Healthcare intermediaries: medical care organizations can, but do not, improve healthcare quality.
Stein, Alex
Medical care organizations (MCOS), such as health maintenance
organizations and preferred provider organizations, have become popular
in recent decades because of their ability to lower consumers'
healthcare costs while increasing providers' throughput. These
organizations function as healthcare intermediaries or, in a technical
language, as platforms in the two-sided market for medical care, with
the two sides being healthcare providers looking for patients and
patients looking for healthcare providers. This function currently has
negative implications for the quality of medical care, but it can be
utilized to improve that quality.
This article explains how to do it. It begins with describing
various factors--both legal and economic--that affect the quality of
medical care under the MCO framework. This discussion singles out a
serious economic anomaly that the law of medical malpractice aggravates
instead of rectifying. This anomaly is the virtual absence of incentives
on the part of MCOs and their doctors to compete with each other over
the quality of medical care. The article offers a semi-regulatory law
reform proposal that would unlock that competition.
TWO-SIDED MARKET
MCOS are not just health insurers, as many take them to be. They
are also, albeit less conspicuously, healthcare intermediaries. An
individual pays the MCO in advance for medical care that he may require
in the future. The MCO provides medical care to the individual when the
need arises. This is how it functions as a health insurer.
The MCO provides this care by paying affiliated doctors and other
healthcare providers who deliver care to the MCO's insureds. The
doctors' affiliation to this plan is contractual. They contract
with the MCO to set the prices it will pay them for the delivery of
medical care to the MCO's insureds. The MCO pays the doctors by
using the money collected from the insureds (either directly or, as
typically is the case, through the insureds' employers). This is
how the MCO intermediates between doctors and patients--a characteristic
identifying it as a platform in a two-sided market. It is here where my
account of MCOs' economically perverse incentives begins.
PLATFORM ECONOMY To understand these incentives, consider the
simplest example of a platform in a two-sided market: a videogame
console such as Sony's PlayStation or Microsoft's Xbox. These
platforms effectuate transactions between the sellers of videogames
(such as Bungle or EA Sports) and gamers. In this example, buyers and
sellers cannot transact without the platform (no matter what transaction
costs they are willing to expend). To play FIFA-07, a soccer enthusiast
cannot just purchase the program from EA Sports; he needs Sony's or
Microsoft's console to run the program. Without the platforms,
game-programmers would not have buyers. A platform developer thus needs
to design a platform that attracts many gamers and thereby induces
game-programmers to develop games that port to its platform.
In other two-sided market scenarios, buyers and sellers
theoretically are able to transact with each other, but their
transaction costs are too high to make it happen. A seller, for example,
may be willing to sell its product for, say, $100 to an individual
buyer. The buyer, however, would not buy the product because $100 is too
expensive. He would only be willing to pay, say, $70 for the product--a
price the seller would gladly accept as well if she had at least 1,000
buyers rather than just a few. In the 1,000-buyers scenario, the seller
might even be happy to sell the product to each buyer for $60. There may
be 1,000 or more potential buyers for the product, but they are
dispersed and consolidating them would be too expensive.
A cost-efficient platform, however, may still effectuate the
product's sales. To be cost-efficient, a platform needs to make a
profit by collecting a fee from both buyers and sellers. For example, it
may charge a $10 access fee to each buyer in exchange for its
undertaking to the buyer to sell her the product for $60. To be able to
deliver the product for that price, the platform needs to secure the
appropriate contract with the seller. Making and executing such
contracts is much cheaper than making and executing a collective
agreement that embodies 1,000 buyers' undertaking to buy 1,000
products for $60,000. The platform, therefore, generates economy of
scale that benefits both the seller and the buyers of the product.
By using its expertise in the market for this and similar products,
the platform also generates information. It reliably informs buyers
about the products' availability, variety, and prices. It reliably
informs sellers about the buyers' demand for the products. When a
product's potential buyers and sellers do not have this
information, they often decide not to transact. These failed
transactions could have been mutually beneficial to buyers and sellers.
For the right price ("the access fee"), the platform can
remove the coordination and asymmetric-information obstacles for such
buyers and sellers. The fee is a fraction of the buyers' and the
sellers' combined saving in transaction costs. In essence, the
platform pockets the agreed-upon part of its end-users' saved
expenditures on acquisition of information and coordination.
THE MCO PLATFORM This is what MCOs basically do. They sell plan
members (the insureds) the right to receive medical care from doctors
who contract to act as care providers under the plan's conditions.
This right is sold in the form of insurance: a patient's
entitlement to medical care depends upon need. To avoid moral hazard (overuse of medical care), an MCO also introduces a system of
co-payments and deductibles. This system requires a patient to pay a
fixed fee (say, $30) for each delivery of a medical service listed in
the plan. The fee is paid to the service's provider in addition to
the payment that she recovers from the MCO. The co-payment becomes part
of the price that the affiliated doctor receives for service.
The MCO also stipulates in advance the deductible amounts by which
it will reduce its payment toward a patient's medical bills. The
economic effect of these deductibles is similar to that of co-payments.
Both are part of the access fee that the platform--the MCO--charges the
buyer (the patient) for consuming medical care at an attractive price
that the buyer agreed to and paid in advance. To make those prices
attractive, the MCO negotiates them with doctors and other
"in-network" healthcare providers. To obtain the seller's
position on the platform and the consequent access to the numerous
buyers that the platform consolidates, doctors commit themselves to
service the MCO's plan members for discounted prices. Doctors
recover those prices directly from the MCO (patients' co-payments
are only a modest addition to those prices).
Price discounts to which doctors commit themselves are the fee that
they pay for the access to the MCO's platform. The access fee that
a patient pays is a more complex figure. This figure equals the
difference between the patient's payment to the MCO and the
"direct insurance value" of the medical services covered by
the MCO's plan. This value equals the price of insurance negotiated
directly between patients and doctors in a hypothetical collective
bargain.
Finally, a patient always needs to pay a lot more if he goes out of
network. This requirement encourages patients to patronize healthcare
providers with whom the MCO has struck agreements. The consequent
increase in the number of patients encourages healthcare providers to
join the MCO's network.
SETTING PRICES The aggregate access fee that a platform recovers
from its end-users (e.g., game-makers and gamers, doctors and patients)
determines the platform's price level. To generate profit, a
platform's price level always needs to be a positive amount. A
platform's price structure, on the other hand, can distribute the
price level unevenly between end-users. A platform targeting the price
level of, say, $100 per transaction may charge this whole amount to the
end-users on Side A and let the end-users on Side B access it for free.
A nightclub, for example, may require men to pay a $100 admission fee
while women can enter at no charge. An end-user's access fee can
even be a negative sum; nightclubs may provide women with free drinks on
Ladies' Night while men pay a steep cover charge just to enter.
For each platform, both the price level and price structure for
individual participants are determined by the end-users' bargaining
positions. The regular supply-and-demand economy is at work. To the
extent the market permits it, each end-user wants to modify the price
structure by reducing the access fee that he individually pays the
platform. Both sides of the platform thus collectively attempt to reduce
its price level.
The aggregate price level is the only thing that the platform cares
about. The platform cares about the price structure only when it affects
the aggregate price level. When the price structure drives away paying
users or reduces the number of chargeable transactions, the platform
restructures the price. The possibility of increasing the number of
paying users and chargeable transactions also induces the platform to
restructure its access fees. To increase the number of paying users and
chargeable transactions, the platform may even decide to decrease the
price level per transaction. For example, in order to attract 95
additional end-users to each side of the platform, a platform with five
end-users on each side would be willing to decrease its $100 price level
per transaction to any amount above $5.
PURSUIT OF QUALITY Crucially to the quality of medical care,
platforms do not care much about the quality of the traded goods. For a
platform, the good's optimal quality is one that attracts the
greatest possible number of paying users and chargeable transactions.
This incentive for maximizing the economy of scale explains
platforms' specialization in mass consumption goods. Acting upon
this incentive, platforms tend to effectuate transactions with goods
that only have the average or below-average quality.
There is nothing intrinsically wrong with those transactions. When
buyers know exactly what they buy and sellers know exactly what they
sell, the trade is mutually beneficial. Problems emerge, however, when
the information pertaining to the transaction is asymmetrical.
Consider a scenario in which information about the good's
quality is known only to the sellers. The platform's opposite
side--the buyers--do not have this information. They do know, however,
that the sellers have the information; and the buyers may expect to
receive it through the platform. Unfortunately, neither the sellers nor
the platform can credibly communicate this information to the buyers.
Every potential buyer knows that sellers always speak favorably about
the goods they want to sell. There is also nothing special in the
platform to make the sellers' assurance credible. On the contrary:
the platform is interested in simply increasing the number of paying
users and chargeable transactions, and the buyers know it well.
Information about the good's quality consequently remains
asymmetrical.
In a world without transaction costs, this would not be a problem.
Any user facing informational asymmetry would be free to assume the
worst about the traded good and do what is good for her. The sellers and
the platform would consequently have to find ways for making credible
assurances about the good's quality. Failure to do so would
transfer prospective buyers to competitors. Regrettably, however, a
world without transaction costs is not ours. Transaction costs are part
and parcel of any economic reality. Economic analysis, therefore, should
focus on the users' platform-selecting and disembarkment expenses.
Those expenses are decisive. When they are low, informational asymmetry
is not a big problem. When they are high, informational asymmetry
constitutes a serious problem that the market cannot resolve.
With MCOs, these expenses are substantial. By and large, a
person's membership in an MCO's plan is determined by her
employment benefits package. This is how most people come to occupy the
buyers' side on MCOs' platforms. Those platforms are selected
predominantly by people's employers. A person's employer may
select an MCO by evaluating the quality of its medical services against
its price. In a more realistic scenario, however, the employer
shortlists the cheapest MCOs that appear to be of acceptable quality.
In either scenario, employees cannot expediently participate in the
MCO's selection. The collective-action problem blocks their
participation in that important decision. Employees are numerous and
dispersed, as well as diverse in their job-related motivations and
incentives. For that reason, they cannot consolidate into a collective
entity that speaks with one voice in order to bargain with MCOs. Nor can
they adequately negotiate the MCO's identity and plan conditions
with their employers. There is, therefore, no counterbalance to the
employer's incentive for shortchanging employees' healthcare.
(A slight hope that unionization will do the trick would likely be
dashed away by the new set of agency costs.)
An employee also cannot easily switch from one MCO to another. To
move privately to a new MCO, she needs to obtain information about the
quality, scope, and price of medical services that it offers.
Subsequently, the employee needs to evaluate this information. Among
other things, this evaluation needs to account for the employee's
medical needs, both present and future. Together with the high price of
private medical insurance, all this makes the contemplated switch costly
and uncertain at once.
MCOs know all this very well. Their strategy, therefore, is to
attract as many large employers as possible in order to have as many
people as possible on the buyers' side of the platform. This
strategy diversifies the risks that MCOs insure against. The randomized assembly of an MCO's patients will include those whose medical
needs will be modest relative to their payments to the MCO, and those on
whom the MCO will have to spend a lot. Most patients, however, will
incur medical expenses that fall in the average.
POOLING DOCTORS Another part of the MCO's strategy is to find
doctors willing to deliver medical care at attractively discounted
prices. The MCO finds those doctors by offering them a massive and
steady supply of patients. The MCO also works to increase the number and
variety of participating doctors. Making both sides of its platform
densely populated increases the MCO's profit.
An MCO's selection of doctors consequently becomes as
randomized and perfunctory as its recruitment of patients. To shield
itself from liability for medical malpractice, an MCO only needs to
verify its doctors' formal credentials (education, training, and
work experience). Subsequently, the MCO needs to formalize the
doctors' price-discount commitments, fix their status as
independent contractors as opposed to employees (for whose actions the
MCO would be legally responsible), and start reaping the platform's
benefits.
The MCO platform consequently allows bad, average, and good doctors
to pool with each other. Stellar practitioners with an independent and
virtually endless supply of patients would not provide discounted
services to MCOs because those doctors have no economic incentives for
joining the platform. Bad doctors do have such an incentive. For them,
pooling with good and average doctors is an attractive business
strategy.
On the MCO "all aboard" platform, this pooling reaches
its extreme because patients are generally unable to distinguish between
good, average, and below-average doctors. Bad doctors exploit this
asymmetrical information, as well as the fact that average and even good
doctors are still better off staying on the platform than opting out.
For them, the optimal strategy is to benefit from the platform's
massive supply of patients and streamline the provision of medical care.
The quality of care that these pooled doctors deliver would thus
likely fall, given the incentives of the system. Altruism, good
conscience, self-image, and the doctors' culture of "doing the
right thing" would temper this patient-unfriendly incentive. This
mitigating effect, however, cannot be expected to eliminate the pooling
of doctors and its harmful consequences. The intermediated healthcare
system would therefore give a patient less than what she paid for.
In this system, only a few doctors would be able to separate
themselves from others by establishing strong professional reputation
among patients. After establishing this reputation, however, the doctors
would have every incentive to leave the platform. The pooling problem
will consequently persist.
RACE TO THE BOTTOM
Medical malpractice law does not solve this problem. On the
contrary, it exacerbates it. The law requires doctors to provide
patients with customary care. This level of care is defined by the
standards evolving within the relevant medical profession or specialty.
This insider criterion tells a doctor that she would not assume
liability for malpractice if she aligns with what other doctors do.
Doctors therefore can collectively reduce the level of care and reduce
their malpractice risk. By placing doctors on the same platform, the
intermediated healthcare system facilitates this race-to-the-bottom
dynamic.
MCO AS MONITOR MCOs are best positioned to select and monitor
doctors for quality of their services. The law, however, gives MCOs
every incentive not to do it. An MCO's liability for medical
malpractice crucially depends on its contracts with the negligent doctor
and the injured patient. When the MCO has an employment contract with
the doctor, it becomes vicariously liable. When the doctor acts as an
independent contractor, however, vicarious liability does not attach.
The MCO, therefore, can disassociate itself from its doctors'
malpractice by making contracts that establish and unequivocally
communicate to the patient the doctor's independent-contractor
status. The MCO may still assume institutional liability for negligently
credentialing the doctor, but it can easily avoid that liability. To
achieve this result, the MCO only needs to ask about and verify its
doctors' education, training, and other relevant credentials.
Absence of selection and monitoring incentives on the part of the MCO
thus further induces the pooling of good, average, and bad doctors.
POOLING PATIENTS Courts try to decide cases correctly, but do not
always succeed. Every liability system therefore needs to shape its
rules in a way that accounts for the inevitable presence of adjudicative errors. The medical malpractice system generally fails to do so. This
system gives a patient an inalienable right to recover full compensation
from his doctor in the event of injury that results from the
doctor's negligence. This compensation may be a skyrocketing
amount. The patient and the doctor cannot make a contract that
eliminates or downsizes this entitlement. The doctor's liability
for malpractice is fixed by the law of torts, which the patient and the
doctor cannot unmake.
This regime allows opportunistic patients to exploit the presence
of adjudicative errors by suing non-negligent doctors for malpractice.
As a result, the cost of medical care increases for all patients.
Doctors' pricing decisions account for opportunistic lawsuits and
the ensuing payouts. Unable to differentiate between honest and
opportunistic patients, doctors make those decisions for all patients
and subsequently charge the same treatment price (to the patient or the
MCO).
After finding a good doctor, an honest patient may want to, but
cannot, separate from this pool by undertaking not to sue the doctor or,
more realistically, by making a contract that caps her prospective
entitlement to compensation. By making any such agreement ineffectual,
the law effectively forces an honest patient to subsidize the
opportunists.
SUPPRESSING COMPETITION By doing all this, the medical malpractice
system suppresses three competitive dynamics. First, it motivates MCOs
to operate predominantly as financial institutions without competing
with each other over the quality of medical care. Second, it dilutes
doctors' incentives to compete with each other professionally.
Third, it does not allow patients to compete with each other by
utilizing offers to remove or reduce the malpractice liability threat
from selected doctors. This competition could help an honest patient to
obtain quality care for a price that does not subsidize the
opportunistic tort plaintiffs.
RECOMMENDATIONS FOR REFORM
There is a misalignment between MCOs' incentives and the
social good. The law therefore needs to step in and fix the incentives.
Making MCOs institutionally liable for their doctors' malpractice
would force the MCOs to closely monitor doctors and exercise care in
their selection. MCOs should assume this liability irrespective of their
doctors' formal status as employees or independent contractors.
Malpractice victims should have a right to recover compensation from
their MCOs.
This institutional liability should be based on a menu of
agreements. Any doctor working through an MCO's platform and the
MCO itself would have to offer a patient an agreement under which the
MCO assumes full liability for the doctor's malpractice. In
addition to this baseline agreement, the MCO and the doctor should be
allowed to offer the patient any limited-liability agreement, as well as
an agreement that removes the malpractice liability completely (except
for intentional torts). To protect consumers, the law also should
require that MCOs supplement each agreement on their menus with a simple
plain-language explanation of the agreement's basics.
Under this arrangement, medical services would be priced
differentially. An agreement imposing full liability on the MCO would
likely be most expensive. An agreement that completely removes liability
from both the MCO and its doctors would presumably be the cheapest. The
in-between category of limited-liability agreements, also appropriately
priced, would be virtually unlimited. A good example of such an
agreement is a healthcare plan that limits the member's right to
recover compensation for pain and suffering and other non-economic
damages. This limitation may be absolute or it may cap non-economic
damages by specifying the maximum amount of compensation.
This menu of agreements would substantially attenuate the
asymmetrical information problem. The price-difference between the
full-liability agreement and other agreements on the MCO's menu is
a fairly straightforward factor. This factor would credibly communicate
the MCO's internal assessment of its doctors' quality and
propensity to commit malpractice. When the full-liability agreement is
considerably more expensive than other agreements on the menu, the
MCO's assessment of its doctors' malpractice propensity would
be particularly unflattering to the doctors and the MCO. For example, an
MCO that offers a full-liability agreement for $10,000 and a
no-liability agreement for only $1,000 signals patients that 90 percent
of the non-discounted price goes toward the expected medical liability
payouts. Based on this information, prospective patients can safely
assume that joining this MCO's plan would make them unsafe. These
patients would consequently start looking for a better MCO.
As an empirical matter, the general incidence of iatrogenic injuries associated with malpractice ranges between 1 percent and 2
percent. Normally, therefore, the price-difference between the
MCO's full-liability and no-liability agreements must not exceed 2
percent. The price difference between the full-liability agreement and
partial liability agreements can thus be expected to be below 2 percent.
Also, there should be a very little price difference between the
MCO's full-liability agreement and an agreement stipulating that
the patient would only be able to recover economic damages. Note that
compensation for pain and suffering, lost consortium, and other
non-economic damages is generally much higher than what the tort victim
usually receives for his economic losses.
A substantial price difference between the full-liability agreement
and other options offered by the MCO would therefore indicate a
substantial prospect for medical malpractice. This factor would
constitute bad signaling that steers away honest patients and marks the
MCO as a convenient target for opportunists. MCOs therefore would try to
avoid such signaling as much as they can. They would disengage from bad
doctors and would narrow the pricing gap between the agreements on their
menus.
PATIENT SIGNALS This system would also elicit credible signaling
from the patients. A patient normally would not accept an agreement that
altogether removes liability for medical malpractice from both the MCO
and its doctors. By assuring the provider ex ante that malpractice
liability is not a threat, the patient exposes himself to an increased
risk of mistreatment.
The rate of injurious malpractice, presently ranging between 1
percent and 2 percent, attaches to medical patients generally. Those
patients did not turn their doctors into moral hazards by telling them
in advance that they are free to commit malpractice. An honest patient,
however, may well accept a limited-liability agreement that allows her,
in the event of malpractice, to recover compensation for economic
damages alone.
Alternatively, the patient might sign an agreement that limits her
future recovery for non-economic damages to a specified amount. The
patient would accept such an agreement for two reasons. First, she would
pay less for her medical plan and would not subsidize opportunistic
patients. Second, the patient would avoid signaling the MCO that she
might sue it opportunistically. This signaling would shield the patient
from defensive medicine that potentially opportunistic patients, opting
for the full-liability agreement, would receive.
These predictions are good not only for risk-neutral patients but
also for patients who are averse to risk. A risk-averse patient would
prefer better treatment at an affordable cost over a full-liability
agreement that exposes him to defensive medicine and forces him to
subsidize the opportunists and their attorneys.
STRICT INSTITUTIONAL LIABILITY An alternative to this proposal is
an imposition of unmodifiable institutional liability upon MCOs. This
regime, however, is unlikely to induce MCOs to compete over the quality
of medical care.
Under this regime, an MCO would simply add the appropriate
liability insurance requirement to its credentialing checklist and
incorporate an indemnification provision in its agreements with doctors.
Premiums that different doctors pay for liability insurance generally do
not track their individual performance and propensity to commit
malpractice. Liability insurers, indeed, are not as well positioned as
MCOs to evaluate and predict doctors' performance.
Under the menu-of-agreements regime, MCOs would still be able to
shift their liability prospect to insurers. But they would have to
compete with other MCOs who would self-insure more efficiently by
utilizing their superior expertise and informational advantage. These
more efficient MCOs need the contractual flexibility of the
menu-of-agreements regime. By helping these MCOs to improve their market
performance, this regime would make good doctors, honest patients, and
society at large better off.
Readings
* "The Assault on Managed Care: Vicarious Liability, ERISA Preemption, and Class Actions," by Richard A. Epstein and Alan O.
Sykes. Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 30 (2001).
* Health Economics, 3rd ed., by Charles Phelps. Upper Saddle River,
N.J.: Addison Wesley, 2003.
* "Liability for Medical Malpractice," by Patricia M.
Danzon. In Handbook of Health Economics, edited by Anthony J. Culyer and
Joseph P. Newhouse. London, UK: Elsevier Science, 2000.
* "Malpractice Liability for Physicians and Managed Care
Organizations," by Jennifer Arlen and W. Bentley MacLeod. New York
University Law Review, Vol. 78 (2003).
* The Medical Malpractice Myth, by Tom Baker. Chicago, Ill.:
University of Chicago Press, 2005.
* "Platform Competition in Two-Sided Markets," by
Jean-Charles Rochet and Jean Tirole. Journal of the European Economics
Association, Vol. 1 (2003).
* "Torts, Expertise and Authority: Liability of Physicians and
Managed Care Organizations," by Jennifer Arlen and W. Bentley
MacLeod. Rand Journal of Economics, Vol. 36 (2005).
* "Two-Sided Markets: An Overview," by Jean-Charles
Rochet and Jean Tirole. Unpublished manuscript, 2004.
* "Uncertainty and the Welfare Economics of Medical
Care," by Kenneth J. Arrow. American Economics Review, Vol. 53
(1963).
* "Vicarious Liability: Relocating Responsibility for the
Quality of Medical Care," by Clark C. Havighurst. American Journal
of Law and Medicine, Vol. 26 (2000).
BY ALEX STEIN
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Alex Stein is visiting professor of law at Yale Law School and
professor of law at the Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law. He may be
contacted by e-mail at
[email protected].