources of Lyons,
Burgos, Lisbon, and Flanders for the purpose.
Close upon the merchant's paces followed the money changer,
who traveled from fair to fair and from place to place with his table
and boxes and books. (7) In theory the money changer was a public
official whose business was to deal in cambium minutum or the changing
of gold coins into silver or other money in return for a small fee.
Money changers were to keep proper books "and not leave blank
sheets between the pages already used," and only persons appointed
by the cities or "villas" might act as brokers. The whole
business of the fair was conducted through the money changers, and cash
transactions were reduced to a minimum by the cancelling out of book
entries. Tomas de Mercado complains that "the money changers sweep
all the money into their own houses, and when a month later the
merchants are short of cash they give them back their own money at an
exorbitant rate." (8) In this and other ways the money changers
made big profits, and it is for them that the severest verdicts of the
theologians were reserved.
The proper banker was a much more dignified personage. The bankers
served their depositors free of charge and used the money deposited to
finance their own operations. The bankers, writes Tomas de Mercado,
are in substance the treasures and depositaries of the merchants....
In Spain a banker bestrides a whole world and embraces more than
the Ocean, though sometimes he does not hold tight enough and all
comes crashing to the ground. (9)
As early as 1526 the Venetian ambassador had observed that although
goods were abundant at the fair of Medina del Campo the most important
business was done in exchange transactions. All the evidence points to
an accentuation of this tendency during the succeeding decades, and the
fairs of Medina del Campo, Medina de Rioseco, and Villalon (10) lost the
last traces of their old local character, and became great national, and
indeed international, clearing centers. They were by this time
"mainly places for settling accounts, not for true buying and
selling," though of such there was still "a good share."
(11)
Financial Innovation and Excesses
A contract can be defined as a mutual agreement generating an
obligation from the consent of the parties. Several contracts in the
sixteenth and seventeenth centuries were financial instruments. In
Molina's Treatise on Money, Argument 398, we find a description of
different kinds of economic contracts. A principal division of contracts
into "named" and "unnamed" contracts is established.
There are four kinds of "unnamed" or generic contracts:
"I give that you may give"; "I give that you may
do"; "I do that you may pay"; "I do that you may
do." A named contract is one that has a special proper name by
which it is distinguished from any other: purchase, sale, loan (mutuum),
hire, association (partnership), accommodation (commodatum), pledge or
mortgage, deposit, and so forth. Contracts are also divided into
lucrative and onerous or burdensome. Contracts by which ownership is
transferred may be listed: gift (donation), exchange (permutation), loan
(mutuum), purchase (emptio), sale (venditio), monetary exchange
(cambium), and so forth. The important thing to note is the variety of
juridical figures as a form of reply to the different social and
economic circumstances that originated with the arrival of precious
metals.
A special juridical figure was dry exchange, a term loosely applied
to any fictitious operation devised to evade the usury laws. We first
meet it in Florence in the later Middle Ages, and it was, in fact,
nothing but a loan camouflaged as an exchange deal. The borrower drew a
bill of exchange in favor of the lender on some man of straw nominated
by the latter, and this nominee protested the bill on its arrival. The
borrower was then legally obliged to compensate the lender for the
pretended loss sustained on both the exchange and the re-exchange. Dry
exchange in this narrower sense was redefined and condemned by a Papal
Bull of 1566 and again by a Spanish pragmatic of 1598, and was
stigmatized as a "manifest cankered usury" also in England by
Thomas Wilson in 1572.
The Question of Continuity and Change of Paradigm
When I first published The Theory of Just Price, by Luis de Molina,
appealing to the philosophical methodology of Thomas Kuhn, I wrote that
The Spanish doctors of the sixteenth century and, more concretely
Luis de Molina, used in their moral reasoning an economic paradigm
that, in so far as it was to be substituted by the classical
paradigm, allows one to judge how much the just price does not
coincide with the equilibrium price of classical theory. It does
not seem possible to defend the identification of these prices
without denying by doing so the existence of an authentic
scientific revolution in the second half of the eighteenth century.
It seems clear that the classical and scholastic disciplinary
matrices could not harbor the same offspring. (12)
Two main philosophical reasons seem to endorse this thesis: First,
there was a change in the philosophical and scientific notion of
causality and, accordingly, second, a change in the anthropology and
vision of the economic agent. The change in the anthropological vision
of the economic agent has been mentioned before; namely, the scholastic
economic agent is not the homo oeconomicus of the classical economists,
it is closer to the "Keynesian apple." This change of the
philosophical and scientific notion of causality and natural law A.
Koyre describes as
the destruction of the cosmos and the geometrization of space, that
is, the substitution for the conception of the world as a finite
well-ordered whole, in which the spatial structure embodied a
hierarchy of perfection and value, that of an indefinite or even
infinite universe no longer united by natural subordination, but
unified only by the identity of its ultimate and basic components
and laws; and the replacement of the Aristotelian conception of
space--a differentiated set of inner worldly place--by that of
Euclidean geometry--an essentially infinite and homogeneous
extension from now considered as identical with the real space of
the world. (13)
This change was introduced in the seventeenth century by the
scientific revolution, but, of course, a change of mentality does not
occur suddenly, it needs time for its accomplishment. The consequence of
this change of "vision" (14) by the scientific revolution was
the discarding by scientific thought of all considerations based
upon value-concepts, such as perfection, harmony, meaning, and aim,
and finally the utter devalorization of being, the divorce of the
world of value and the world of facts. (15)
The classical economists followed the epistemology and anthropology
of the scientific revolution and their interpretation of the natural law
was different from the scholastic interpretation. The following points
were crucial in this change of "paradigm": a new concept of
causal relation substituted the scholastic causal relation, and a new
vision of the person as economic agent substituted the old scholastic
vision.
The Old Causality and the New Causality in Relation to a Free
Market: From Moral Philosophy to Natural Science
It is J. Hicks who underlined the transition in the seventeenth
century from the old causality to the new causality as a consequence of
the scientific revolution in the seventeenth century. The old causality
belongs to a
System of thought ... in which causes are always thought of as
actions by someone; there is always an agent, either a human agent
or a supernatural agent, responsible for the action. It is
fascinating to observe, in the literature of the seventeenth and
eighteenth centuries, how this old causality broke down. (16)
The scholastic doctors developed a system of economic thought in
which the subjects were active agents, responsible for their actions,
therefore, they developed a system of economic thought based on the old
causality. The difference between the scholastic agent and the economic
agent in a free market has to do with the distinction between a
"price maker" and a "price taker" agent, a
distinction consequent upon the philosophical distinction between the
old causality and the new causality. A "price maker" is
responsible for the market price but a "price taker," to the
contrary, is not responsible for the market price. In other words, a
price that depends on the subject's behavior is not a price based
on a necessary law, as it is a price based on the forces of supply and
demand. With the philosophers of the Enlightenment, the new causality
substituted the old causality and, according to Hicks, was "a
permanent acquisition." (17)
Within the scholastic vision, the economic agents were considered
"price makers" and, therefore, morally responsible. The
transition to the new causality from the old causality, to the agent
"price takers" from the agent "price maker,"
introduced a significant change in the vision and interpretation of
"common estimate" as a criterion of justice, a change that we
might label one of "scientific paradigm." Langholm describes
such a change as a process of depersonalization of the idea of the
market.
Taking the common estimate as one criterion of justice, the medieval
scholastics, early on, conceded that this estimate, insofar as it
referred to the market, would vary to some extent with supply and
demand. They would not, thereby, at first, permit economic actors to
disclaim subjective, personal moral responsibility for their own use
of economic power. This was something that happened gradually with
the increasing objectivization (to use Gordon's term) or
depersonalization of the idea of the market. More than anything
else, it signals the breakdown of the medieval scholastic approach
to economic ethics. (18)
What Langholm calls a process of increasing depersonalization is no
different from what I have called a process of transition from a
"price maker" to a "price taker," from the old
causality to the new causality. By the second half of the eighteenth
century this change had been accomplished and scientific reason became
the norm to follow in human economic behavior. The necessary reason of
science had substituted the recta ratio of the scholastics and, as a
consequence, economics was understood as a natural science instead of a
moral science. It will be necessary to wait until Keynes's General
Theory for economics to be viewed as a moral science again. It was in
this new "vision" of economics that the "Keynesian
apple" substituted the utilitarian homo oeconomicus.
What had been to Smith a necessary process of adjustment to the
scientific rationality based on the impersonal forces of supply and
demand, to the scholastics had been a contingent and fallible process of
adjustment to the moral norm of justice. The depersonalization of the
idea of the market was contrary to the scholastic vision. The scholastic
recta ratio is not a depersonalized mathematical reason: it is a
probable human reason. It is true, as Langholm writes,
Until a few decades ago, it was not uncommon in critical studies to
encounter the suggestion that the medieval scholastics simply
permitted the forces of the market to run their course and accepted
the resultant "common estimate of the market" as the just price.
[However] More recently, this liberalistic interpretation has been
challenged by a younger generation of scholars, with whose
arguments, as far as they go, I fully agree. (19)
The subject as a mean subject of an aggregate of individuals
substituted and assumed the role of the scholastic singular individual.
As a logical consequence, a change was produced in the interpretation of
the natural law. (20)
Probabilism and the Knowledge of Natural Law in Scholastic Thought
The scholastic doctors traced their concept of natural law back to
Aristotle and the Roman jurists, although they made of it something very
different. Aristotle, for example, distinguished "natural
justice" from "institutional justice," but this
distinction developed in a wider sense with scholastic nominalism. There
are two different epistemological approaches to natural law: one based
on certainty and necessity, another based on uncertainty and
probability. Luis de Molina, along with the rest of the Spanish doctors,
holds a view of natural law and the decision-making process that can be
described as probablistic. The reason was clear, as Luis de Molina
writes,
... nature does not show us what belongs to natural law in such a
way that, while deducing some conclusions starting from principles,
especially when conclusions are such that they follow first
principles in an indirect and unclear way, some error might not get
into the conclusions. Therefore, in dealing with what belong to
natural law, some error might result. (21)
According to the Spanish scholastics, uncertainty and imperfect
information are two essential features of our knowledge of natural law.
It was this recognition of the importance of uncertainty and imperfect
information that led the scholastic doctors to probabilism and casuistry in moral philosophy. It was a logical answer to the difficult problem of
the application of the general first principle to the singular case in a
decision process. The first principle of moral life can be known with
certainty, but we cannot know with certainty how conduct in a singular
case is related to the first principle. In most branches of academic
logic, such as the theory of the syllogism, all arguments aim at
demonstrative certainty; they aim to be conclusive. In scholastic
probabilism arguments are rational and claim some weight without
pretending to be certain and conclusive. Scholastic recta ratio does not
lead to truth but to opinion, and has nothing to recommend it but its
subjective probability. As Martin de Azpilcueta, doctor Navarro, had
written in his Manual de confesores in 1556,
... science is firm and clear knowledge; faith, not clear but dim;
and opinion, neither firm nor clear knowledge; doubt, neither
clear, nor firm, nor judicative; and scruples is nothing else but
an argument against some of the above mentioned four. It follows,
also, that the first four are opposite to each other and cannot
occur in the same person. (22)
The scholastic recta ratio was not a scientific reason: it was a
moral reason, and therefore, fallible and not necessary. Molina seems to
be the more cautious and skeptical in his approach to knowledge of the
natural law, both in trying to tease out what exactly it was, and in his
grave doubts as to whether in fact it was so obvious and easy to
understand. It is interesting to note that, in his Treatise on
Probability, Keynes mentions the Jesuit doctrine of probabilism as
"the first contact of theories of probability with modern
ethics." (23)
I am not suggesting that scholastic probability is the same as
Keynes's probability, or that Keynes's interpretation of
scholastic probabilism is correct. But it does not seem accidental that
the scholastic doctors and Keynes both agree about economics being a
moral science based on fallible "opinions" about the cases
considered, that both the scholastic doctors and Keynes used the
philosophical distinction between the causa essendi and the causa
cognoscendi when speaking of natural law, and that both accepted some
kind of nominalism. If, as Peter F. Drucker writes,
"Philosophically speaking, Keynes became an extreme
nominalist," (24) Vereecke's opinion is that it seems
impossible to analyze sixteenth-century moral economics without
knowledge of nominalism. (25) Scholastic monetary theory cannot be
understood without knowledge of nominalist philosophy, and something
similar may be said of Keynes' monetary theory.
Nominalism and Scholastic Monetary Theory
If from an anthropological point of view scholastic probabilism and
casuistry go back to the difficult problem of causality and human
knowledge, its philosophical roots have to be seen in nominalist
philosophy. In some areas, such as their political and moral philosophy,
the late scholastics owed a large debt to Occamist philosophy and
voluntarist anthropology, even when they tried to break free from them.
Nominalist philosophy stressed aspects of knowledge that were of
great significance and reached far into the development of monetary
thought. The nominalist claimed, for example, that only those
propositions that could be reduced to the principle of contradiction would be considered absolutely "real," turning the causal
propositions of science into merely probable propositions. They
underlined the empirical dimension of moral and scientific knowledge;
the logical coherence of abstract reasoning needed to be completed by
withstanding the test of specific circumstances that defined the case
under study. At the same time, the empirical knowledge of the case could
not be understood without a general theory that had to be logically
congruent. This is why the decision-making process was seen as a process
born of a fallible subject who took a chance on a specifiable reasonable
probability, which was neither truly necessary nor mathematically
conclusive.
Among the nominalists, there was a certain kind of skepticism about
the possibility of knowledge of an order in the world that human reason
could discover. Nominalist philosophers claimed that abstract concepts
were creations of mind rather than discoveries about the world. Hence,
the relationship between abstract concepts, such as a unit of account
(universals), and individual realities such as a standard commodity
(singulars) was one of the controversial subjects between nominalists
and realists. (26) According to nominalism, "there only exists the
singular or individual" (quidquid existit singulare est seu
individuum), universal concepts are only inventions of the mind. This
principle is essential for a correct understanding of the scholastic
monetary theory, for it applied to the unit of account in its double
meaning, that is, as a pure number or abstract unit and as a standard or
thing referred to as a unit of account.
In Molina's monetary theory, as with the scholastics in
general, there is a significant distinction between the unit of account
as an abstract concept and the singular thing, which is called the
standard unit of measurement. When Molina writes: "A coin can be
considered in two ways: one, as a coin; another, as a metal or as gold
of greater or lesser purity, of greater or lesser weight," (27) the
term coin is understood in a double sense: as an abstract concept and as
the singular thing denoted by such a concept. The distinction between
the name unit of account and the singular thing denoted by this name was
interpreted by Molina and the Spanish doctors according to nominalist
philosophy and, therefore, as what the philosophy of science today terms
a "coordinative definition."
Scholastic Monetary Theory
A Scientific Problem: The Standard Unit of Account as a
"Coordinative Definition" (28)
We can define only by means of other concepts what we mean by a
unit of account or "numeraire," but this definition does not
say anything about the real value of the singular unit that can only be
established by reference to a real given good (gold, silver, or any
other economic commodity). In Hicks's terminology, the
"numeraire" or unit of account has to be "anchored"
to a real commodity. (29) A unit of account is an abstract concept and
an abstract mathematical number. For nominalism, mathematical notions
were altogether connotative: number, extension, time, degree, are
connotative concepts addressing relations between singulars rather than
naming singular objects or absolute properties of them. Of course, such
connotative notions are not without a fundamentum in re, but they should
not be hypostatized. Money as unit of account or "numeraire"
was just an ens rationis, and its fundamentum in re[alitate] was the
standard good or commodity connoted by the concept, and to which the
abstract concept is "anchored." The "coordinative
definition" of the unit of account seems to be a simple legal
operation of "anchorage," but the legal procedure is one thing
and its economic and social meaning another.
A "coordinative definition" poses to the economist a
serious epistemological problem: being a nominal concept, the
relationship between the nominal unit and the real commodity has to be
established by law, and it is here that the problem of metrical congruence begins. Two different questions were asked and answered by
Molina and the Spanish doctors in the sixteenth and seventeenth
centuries: Who must define the "coordinative definition?" What
are the logical conditions of possibility for a neutral (sterile)
definition of the standard money of account? The first one poses a
sociopolitical problem; the second must be seen as an analytical
problem, for it has to do with the scientific and analytical meaning of
such a "coordinative definition."
A Political Problem: Who Must Define the Standard Unit of Account?
According to Luis de Molina and the Spanish doctors, it is the role
of the public authority to determine the economic commodity and to
coordinate the nominal unit of account. The public authority has the
legal right to determine and declare the economic commodity to which the
mathematical and abstract unit of account has to be
"anchored," for it is the right of the state to define the
metrical system of the nation. After the coinage has been minted, the
standard units were supposed to be worth not only what their metal would
bring in the market place, but also what the government that issued it
declared it was worth. If chartalism is the doctrine that holds money is
a creation of the state as Keynes writes, (30) the scholastic doctors
were chartalists and not bullionists or metalists. (31) But Keynes
conceded to the state a monetary function that the scholastic doctors
never recognized. According to Keynes,
... if the same thing always answered to the same description, the
distinction [between the abstract unit and the standard thing] would
have no practical interest. But if the thing can change, whilst the
description remains the same, then the distinction can be highly
significant. The difference is like that between the king of England
(whoever he may be) and King George.... It is for the State to
declare when the times comes, who the king of England is. (32)
In the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, to the contrary, it was
all too evident that any standard of measurement had to be constant
through time and space, and the economic standard of measurement was no
exception. The scholastic doctrine was summarized by Tomas de Mercado in
that way:
It is universal and necessary for (money) to be any fixed
measurement, that is sure and permanent. Everything else can, and
even must change, but the measurement must be permanent, because as
a fixed sign we can measure the changes of the other things. (33)
The difference between Keynes and the scholastics about the
possibility of a change in the standard value of the unit of account
leads us to the second problem mentioned before: the logical conditions
of possibility of a neutral (sterile) definition of the money of
account. We can refer to this as the "economic congruence"
problem or the metric of economic value.
A Logical Problem: The Logic of a Definition of Monetary
"Congruence"
As A. N. Whitehead wrote, we
... must understand at once that congruence is a controversial
question. It is the theory of measurement in space and time. The
question seems simple. In fact it is simple enough for a standard
procedure to have been settled by act of parliament; and devotion
to metaphysical subtleties is almost the only crime which has never
been imputed to any English parliament. But the procedure is one
thing and its meaning is another. (34)
One thing is the legal "coordinative definition" of the
standard unit of account and another its use and meaning in a process of
measurement in space and time. The process of measurement presupposes,
first, that the quantity to measure is given, that it is an invariable quantity during the process of its measurement and, second, that the
standard unit of measurement employed is a constant value. Neither of
these two suppositions is unproblematic. Devotion to metaphysical
subtleties may be a crime that has never been imputed to any English
Parliament, but the scholastic doctors were charged with such a crime
and especially in relation to the notion of equality and measurement in
time and space. Let us see the logical meaning of congruence in its
relation to measurement and equality.
Measurement is an operation by which we know how many standardized
units has a determinant magnitude, length, weight, economic value, and
so forth. A judgment of measurement is a metrical assertion and it is
essentially a judgment of comparison; but a comparison is not
necessarily a judgment of measurement. Measurement and comparison are
different processes, although both are judgments of comparison. Russell
provided the following explanation of the difference:
A judgment of magnitude is essentially a judgment of comparison: in
unmeasured quantity, comparison as to the mere more or less, but in
measured magnitude, comparison as to the precise how many times. To
speak of differences of magnitudes, therefore, in a sense where
comparison cannot reveal them, is logically absurd. (35)
The metrical function of money is not a "comparison as to the
mere more or less," it is a "comparison as to the precise how
many times" and, therefore, presupposes a definition of the
monetary unit as congruent to itself. It is of the essence of
measurement that the standard unit of measurement remains unaltered,
equal to itself; for "... it is a universal rule and necessary for
(money) to be any fixed measure, that is, sure and permanent." (36)
Equality is the term the scholastics used to define justice in economic
exchanges and the classical economists to define economic equilibrium.
It is important, therefore, to know how the logic of relations defines
the relation of equality. In monetary theory this relation is
fundamental to a definition of the metrical function of money.
The Logical Meaning of an Equality Relation
According to the logic of relations, a relation of equality E holds
between any two successive values a and b if it holds also between
values b and a, and if it is also a "symmetrical" relation.
But suppose we compare values b and c, and their relation is a
"symmetrical" relation, if we want to call it a
"transitive" relation it must also hold between values c and
a. A relation that is both transitive and symmetrical, it must also be
reflexive if it has to be a relation of equality. Any value with the
relation of equality E has to be equal in value to itself. In the logic
of relations, a relation that is both symmetrical and transitive is call
an equivalence relation, but equality is a special equivalence, it is a
symmetrical, transitive, and reflexive relation of equivalence. Equality
means equivalence but equivalence does not necessarily mean equality,
and the difference is due to their relation to time. In relation to
equality, time is not a causal factor what, indeed, it can be in
relation to equivalence. Time cannot have a causal effect on a reflexive
relation of equality because the passing of time cannot change a
reflexive relation of equality, and this is the origin of the scientific
and scholastic principle of the uniformity of nature.
A value equal to itself can be a standard measurement of value when
applied successively to measure another value because the nature of its
value is uniform; it is a homogeneous value. A uniform or homogeneous
value means that it can move freely in time and space, and this is the
reason why Russell considered the axiom of free mobility a necessary
logical condition of measurement of a quantitative magnitude. Uniformity
of nature and free mobility mean the same thing, and both depend on the
concept of time and its relation to nature or economic value. Now, when
Dempsey asks why the scholastic doctors were so vigorous in their
exclusion of time as a determining factor for change in economic value,
he answers:
The reason seems to be, not the crudity of the Schoolman's concept
of time, but the perfection of it. From the earliest days of
Scholastic philosophy and theology, and even in positive theology,
the problem of God's eternity and timelessness had forced attention
on the problem of the nature of time. With such a refined concept
in mind, and facing the problem of the exchange of values to an
equality, they laid their emphasis on the fact that time in and by
itself alters no values. With time may come changing circumstances,
especially increasing risk [due to uncertainty], by which values
are altered. These circumstances may found new titles or invalidate
old ones. But the Schoolman consistently and characteristically
insisted that this was the question of fact that required
investigation and was to be probed in each case. An indeterminate
appeal to the passage of time alone was of no avail. (37)
Free mobility depends on time because without a homogeneous time
there is no free mobility, neither is there uniformity of nature. These
two principles are fundamental to a scientific understanding of the
concept of magnitude and causality in scholastic economics. (38)
Differences between one event and another, between one value and
another, do not depend on the mere difference of the times or places at
which they occur, for time and space are homogeneous and, therefore,
causally irrelevant or neutral. We will see later how this relation
between causality and time can be applied to the economic concept of
money as a productive economic factor (interest), but now it is
necessary to return to the process of measurement, that is, to the
metric of economic value.
Fungibility, Liquidity, and Quantification of Economic Value
The scholastic concept of fungibility is a homogeneous form of
time, a form of externality, as Kant would say. A fungible good is a
good whose unit of value can take the place (vices fungi) of any other
unit; because vices fungi of any other unit, such unit of value is
congruent or equal to itself in time and space and can be a standard
unit of measurement. But fungibility, as with liquidity, can be perfect
and imperfect, and a good whose unit of value cannot take the place of
another unit is an imperfect fungible value. A unit of such a good or
value is not necessarily equal to itself, for the passing of time or the
change of place affects the quantity of such a value. An imperfect
fungible value is also an imperfect liquid value, and fungibility and
liquidity are qualities of economic value, they are not quantities of a
homogeneous value. To pass from quality to quantity means to pass from
imperfect to perfect information.
A quantitative magnitude supposes perfect information, but the
scholastic economic subject did not have perfect information, and this
imperfection makes him similar to the Keynesian economic subject.
Fungibility, liquidity, and "reflexibility" are qualities
referred to a temporal value, and only when a "coordinative
definition" of such value is coined by the state, its degree of
liquidity can be considered perfect liquidity or fungibility based on
"perfect" information. But, as Molina observed,
But if the circumstances were to change with time, and the value of
the metal of such coins increased considerably, it should not be
assumed that the legislators would want the laws which fixed the
old rates to be still in force. And even if they wanted to, it
would not be just nor fair.... (39)
The value of money "is not so rigid that it cannot rise and
fall just as the goods do whose price is not fixed by law." This
similar behavior of money and other economic goods introduces imperfect
information on monetary values, and such imperfect information can be
expressed in mathematical terms. Suppose the value of a standard unit of
value, when coined by the state, is represented by an infinitesimal arc
ds; after a period of time, in any other moment of time (t) its value
would be ds.f(t), where the form of the function f(t) must be supposed
as known. How are we to determine the moment t if our information is
imperfect? For this purpose we require a coordinate of time and some
measurement of duration from the origin of the coordinate, and here is
where the axiom of free mobility must be introduced if fungibility is to
be perfect.
A temporal distance from the origin only could be measured if we
assume a law to measure it, but such a law must be implicit in our
function f(t); therefore, until we assume f(t) we have no means of
determining t and the value of the standard unit of value in time and
space. If we accept the axiom of free mobility, the function f(t) would
be zero, for the passing of time would be causally neutral to economic
value. But there is no certainty about the function f(t) for, as Russell
observes,
... experience can neither prove nor disprove the constancy of
shapes [or value] throughout motion, since, if shapes [or value]
were not constant, we should have to assume a law of their
variation before measurement became possible, and therefore
measurement could not itself reveal that variation to us. (40)
Ullastres referred to the divorce between the nominal unit of
account and the "real" one as the "fundamental failure of
the Old Nominalism," and Pierre Vilar observed how difficult it is
to submit a money-commodity to the "coordinative definition"
coined by the public authority. When the divorce occurs, we find
ourselves before two economic metrical systems, two different
"coordinative definitions" of the standard unit of
measurement, one legal and another "real," and a choice has to
be made. Molina's option was for a real commodity standard, but the
important thing to remember is this: whatever the option might be, the
economic subject must know that Molina's option has a moral,
political, and a logical dimension. Molina's option is not the
result of a mechanical decision, but of a responsible moral decision
guided by fallible recta ratio. He provides the following example of
such a moral decision.
In 1558, the ratio of gold and silver set by King Sebastian was
disturbed by unexpected shipments from Ethiopia and, after narrating
these facts, Molina opted for the real standard of measurement,
subordinating the "constitutional" or "legal"
metrical system to the one "empirically" established by the
people.
They tell me that the merchants from here in Castile brought a huge
amount, and that they sold each coin of 1,000 reais for 33 silver
reales, which taken to Portugal were worth 1,320 reais. That is why
I warned King Sebastian that it would be convenient to increase the
price of gold, and such is what I taught from my chair as
professor. But it was useless.... (41)
Molina concludes his narration with the following statement:
... in these exchanges, more importance is given to the amount of
silver comparing it to an equal amount of silver, or to the amount
of gold comparing it to an equal amount of gold of the same purity
than to the amount of copper and its price in different places.
(42)
According to the Spanish doctors, an economic assertion belongs to
moral philosophy and not to natural science; and any moral assertion is
epistemologically on par with opinion in Azpilcueta's previously
mentioned schema, that is, "neither firm nor clear knowledge."
(43) Therefore, an economic transition from certain to uncertain
liquidity, from atemporal to temporal fungibility can only be considered
a moral transition, that is, the result of a personal decision in time
in a world of uncertain economic relations. This was one of the
scholastic reasons to study carefully the notion of time and space, even
if such a study could seem like a set of philosophical subtleties.
A Dynamic Definition of Monetary Congruence: Time and the Rate of
Interest
A rate of interest expresses a relation between a present value and
a future value, a relation between value at moment t and value at moment
t1, two different or successive moments in time. If this relation is
considered a continuous relation we could say that time and economic
value are mathematically continuous. Let us fix attention on the purely
mathematical problem. The relation between the new and the old value as
a continuous relation in time can be named a rate of interest. Suppose
that the old unit of account or measurement, as a result of its
"coordinative definition" by the state, was in a moment t
"anchored" to a real value ds, so that we may write ds = 1,
this valuation of the standard unit must be considered just a
convention. Now, if after a time the state changes the unit of account
and its new value bears a definite relation of continuity with the old
unit, this continuous relation to time of the standard unit could be
written as ds.f(t). Suppose a coordinative system O1, where the axis t
represents the variable time and the axis v represents different
continuous values of the standard unit of measurement, the meaning of
economic congruence in scholastic monetary theory could be explained in
mathematical and geometrical terms as follows:
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
The standard unit of measurement ds = 1 is a congruent value in a
moment of time t, the moment of its coinage or "anchorage."
Suppose that in another moment [t.sub.1] its value has changed to s =
[O.sub.1][O.sub.3], this new value must be a continuous function of
time, therefore, it could be expressed as s = ds.f(t). It is the nature
of this function f(t) and its "empirical" connotation that has
to do with the logical problem of the dynamic congruence of money as the
standard unit of measurement. In scholastic monetary theory it also has
to do with the productivity (or sterility) of money and the notion of
"extrinsic titles" to earn interest. About the nature of the
function f(t) there are three possible choices:
1. f(t) might be the expression of a rate of zero interest, f(t) =
0, and then, ds = constant. Therefore, [O.sub.1][O.sub.3] = ds = s.
2. It might express a rate of interest distinct of zero, f(t) = 0,
but such a rate could be, (2.a) a simple rate of interest and,
therefore, a linear function of time; (2.b) a compound rate of interest
and, therefore, an exponential function of time.
There are three possible elections of a monetary metric regime, but
the question in any of these possible elections is: Who must decide the
kind of relation or function f(t) between the present unit of measure
and the future one? How does he know which one of these three possible
functions will be the right one? The state has the right to define the
standard unit in a moment of time, in the moment of its
"conventional" definition and "anchorage." But this
definition is a link between an abstract concept to a "real"
value or economic good, and we are asking now for the relation between
two "real" and successive values of the same economic good.
How can the state know the "real" relation between the present
and the future value of the standard unit of measurement? How does the
state know if the function f(t) has a zero value or is distinct of zero,
if it is a linear function or an exponential function? Can it be a
question of free election of a definition or it is a question of
empirical recognition of the actual relation between a present and a
future value? In the moment of the "anchorage" of the standard
unit it was a question of social "convention" and definition,
but our question now is how long such "convention" and
definition must last? Can it be changed from time to time, as Keynes
said, or must it be maintained permanently as a moral and legal
obligation?
Although the scholastics were not acquainted with the theory of
relativity, they knew the meaning of a relative relation and its
temporal dimension, and this knowledge was the origin and foundation of
their doctrine of the lucrum cessans and damnum emergens. Before this
doctrine is presented, let us finish with the problem of the election of
the dynamic congruence of the standard unit, the election of the
function ds.f(t). The problem will be set now in mathematical terms of
first and second derivative of value in respect to time.
The Rate of Interest and the Axiom of Free Divisibility of a
Continuous Time
According to the mathematical definition of interest, a simple rate
of interest depends on the duration of the interval between t and t1,
and such an interval is not divisible. On the contrary, a compound rate
of interest does not depend on the duration of the interval and,
therefore, such an interval is divisible ad infinitum. A simple rate of
interest is a magnitude with a temporal dimension, depends on time and,
therefore, the passing of time is an intrinsic cause of a change of
value. Such a time is a discrete magnitude, it is not a continuous
magnitude, and its relation to another interval must be considered an
external relation between different and successive intervals of time. On
the contrary, a compound rate of interest does not depend on the
interval of time, it has no temporal dimension, and time is a continuous
magnitude, but such continuity must be considered an internal relation
between successive values in an infinite period of time. Therefore, a
compound rate of interest connotes an intrinsic cause as the origin of
such a rate of interest, while a simple rate of interest connotes an
extrinsic cause as the possible origin of the interest produced. In
relation to time, there is a distinction between internal causality and
external causality, endogenous and exogenous causality, and the
distinction between these two kinds of causal relation is the analytical
origin of the scholastic distinction between "extrinsic
titles" to interest and "intrinsic titles."
A simple interest is an imperfect liquid value, for its quantity
depends on the passing of time; but this relation is unknown before an
interval of time is bound. As a linear function of time, its
characteristic depends on the relation between time and value, though
once the characteristic is known the relation must be constant, and this
constant relation means imperfect liquidity in any other temporal
relation. Perfect liquidity is contrary to a causal relation of time
and, therefore, to a simple rate of interest; perfect liquidity means
causal independence with respect to time. A change on the liquidity
degree can have an internal cause, that is, a change in the interval of
time. A compound interest is a perfect liquid value, for its quantity
does not depend on the passing of time, there is no causal relation
between time and value. Therefore, any change of value must have a
different origin from the passing of time--it has to have an external
causality. This is the meaning of the scholastic phrase--"the mere
passing of time does not produce interest."
The problem arises when the "coordinative definition" of
the standard unit of measurement is employed in a measurement of the
rate of interest. A standard unit of measurement must be independent of
time but, at the same time, it must be a constant value; therefore, its
dynamic cannot be the dynamic of either a simple interest or of a
compound interest. Is there any other possible dynamic explanation? The
dynamic of a "conventional" value, of a value defined by law
and not by experience. This is the real meaning of a "coordinative
definition" of the standard unit of value; it is a definition of
perfect liquidity in as much as it is accepted and obeyed by the people.
But the state can change the "coordinative definition," and
this change means two different things: It is a quantitative change of
the standard value but also a qualitative change of liquidity from
perfect to imperfect liquidity, and it is important to note that a
"coordinative definition" of perfect liquidity by the state is
only a temporal definition. Keynes exposed clearly the
"conventional" aspect of the definition of economic congruence
when he wrote in his Treatise on Probability that
We must ... distinguish between assertions of law and assertions of
fact, or, in the terminology of Von Kries, between nomologic and
ontologic knowledge. It may be convenient in dealing with some
questions to frame this distinction with reference to the especial
circumstances. But the distinction generally applicable is between
propositions which contain no reference to particular moments of
time, and existential propositions which cannot be stated without
reference to specific points in the time series. The principle of
the uniformity of nature amounts to the assertion that natural laws
are all, in this sense, timeless. We may, therefore, divide our
data into two portions k and l, such that k denotes our formal and
nomologic evidence, consisting of propositions whose predication
does not involve a particular time reference [numeraire], and l
denotes the existential or ontologic propositions [standard unit of
value]. (44)
If the state can change the assertion of law, the
"coordinative definition," this change means a quantitative
change of the standard value, but it also means a qualitative change of
liquidity from perfect to imperfect liquidity, and these two dimensions
are present and characterize the scholastic damnum emergens and lucrum
cessans. A lucrum cessans means that a process of production stops, and
this process can be a process of simple or compound interest. If it is a
process of compound interest, a lucrum cessans must have an external
cause, an ontologic dimension, and means that a qualitative change has
been produced in the nature of the process. If it is a process of simple
interest, the lucrum cessans can have an internal cause, a change in the
interval of time and, therefore, a change of the assertion of law that
is the "coordinative definition" of the standard unit of
value. In any case, what the existence of lucrum cessans or damnum
emergens means is that the principles of the uniformity of nature and
free mobility in space and time are not "natural" principles
but social "conventions," as it is a social
"convention" the "coordinative definition" of the
numeraire as a standard unit of measurement. And because free mobility
in space and time is not a "natural" freedom, a congruent
theory of economic value and exchange cannot be interpreted as an
absolute and universal truth, but as a temporal and local theory about
economic value grounded on a "conventional" definition of
economic congruence.
To the Spanish doctors, the only congruent definition of any
standard unit of measurement had to be an "absolute"
definition, which means that it had to be founded on the axiom of the
uniformity of nature, (45) and such uniformity is contrary to the
lodging of a first and second derivative simultaneously in time. It is
true that the axiom of the uniformity of nature, as the axiom of free
mobility or any other axiom, is a nomologic proposition and not an
"existential" proposition, for experience can neither prove
nor disprove it. To use a scholastic distinction, it is true that the
axiom of the uniformity of nature is the causa cognoscendi of economic
values, though economic values are the causa essendi. But the
peculiarities that define the merits of the scholastic treatises De
iustitia et iure, to which Molina's De cambiis belongs, is the way
in which the causa essendi and the causa cognoscendi are related to each
other. The achievement of this relation was a function the scholastic
doctors entrusted to recta ratio, and its development through the
different cases (casus) reveals how "coordinative definitions"
and empirical statements were interconnected in what today is called a
constitutional monetary regime.
Constitutional Monetary Regimes and Personal Expectations
A monetary regime, writes A. Leijonhufvud,
is, first, a system of expectations governing the behavior of the
public. Second, it is a consistent pattern of behavior on the part
of the monetary authorities such as will sustain these
expectations. The short-run response to policy actions will depend
on the expectations of the public, which is to say, on the regime
that is generally believed to be in effect. (46)
A simple interest supposes a monetary regime in which freedom and
discretion of the economic agents is constrained by the axiom of
indivisibility of time, for the passing of time could produce a change
of value. A compound interest is rooted in a monetary regime in which
freedom and discretion of the economic agents are not constrained by the
axiom of divisibility, for the passing of time and its free division
does not produce a change of value. Scholastic monetary system was a
constitutional regime congruent with the axiom of divisibility and,
because it was congruent with this axiom the passing of time was
considered causally neutral with respect to the production of economic
value. The scholastic metric of value, therefore, may be called a
Euclidean metric; nevertheless, the invariance of the standard unit of
value was as a matter of definition, an assertion of law and not an
assertion of fact, for there is no way of knowing whether a measuring
standard actually retains its value when it moves from time to time or
changes from place to place. The value of the standard unit had to be a
fungible or homogeneous value in space and time, and the
"coordinative definition" of the standard unit of measurement
as a fungible and homogeneous value had to be a legal definition. All
these philosophical considerations must be present when analyzing
scholastic economic literature and, especially, the subject of economic
contracts and the problem of usury.
The Contract of Mutuum, Usury, and the Axiom of Free Divisibility
A transaction of mutuum is defined as a translation of ownership of
some fungible value: from the lender to the borrower and, after a
certain time, from the borrower again to the lender. A loan of mutuum is
a "delivery" of a fungible article (the qualities of which are
fixed in number, weight, or measure) with the intent that it immediately
becomes the property of the one receiving it with the obligation to
restore after a certain time an article of like kind and quality. Your
value becomes my value (tuum fit meum). How do we know if the article
restored to the lender is of like kind and quality as the article
received from him? How do we know if the number, weight, or measure of
the good received is or is not equal to the number, weight, and measure
of another good returned after a period of time? We must distinguish the
"empirical" problem from the problem of juridical and moral
obligation, for without solving the "empirical" problem there
is no reason to inquire of the juridical and moral problem. But the
"empirical" problem is related to the logical problem, that
is, to the logical definition of congruence and its observance by the
economic subjects. This is the moral problem.
A mutuum presupposes perfect fungibility or liquidity, and perfect
fungibility does not change the economic value with the passing of time.
But perfect fungibility is a matter of definition, as we have seen, and
can be broken by a free economic agent. Therefore, the constraint to
observe the definition of perfect fungibility must be a constitutional
monetary constraint, for it is not a necessary physical constraint. A
juridical constraint is a matter of obedience and morality and can be
broken by a free economic agent but, in such a case, the nature of the
legal contract should have been defined. It is a legal and moral
function to determine in such cases what the actual contractual relation
was between the economic agents.
The "constitutional" requirement to defend a fixed
standard value in monetary transactions is a conditio sine qua non of
perfect fungibility, and a mutuum is a dual transaction of perfect
liquidity, from the lender to the borrower and, after an interval of
time, from the borrower to the lender. The scholastic doctors were
opposed in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries to a debasement of
currency because debasement was an operation contrary to a
"constitutional" norm. Under a gold standard, for instance,
the temporary suspension of convertibility means a temporary suspension
of the "coordinative definition" of the standard, the
suspension of its constitutional rule; debasement was a permanent change
of the constitutional norm.
Debasement and Monetary Policy in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth
Centuries
The standard value of the unit of account should not vary, but was
it not evident in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries that it
varied? The experience of repeated new minting of coins had demonstrated
that in difficult situations or emergencies like those that the Crown
frequently experienced the public authority could change the
"coordinative definition" of the standard unit of account. The
question to answer is this: Should we put constraints on the exercise of
discretion in monetary management? This is not the place to give an
answer, but the answer given by Molina and other scholastic doctors was
the following. A frequent manipulation of the currency meant an equal
number of broken words, an equal number of changes in the correlation
between the nominal unit of account and the real commodity chosen as the
unit. The scholastic doctors reacted to these changes of the
"coordinative definition" of the unit of account in the only
way a moral philosopher could in the sixteenth and seventeenth
centuries: condemning the public authority's failure to keep its
word. Altering the value of the currency, just like altering the length
of the meter or the weight of the kilogram, constituted a fraud that
should be condemned. Debasement was robbery, and robbery was prohibited
by moral and secular law. Mariana was explicit on this point. Asking if
the king could lower the weight on a coin against the will of the
people, if the king could go back on his word without the consent of
society, Mariana writes:
Two things are certain here: the first, that the king can change
the form or the minting of money, as long as he does not make it
worse ... the second, due to some difficulties like war or siege,
he can lower its value on two conditions: one, that it be for a
short period of time, or as long as the circumstances required;
two, once the difficulty has abated, he must restore the losses
suffered by the interested parties...; because if the prince is not
a lord but the administrator of the goods of the citizens, he
cannot take part of their patrimony by these means or by others, as
occurs each time money is devalued, since more is charged for what
is worth less. (47)
The reference to the need that arises from "war or siege"
allows us to inquire about a third possible need: reactivation of the
economy. The answer we read in Mariana's work may be surprising,
formulated as it was two centuries before The Wealth of Nations.
Mariana clearly distinguished two time frames in which the
manipulation of money by the authorities would produce its effects: the
short and the long run. This manipulation "is like the drink given
the sick person unduly, which first refreshes him, but later causes more
serious accidents and makes the illness worse." (48) Mariana
explains the "advantages" and "disadvantages" of
enlarging the supply of money by minting "vellon" coins; he
recognizes that money will not flow out of the kingdom and, therefore,
there will be more money in circulation within the nation and the
economy would be stimulated (1) by increasing domestic production, which
will lead to an abundance of cheaper fruits and goods, and (2) debtors
would find money cheaper. (49) In relation to foreign nations a decrease
on imports will be produced, for greater domestic production would make
them unnecessary and, what is more, they will be reduced to being paid
with money of lower value. (50) Finally, the foreigners who still bring
their goods to Spain would prefer to be paid in goods rather than in
cash, which would stimulate once again domestic production. Mariana
recognizes all of these short-term advantages, and that
the king would benefit greatly from it, since he would fulfil his
needs, pay his debts, remove the annuities consuming him, without
hurting [directly] anybody. There is then no doubt that immediate
interest is great. (51)
Nevertheless, Mariana's opinion is that these immediate
benefits will turn into future impediments: farming would be abandoned;
commerce with foreign countries would cease and, due to this shortage,
the people and the kingdom would become impoverished and prices would go
up. To avoid this general increase in price, Mariana adds,
The king will want to fix a legal price on everything, and that
would make the wound fester, because the people will not want to
sell at low prices. (52)
The conflict between short-term and long-term interests is thus
outlined, and the scholastic doctors will solve it by offering a
compromise solution. As a general rule, they rejected the manipulation
of the standard value by the public authority, for debasement was
considered an "infamous systematic robbery," but the Spanish
doctors also recognized that socioeconomic circumstances could evolve
over time in such a way that the legal definition of the standard, its
"coordinative definition," no longer corresponded to the first
"anchoring" of the previous definition, thus making a change
necessary. Hence, the role of the public authority with respect to the
standard unit of account was twofold: first, to respect the
"coordinative definition" given, avoiding any practice that
would involve cheating or robbing society; second, to be aware of the
evolution of circumstances in time. And when these circumstances
warranted, modify the previous definition, adjusting the standard
measure to economic reality.
Conclusion
If the Spanish doctors agreed with Smith and Ricardo as to the
invariability of the standard of measurement, they also agreed with
Keynes as to the need, according to circumstances, "to vary its
declaration [of the standard] from time to time." This conclusion
they learned from the experience of a persistent rise in prices, which
in the first half of the sixteenth century had more than doubled. The
theory developed by the Spanish doctors to explain this rise in prices
is known today as the "quantity theory of money," (53) and
Pierre Vilar speaks of the "Spanish quantitativists" as
authors of a "well founded scholastic tradition." (54)
Grice-Hutchinson, like Pierre Vilar and Wilhelm Weber, is also right in
insisting that the Salamancan theologians discovered the
"purchasing power" theory of exchange, (55) but the meaning of
a "quantity" of value must be rightly understood if we want to
know why the "constitutional monetary regime" of the
scholastics was contrary to usury. To understand scholastic monetary
theory, a serious study of the concept of time and its role in monetary
phenomena is necessary.
(1) J. Gordley, The Philosophical Origins of Modern Contract
Doctrine (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 91.
(2) O. Morgenstern, "Perfect Foresight and Economic
Equilibrium," Economic Research Program, Research Memorandum no. 55
(Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University, 1963).
(3) J. Robinson, La segunda crisis del pensamiento economico
(Mexico City: Ed. Actual, 1973), 66.
(4) J. Hicks, Causality in Economics (Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
1979), 11.
(5) E. Vansteenberge, "Molina," Dictionnaire de theologi
catholique (1929), X, 2092 (part II).
(6) The references to Luis de Molina's Treatise on Money
throughout this introduction are to the Spanish critical edition,
Tratado sobre los cambios, ed. and intro. Francisco Gomez Camacho
(Madrid: Instituto de Estudios Fiscales, 1990).
(7) Luis Saravia de la Calle, Instruccion de mercaderes muy
provechosa (Medina del Compe: A. de Urvena, 1544), f. xciv (verso). A.
W. Crosby, The Measure of Reality: Quantification and Western Society,
1250-1600 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997).
(8) Tomas de Mercado, Summa de tratos y contratos de mercaderes
(Sevilla: H. Diaz, 1571), 87.
(9) Mercado, Summa, IV.3-4.
(10) Molina, Treatise on Money, arg. 409.
(11) Mercado, Summa, IV, 88-89.
(12) Luis de Molina, La teoria del justo precio, ed. and intro.
Francisco Gomez Camacho (Madrid: Editora Nacional, 1981), 98.
(13) A. Koyre, From the Closed World to the Infinite Universe
(Baltimore and London: John Hopkins University Press, 1957), viii. Cf.
A. Funkenstein, Theology and the Scientific Imagination from the Middle
Ages to the Seventeenth Century (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1986), II.B.
(14) Cf. Joseph Schumpeter's notion of "vision" in
History of Economic Analysis (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1967),
Part I, chap. 4, sec. 1d.
(15) Koyre, From the Closed World, 2.
(16) Hicks, Causality in Economics, 6-8.
(17) Hicks, Causality in Economics, 8. "Causation can only be
asserted in terms of the new causality if we have some theory, or
generalization, into which observed events can be fitted; to suppose
that we have theories into which all events can be fitted, is to make a
large claim indeed. It was nevertheless a claim that thinkers of the
eighteenth century, dazzled to the prestige of the Newtonian mechanics,
were tempted to make ... a complete system of natural law seemed just
round the corner. The laws in which 'God' expressed himself
must form such a system."
(18) Odd Langholm, The Legacy of Scholasticism in Economic Thought:
Antecedents of Choice and Power (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge
University Press, 1998), 99.
(19) Langholm, The Legacy of Scholasticism, 85.
(20) Cf. F. Gomez Camacho, "El pensamiento economico de la
Escolastica espanola a la Ilustracion escocesa," in El pensamiento
economico en la Escuela de Salamanca, ed. F. Gomez Camacho and R.
Robledo (Salamanca: Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca, 1998), 205-39;
and F. Gomez Camacho, "Later Scholastics: Spanish Economic Thought
in the XVIth and XVIIth Centuries," in Ancient and Medieval
Economic Ideas and Concepts of Social Justice, ed. S. Todd Lowry and B.
Gordon (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1998), 503-62.
(21) Luis de Molina, De iustitia et iure (Cuenca, 1597), I, col.
15, C.
(22) Martin de Azpilcueta, Manual de confesores (Salamanca, 1556),
cap. 27, no. 273ff.
(23) John Maynard Keynes, The Treatise on Probability (London:
Macmillan, 1921, reprinted 1952), 340.
(24) Peter F. Drucker, "Toward the Next Economics," in
The Crisis in Economic Theory, ed. D. Bell and I. Kristol (New York:
Basic Books, 1981), 5.
(25) L. Vereecke, De Guillaume d'Ockham a Saint Alphonse de
Liguori: etudes d'historie de la theologie morale moderne,
1300-1787 (Rome : Collegium St. Alfonsi de Urbe, 1986), 31.
(26) It is not unfounded that new scholarship, studying
Keynes's philosophy in order to get a better understanding of his
economics, makes a great deal of his distinction between the medieval
scholastic terms causa essendi and causa cognoscendi. The cause of an
event is not the cause of our knowledge of it.
(27) Molina, Treatise on Money, arg. 401, col. 986; arg. 410, col.
1036, B, C, D; Domingo de Soto, De iustitia et iure, libri decem
(Salamanca, 1553), VI, q. 9; and Azpilcueta, Manual, cap. 17, no. 288.
(28) H. Reichenbach, The Philosophy of Space and Time (New York:
Dover, 1958), [section] 4, 14-24.
(29) J. Hicks, Critical Essays in Monetary Theory (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1965), 10, 13.
(30) John Maynard Keynes, A Treatise on Money (New York: AMS Press,
1976), chap. 1.
(31) Pierre Vilar pointed out how the accusation of
"bullionism" that used to be levelled against the scholastic
doctors was unfounded. Pierre Vilar, A History of Gold and Money,
1450-1920, trans. Judith White (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities
Press, 1976), 140. Also B. Gordon refutes Schumpeter's allegation
that Aristotle was a bullionist, in Pre-Classical Economic Thought: From
the Greeks to the Scottish Enlightenment, ed. S. Todd Lowry (Boston:
Kluwer-Nijhoff Publishers, 1987), 226-30.
(32) Keynes, A Treatise on Money, 3-4.
(33) Mercado, Summa, I, 220.
(34) A. N. Whitehead, The Concept of Nature (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1964), 120. (Italics mine)
(35) B. Russell, An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry (New York:
Dover, 1956), 153. (Italics mine)
(36) Mercado, Summa, I, 220.
(37) B. W. Dempsey, "The Historical Emergence of Quantity
Theory," Quarterly Journal of Economics 50 (November 1935): 175-76.
(38) Hicks, Causality in Economics.
(39) Molina, Treatise on Money, arg. 401, col. 988, B.
(40) Russell, Geometry, 153.
(41) Molina, Treatise on Money, arg. 400, col. 979, D.
(42) Molina, Treatise on Money, arg. 400, col. 980, C.
(43) Cf. ftn. 34, 35. Molina, De iustitia et iure, I, col. 15, C;
and Azpilcueta, Manual, cap. 27, no. 273ff.
(44) Keynes, Treatise on Probability, 306-7.
(45) Cf. C. B. Boyer, The History of the Calculus and Its
Conceptual Development (New York: Dover, 1959), chap. 4.
(46) A. Leijonhufvud, Macroeconomic Instability and Coordination:
Selected Essays of Axel Leijonhufvud (Cheltenham, U.K.: Edward Elgar,
2000), 166-83.
(47) Juan de Mariana, Tratado y discurso sobre la moneda de vellon
(Madrid: Instituto de Estudios Fiscales, 1987), 39. This Spanish
translation was made by the author from his original Latin work, De
monetae mutatione. A modern critical edition of the Latin original was
prepared by Josef Falzberger and published recently under the same title
(Heidelberg: Manutius, 1996). Moreover, an English translation of
Falzberger's text was prepared by Patrick T. Brannan, S.J. and
published in the Journal of Markets & Morality 5, no. 2 (Fall 2002)
under the title, A Treatise on the Alteration of Money.
(48) Mariana, Tratado, 48.
(49) Mariana, Tratado, 53-55.
(50) Mariana, Tratado, 54.
(51) Mariana, Tratado, 54.
(52) Mariana, Tratado, 71.
(53) Molina, Treatise on Money, arg. 406, col. 1010, B, C, D.
(54) Vilar, A History of Gold and Money, 140. On the scholastic
tradition in the Indies, see the work of Oreste Popescu, "Origenes
Hispanoamericanos de la Teoria cuantitativa," in Aportaciones del
Pensamiento Economico Iberoamericano, siglos XVI-XX (Madrid: Ediciones
Cultura Hispanica del Instituto de Cooperacion Iberoamericana, 1986),
4-33.
(55) Cf. M. Grice-Hutchison, Economic Thought in Spain: Selected
Essays of Marjorie Grice-Hutchinson, ed. Laurence S. Moss and
Christopher K. Ryan (Aldershot, U.K.: Edward Elgar, 1993), 14-16.