Aristotle, Aquinas, and Seligman on happiness.
Kaczor, Christopher
What exactly is happiness? Ancient philosophers like Aristotle,
medieval theologians like Thomas Aquinas, and contemporary psychologists
like Martin Seligman have wrestled with this perennial question. In
seeking happiness myself, I've learned a great deal from all three.
I found instructive the ways they accord as well as ways that they
differ.
It might seem at first silly to try to define happiness. "I
know it when I feel it," you might say with some justification. In
a similar way, we know about our bones, but the systematic study of our
bones can nevertheless be useful, especially if something is going wrong
with our bones.
A Positive Psychology Framework for Happiness
In his book Flourish: A Visionary New Understanding of Happiness
and Well Being (2011), Martin Seligman that happiness, which he also
calls flourishing and well-being, involves five different elements:
Emotion, Engagement, Relationships, Meaning, and Achievement (PERMA)
(Seligman 2011). Each of these five elements contributes to human
flourishing, and each is chosen by people as an end desired in itself,
rather than simply as a means to some further end.
The first element of flourishing is positive emotions such as joy,
delight, warmth, euphoria, and gladness. One element of positive
emotion, subjective well being, is how people respond to questions such
as, "How happy are you right now?" or "How satisfied are
you with your life?" (Diener & Biswas-Diener, 2008, p. 4). We
can distinguish feelings, our own subjective and conscious awareness of
emotions, from the emotions themselves. We can be having an emotion
manifesting itself in our bodies and yet not really feel or consciously
realize we have the emotion, as when people say, "I didn't
realize how happy I was until he walked into the room." Likewise,
our bodily reactions may be expressive of positive emotion, but we might
not be (fully) aware of what our emotions are and so not (fully) feel
our emotions. Positive emotions are the first element in Seligman's
conception of flourishing, but other elements also contribute to
well-being.
The second element is engagement with life. Engagement is also
known as flow, making use of signature strengths in an activity
requiring energized focus on the moment, an activity that is neither too
difficult nor too easy. Csikszentmihalyi (1991) understands engagement
or flow as involving challenging activity requiring concentration on the
present which results in a sense of 'time stopping' and a
'loss of self.' Flow can take place in work, hobbies, or
sports, such as when the athlete is 'in the zone' making use
of a signature strength. In Anna Karennina, Tolstoy describes flow in
one character's work,
The longer Levin went on mowing, the oftener he experienced those
moments of oblivion when his arms no longer seemed to swing the scythe,
but the scythe itself his whole body, so conscious and full of life; and
as if by magic, regularly and definitely without a thought being given
to it, the work accomplished itself of its own accord. These were
blessed moments. (Tolstoy, 2004, pp. 252-253)
We can have flow in many different kinds of activities, and flow is
part of a happy life. Taking note of human diversity, positive
psychologists hold that each person has signature strengths that fall
under the general categories of wisdom, courage, justice, temperance,
transcendence, and humanity (charity). Within each general category,
there are sub-categories that define more precisely the strength in
question, such as creativity, leadership, loving and being loved, open
mindedness, teamwork, and kindness. When a person makes use of a
signature strength in a challenging activity with energized focus of
attention to optimum performance, the person experiences flow or full
engagement.
The third element of PERMA, relationships, constitutes another
aspect of human flourishing, indeed perhaps the central element.
Seligman (2011) explains:
When asked what, in two words or
fewer, positive psychology is about,
Christopher Peterson, one of its
founders, replied, " Other people"
Very little that is positive is solitary.
When was the last time you laughed
uproariously? The last time you felt
indescribable joy? The last time you
sensed profound meaning and purpose?
The last time you felt enormously
proud of an accomplishment?
Even without knowing the particulars
of these high points of your life, I
know their form: all of them took
place around other people. Other
people are the best antidote to the
downs of life and the single most
reliable up. (p. 20)
Positive, loving relationships are an essential part of happiness.
Without close, loving, positive relationships, human persons face the
likelihood of physical and mental health problems, and undergo a loss in
human flourishing (Baumeister & Leary, 1995).
On Seligman's view, meaning is another part of flourishing.
Meaning is understood as "belonging to and serving something that
you believe is bigger than the self" (Seligman 2011, p. 17).
Although a person cannot be mistaken about a purely subjective feeling,
it is possible, Seligman holds, to be mistaken about meaning. Pot
smoking adolescents may think their midnight philosophizing was quite
meaningful, but when they sober up and grow up, they may come to realize
if they listen to a recording of their conversation that nothing
meaningful was really said. Likewise, depressive persons like Abraham
Lincoln or Winston Churchill may feel as if their lives are meaningless,
but we can rightly judge that they lead meaningful lives. Meaning
involves a connection and a contribution with something that is larger
than the self: family, school, vocation, political party, country, or
God.
The final element of flourishing on Seligman's (2011) view is
achievement. He says, "Accomplishment or achievement is often
pursued for its own sake, even when it brings no positive emotion, no
meaning, and nothing in the way of positive relationships" (p. 21).
Accomplishment can be sought via mastering certain skills such as
playing a complicated song on the piano, running a marathon in under
three hours, or learning German. Achievement may also be understood
comparatively, such as winning a race, becoming the valedictorian, or
making more money than your peers.
For Seligman, all five elements are needed for full flourishing,
all can be desired as ends in themselves, and all can be quantifiably
measured. Positive emotions are important for happiness, but a
person's happiness is augmented if they not only are experiencing
positive emotions but are also engaged in meaningful work and
achievement. Not just subjective experience but objective reality is
relevant for flourishing in Seligman's (2011) understanding:
Engagement, meaning, relationships,
and accomplishment have both subjective
and objective components,
since you can believe you have
engagement, meaning, good relations,
and high accomplishment and
be wrong, even deluded. The
upshot of this is that well-being cannot
exist just in your own head:
well-being is a combination of feeling
good as well as actually having
meaning, good relationships, and
accomplishment. (p. 25)
Flow-making use of signature strengths is relevant because part of
what people want out of life is not just feeling a certain way, but also
engagement with life. An illusion could generate feelings, but an
illusion does not involve engagement with (real) life. Similarly,
actually having good relationships and accomplishing something (real) is
not merely a subjective feeling. It is hard to imagine a flourishing
human life without some element of each aspect of PERMA: Positive
emotion, Engagement, Relationships, Meaning, and Achievement. How does
the PERMA conception of flourishing compare with the ideas put forward
by two of the preeminent philosophers of happiness, Aristotle and
Aquinas?
PERMA in the Context of Aristotle and Aquinas
Positive Emotions
The importance of emotions is a shared emphasis for positive
psychologists and the philosophers of virtue. For Aristotle, eudemonia
involves experiencing enjoyment, and the emotional life of virtuous
persons--what they take pleasure in and what they find
painful--contributes to their happiness. Likewise, Aquinas devotes a
huge section of the moral part of the Summa theologiae to exploring what
he calls "the passions" such as love, hatred, delight, sorrow,
and fear. Why?
Some might be tempted to think that all that really matters, at
least morally speaking, are your exterior actions, especially doing your
duty, not whether or not you are experiencing certain emotions. Indeed,
it might seem that concern for one's own emotions is a selfish
preoccupation in tension with the demands of duty understood as an
altruistic regard for others. Zagano and Gillespie (2006) express this
concern, "Positive Psychology can appear as a self-seeking and
self-serving process aimed simply at obtaining individual and
interpersonal happiness" (p.50).
I used to think that, ethically speaking at least, all that really
matters is doing your duty and that emotions were insignificant and
irrelevant. While it is true that what we do is vitally important for
our own happiness as well as the happiness of others, I now think that
it is a mistake to belittle the importance of emotions and feelings for
the moral life. When we feel upset, depressed, sad, and angry, it is
still possible to do the right thing, but doing the right thing while
experiencing such emotions becomes immensely more difficult. When we
feel bad, we desire to alleviate our bad feelings, and this can lead us
to act against what we know is right (McGonigal, 2012). We have a moral
responsibility to avoid, insofar as reasonably possible, putting
ourselves in occasions of wrongdoing. Since negative emotions are often
occasions of doing wrong, our moral responsibilities include a concern
for our emotional life.
As negative emotions can draw us to doing wrong, positive emotions
can draw us outwards towards connecting and contributing to others. As
Gretchen Rubin points out, "studies show that happier people are
more likely to help other people. They are more interested in social
problems. They do more volunteer work and contribute more to
charity" (Rubin, 2009, p. 215). It is, therefore, a mistake to
suppose that our own happiness is necessarily set in opposition to the
well-being of others, for often our positive emotions help us to be our
best selves for others.
In addition, the duty to love our neighbor as ourselves leads to a
concern about our own emotions. We would all prefer to experience
positive emotions rather than negative emotions. When we experience
negative emotions, it affects all those with whom we have contact. Just
as we can transmit a contagious disease to other people, so too through
emotional contagion, we influence (positively or negatively) all those
around us (Hatfield, Cacioppo, Rapson, 1993).
Emotions also matter morally because we have a moral duty to take
care of our own health which is damaged by chronic negative emotions.
Since our emotions greatly influence the emotions of others, we are also
negatively or positively influencing the health of others in our life.
Finally, our emotions also matter because our emotions can distort
or enhance our thinking. When we are upset, for example, when we are in
a "fight or flight" mode, we cannot think as clearly as when
we are in a "calm and connect" mode. Since practical wisdom is
needed in order to act well, we have good reason to cultivate positive
emotion. As Fredrickson (2013) points out:
The tightly controlled laboratory
experiments ... convincingly reveal
that the scope of your awareness
changes dramatically over time,
depending on your current emotional
state. Your awareness narrows with
negative emotions and broadens with
positive ones. It is when feeling
good, then, that you're best equipped
to see holistically and come up with
creative and practical solutions to the
problems you and others are facing.
Your wisdom, then, ebbs and flows
just as your emotions do. Let's face
it, you're just not able to access and
integrate all the knowledge and experience
you've gained over the years.
Think back to when you've made
your most unwise choices, and odds
are you'll uncover images of yourself
during particularly strained
times--stressed beyond your limits,
overwhelmed, in pain, wholly alone,
or otherwise adrift from the moorings
of your most-cherished values. By
opening the doors of perception, positive
emotions provide you with the
much-needed space to recognize disparate
points of view and weigh your
various options for action. (p. 82)
St. Ignatius Loyola, the founder of the Jesuits and the author of
the Spiritual Excercises, made similar recommendations to those whom he
gave spiritual direction. He advised them to make decisions and changes
out of a spirit of consolation, rather than desolation. Consolation is
an uplifted, joyful, and happy spirit. Desolation is a feeling of
downheartedness, fear, and anxiety. When enveloped in a spirit of
desolation, Ignatius recommended not making any significant
life-decision or major change (Ignatius, 1964). By contrast, we make
wiser decisions out of a spirit of consolation. So, the emphasis on
emotion and feelings found in contemporary positive psychology (as well
as Aristotle and Aquinas) makes sense even from an ethical point of view
that emphasizes duty.
Aquinas and Aristotle differ from Seligman in their view that the
pleasure of positive emotions is not, without qualification, in every
case good. The pleasure of positive emotions is good, on their view, if
and only if it arises from a good cause, but pleasure can be evil if it
arises from an evil activity. Pruss (2013, pp. 115-127) imagines the
case of someone who delights in the painful death of children in a
cancer ward. Surely, having pleasant emotions because of these deaths is
not a pleasure that is good. Similarly, he imagines a person living in a
delusion that he is the greatest scientist of all time. His wealthy
parents have hired a team of actors who serve to guide him into
"discoveries" that have really been made centuries before. He
feels exhilaration, but again his good feelings are derived from
delusions of grandeur. Such a person's situation is not
choiceworthy. Both the virtuous person and the vicious person experience
pleasant emotions, but the virtuous person derives pleasure from
virtuous activity while the vicious person derives pleasure from vicious
activity. Delight over evil moves a person farther away from true
happiness by serving as an incentive for further wrongdoing.
Positive psychology adds dimensions to the discussion of emotion
that were unknown to Aristotle and Aquinas. For example, researchers
found that exercise is a reliable way to increase positive emotion.
Positive psychology has investigated practices that characteristically
generate positive emotion such as practicing gratitude. Positive
psychology has also recommended practices that mitigate negative
emotions, such as forgiveness.
Engagement
Aristotle and Aquinas would recognize, I think, the idea of flow as
what they called, 'activity in accordance with virtue.' Like
flow, this activity must be challenging (neither too difficult nor too
easy). But unlike flow, activity in accordance with virtue is not
'morally' neutral on their view. You can have flow in doing
evil activities, like scientists using their signature strengths to
build weapons of mass destruction for a terrorist group. By contrast,
for Aristotle and Aquinas, there is no activity in accordance with
virtue for someone engaging in evil activities.
Relationships
Aristotle, Aquinas, and Seligman find common ground in an emphasis
on the importance of good relationships and friendship for flourishing.
Aristotle thought that a person could not be truly happy without
friends. For Aquinas, as mentioned, true happiness requires love, love
of God and love of neighbor. Seligman (2011) holds that, "the
pursuit of relationships is a rock-bottom fundamental of human
well-being" (p. 21). But even though they all recognize the
importance of good relationships for happiness, there are important
differences in how each approaches the subject.
Aristotle and Aquinas emphasized that the moral character of these
friends matters for happiness. Mere friendships of utility or pleasure
tend to be transitory, and therefore do not characteristically
contribute to long term flourishing as do friends of virtue. In positive
psychology, by contrast, I've discovered no emphasis on the moral
character of friends.
Aquinas, unlike Aristotle but like Positive Psychology, places a
special emphasis on marital friendship as a source of happiness.
The greater a friendship is, the more solid and long lasting will
it be. Now there seems to be the greatestbetween husband and wife, for
they are united not only in the act of fleshly union, which produces a
certain gentle association even among beasts, but also in the
partnership of the whole range of domestic activity. (Aquinas, 1975, p.
148)
Aquinas also, here departing from both Aristotle and positive
psychologists such as Seligman, places the highest emphasis on the
friendship that can exist between God and a human being. Ultimately,
nothing is more important than this friendship, both because our eternal
happiness is determined by it and because friendship with God influences
how we view and treat other people. On his view, love for God cannot
exist without love also for the image of God that is found in every
single human being (Aquinas, 1975, pp. 127-128).
But what exactly is love? Fredrickson (2013) emphasizes the
biological and emotional aspects of love. She defines love as "the
momentary upwelling of three tightly interwoven events: first, a sharing
of one or more positive emotions between you and another; second, a
synchrony between your and the other person's biochemistry and
behaviors; and third, a reflected motive to invest in each other's
well being that brings mutual care" (p. 17). On this understanding
of love, love between God and human beings is impossible at least if God
is understood as an absolutely perfect, unchanging, spiritual being. At
least on Aquinas' understanding of God, God does not have emotions,
biochemistry, or well-being that can be aided by human care. On the
Thomistic account, God is absolutely unchanging and perfect, and so
cannot be made worse off or better off in any respect. God does not have
a body and therefore does not have biochemical bodily reactions.
Finally, since emotions are certain changes involving the body, since
God does not change and does not have a body, God does not have
emotions. So, on Aquinas's understanding, Scripture is speaking
metaphorically in saying that God becomes angry (1 Kings 11:9). Such
passages point to the reality that what can change is not God but the
relationship of human beings (who do change) to God. Much as the sun is
consistently hot, but feels wonderful or searing depending on the
condition of the human being in question, so too God is consistently who
God is but is experienced by just and unjust human beings in different
ways. Fredrickson's view of love may work well for describing the
love that exists between human beings. But this understanding of love
will not properly capture the love between human beings and God.
On the other hand, if love is defined as involving good will,
appreciation, and desire for unity (Pruss, 2013), (1) a human being can
share love with God. A human being can be united in good will with God,
a human being can appreciate God, and a human being can desire unity
with God. God's unchanging perfection does not exclude any of these
three elements. Indeed, for Aquinas, the most important of all loves is
the love of God. Without love for God, a person is missing out on the
most important relationship of all. Every human relationship has its
weaknesses because every human being has his or her weaknesses. As human
beings, we desire perfect goodness, perfect truth, perfect beauty, and
perfect love which is why even the best of human relationships do not
perfectly satisfy our restless hearts.
Finally, positive psychology adds many dimensions to a discussion
of friendship and relationships that are unseen in Aristotle or Aquinas,
in providing evidence about what practices help and hinder
relationships. For example, psychologists found friendships are deepened
through what is called active positive responding (see Stanley,
Blumberg, & Markman, 2001). When a friend tells you good news, how
do you react? Positive active responding involves acknowledging the good
news, helping your friend relive the fun of finding out the good news,
and celebrating the good news. By contrast, friendship is dulled when
good news is received indifferently or worse still when someone seeks to
find the down side of the good news, "Have you thought about how
much tax you'll have to pay, now that you've got your big
raise?"
Meaning
For Seligman, meaning, which he understands as participating in and
making a contribution to something bigger than oneself, is part of human
flourishing. Some people might understand meaning in a purely subjective
manner. What is meaningful to you, may not be meaningful to me. And, in
a sense, this is true. I care passionately about Notre Dame football,
and you may care passionately about who is appointed head of your local
PTA. But in the sense in which Seligman uses the term, it is not true
that what is meaningful or significant is purely subjective. He appealed
to Lincoln and Churchill who in their depressive episode may have felt
their lives were meaningless, but whose lives we rightly judge as
immensely meaningful. Indeed, one difference between a mature and sane
person and an immature or insane person is what they take to matter.
Whether a person has an odd or even number of eyelashes does not matter,
and so is not meaningful (Pruss, 2013). (1) Someone who made it the
primary goal in life to find out whether other people have an odd or
even number of eyelashes is insane.
Although many people attempt to find meaning through a
materialistic lifestyle, both the philosophers of virtue and the
positive psychologists agree that this meaning is not to be found in the
accumulation of wealth and possessions. On the view of Aristotle and
Aquinas, wealth is not the ultimate end constituting happiness because
we want wealth as a means to purchase other things. Positive
psychologist Emmons (2007) weighs in with contemporary research that
supports ancient wisdom.
A materialistic life style is one based
on accumulation and acquisition of
consumer goods beyond that which
is necessary to meet basic needs.
... research demonstrates that aspiring
toward greater wealth and more
material possessions undermines the
ability to be content. ... A number
of recent studies have found that
materialism can put people in an
emotional debt in that the greater
they place a value on materialistic
pursuits, the more at risk they are
for depression and other distressing
emotional states including envy and
hostility. (p. 88)
Accumulation of cash and material possessions does not satisfy the
desires of the human heart for meaning.
What makes something truly meaningful? Meaning, for Seligman,
involves participating in and making a contribution to something bigger
than oneself. Craig (2008) sees the question of ultimate meaning as tied
to the question of God's existence. A person can live as a great
hero, saving many people from pain, ignorance, and death. But ultimately
he will cease to exist and all those whom he helped will cease to exist.
What he did makes no lasting difference. On the other hand, a person
might be tyrannical, killing people, harming people, making the world
much worse off. But in the end, this person too will die and all those
who were made worse off end up in non-existence. Ultimately, all human
beings, indeed all life, on earth will be dead. Without God and
immorality, there is no lasting meaning possible.
In keeping with its empirical orientation, positive psychology is
neutral with respect to theistic belief. Laboratory tests cannot prove
or disprove God's existence. But, if Craig is right, the emphasis
in positive psychology on meaning objectively understood seems to
implicitly point to the question of God's existence as an essential
for ultimate meaning, and hence to human happiness.
Accomplishment/Achievement
Accomplishment comes into two varieties: non-comparative
accomplishment and comparative accomplishment. Non-comparative
accomplishment is about achieving some goal, the achievement of which is
independent of social comparison with others. Examples include, running
as fast as you can for three miles, learning to speak German, and
writing an excellent short story. Comparative accomplishments, by
contrast, are always embedded in some kind of social ranking with
others. These include winning a three-mile race, speaking German better
than anyone else in German class, and being awarded the short story
prize in the magazine competition.
Non-comparative accomplishment is a necessary part of flourishing,
imparting a sense of agency and control to the person who is able to
bring about the accomplishment. Comparative accomplishment can also
bring about a similar sense of agency and control.
However, positive psychology and the virtue tradition coincide in a
view that cautions about comparative accomplishment. Positive psychology
provides powerful evidence that the pursuit of happiness via upward
social comparison with others is likely to end in disappointment. Many
people believe that happiness will be found in being better than others
in some competition. If only they had more money, more popularity, more
fame, or more power than whomever they are comparing themselves with,
then they would be happy.
However, success, understood in terms of social comparison with
others, tends not last long. Once we achieve a particular goal, and
become a "winner" at any particular level, we quickly adjust
and come to believe new goals will bring deliver happiness. For example,
Lyumbomirsky (2013, p. 166) cites an experience provided by Ben-Shahar
(2007) who reported that his sense of accomplishment and happiness
lasted about three hours becoming his country's youngest national
squash tournament champion. Even those who succeed in being the very
best in terms of social comparison do not find lasting happiness in
their success, for they may end up in a negative comparison with
themselves. "[After Thriller the best-selling album of all time,
Michael Jackson declared that he would not be satisfied unless his next
album sold twice as many copies. In fact, it sold 70 percent fewer. Most
musicians would be thrilled with sales of thirty million, but for
Jackson the contrast with his earlier success was stinging"
(Lyumbomirsky, 2013, p. 120). The arrival fallacy describes the
phenomena that once people achieve their goals, the happiness that they
thought would arrive and last proves surprisingly fleeting (Ben-Shahar,
2007, p. 25). Like the horizon that always eludes our grasp, the
achievement of one goal reveals another yet goal.
Many scholars have investigated the relationship between money and
happiness. They found that increases in money do significantly increase
happiness, but only if one does not have sufficient material goods for
basic living. The person who does not eat three meals a day, or sleep in
a bed, or wear warm clothes is made significantly more happy by the
acquisition of these necessities. However, once basic needs are met,
researchers found no increase in reported happiness. Myers (1993) points
out that although the average American has become much more wealthy,
living in bigger houses, owning more cars and televisions, and having
greater disposable income than ever before, the average American is no
more happy than 50 years ago. After the initial shock wears off, lottery
winners report no greater levels of happiness than they had before
winning. Fortune 500 CEOs are no more happy, and often are less happy,
than average people. Almost everyone says that they need ten to fifteen
percent more money to be "comfortable." Once, after getting a
40% raise, I felt quite wealthy for the first few months, but then it
was business as usual--feeling like more money was needed. As people
become more wealthy, they adjust to the new level of affluence, and
believe they need even more money to be comfortable. For those whose
ears are deaf to the Gospel's warnings against greed, the findings
of positive psychology point to a natural moral theology.
Although Aristotle does not use the term social comparison, his
account of the magnanimity of the "great souled man" concerned
with great honors suggests, arguably, someone who is quite concerned
about his role in the pecking order and whose happiness consists, at
least in part, in being exalted above others. An excessive concern with
one's own greatness can be described as pride.
For Aquinas, by contrast, the virtue of humility--unknown to
Aristotle--plays an important role in happiness. Although Aquinas does
not view magnanimity and humility, both properly understood, as opposed
(Kaczor & Sherman 2009, pp. 403-407), Aquinas' greater emphasis
is on humility. Humility recognizes God as the author of whatever
excellence we have which tempers exaggerated self-exaltation with
gratitude and helps us recall the reality of our weakness and
imperfections. A humble person is a grounded person, in reality, rather
than excessively concerned with social comparison.
The concern expressed by positive psychologists about social
comparison finds an echo in the last of the Ten Commandments, "Thou
shall not covet thy neighbor's goods." I never really
understood this commandment until I studied positive psychology. I
thought, "What does it matter if I wish to have what my neighbor
has? Who does that harm?" It turns out that it harms the one
engaged in the social comparison. For to covet our neighbors goods, we
must first compare ourselves to our neighbor's material goods and
find we do not measure up.
The materialistic orientation of our culture insists that happiness
is just a purchase away. Emmons (2007) notes:
As any advertiser knows, material
strivings are fueled by upward social
comparisons that promote feelings of
deprivation and discontentment. By
focusing on blessings one is grateful
for, attention can be directed away
from making comparisons with others
who have more. A number of studies
have shown that upward social
comparisons lead to less positive
affect and more unpleasant feelings
such as depression and resentment.
When an individual is grateful for
how green her own lawn is, she is
not likely to be looking at the greener
grass on the other side of the fence.
I should note that the converse likely
holds as well: if a person's attention
is consistently devoted to things they
do not have, they will be unlikely to
focus on appreciating the blessings
they do have. (p. 42)
In this too, the positive psychologists and teachings of Jesus find
a resonance. Jesus urged his followers cast aside excessive concern
about their material well-being, "I tell you, do not worry about
your life and what you will eat, or about your body and what you will
wear" (Luke 12:22).
Does Science Alone Provide the Truth About Human Happiness?
Perhaps the biggest divergence between positive psychology and the
virtue philosophers is the limitation of positive psychology to what can
be empirically verified. Each aspect of Seligman's PERMA is capable
of measurement and quantification. By contrast, Aristotle and Thomas
include aspects that either are not, or even cannot, be empirically
verified. For Aristotle, the best kind of friendship is a friendship of
virtue, understood as an excellence with ethical dimensions. But
empirical studies can in principle only determine what is the case, not
what ought to be the case. Since what we ought to do cannot be
empirically determined, it cannot be empirically measured. Ethical
judgment can and should be empirically informed, but ethical judgment is
never simply a matter of scientifically proven facts. For Aquinas also,
his account of a fully flourishing human life includes elements that are
not subject to scientific verification. For example, the workings of
grace are a necessary part of his understanding of a flourishing human
life. But, of course, grace cannot be measured, weighed, or empirically
verified (even though perceptions of grace can be measured). Should such
non-empirical characteristics discredit the views of Aristotle and
Aquinas?
It is said that a sign hung in Albert Einstein's office at
Princeton University which read, "Not everything that can be
counted counts; not everything that counts can be counted."
Although some people wish to limit authentic insight to what can be
verified empirically, this view is self-defeating. We cannot empirically
verify the claim that we should only believe what can be empirically
verified. Science does not establish that we should only accept science.
The philosophy that whatever cannot be established through laboratory
testing is self-defeating because it is a philosophy that itself cannot
be established through laboratory testing. Someone may find good grounds
for rejecting Aristotle's or Thomas's account, but the
non-empirical nature of their accounts is not such a ground.
There is, of course, no opposition between making use of modern
medicine and practicing the Christian faith. Likewise, although there
are elements of tension, I've found that positive psychology, like
modern medicine, can be used to greatly enhance human well being,
without jeopardizing faith. Yet, as Vitz (1995) points out, some people
would take a step further and conceive of psychology as a replacement
for faith. If positive psychology is so wonderful, should I simply give
up Christianity and embrace positive psychology as its modern
replacement?
Psychology, including positive psychology, cannot replace Christian
belief and practice for several reasons. First, psychology cannot
adequately satisfy the human desire for truth. Positive psychology makes
use of the empirical method which cannot--in principle--answer questions
of ethics, the meaning of life, and ultimate truth. The human drive to
ask and answer the ultimate questions is a sign of the human disposition
for a relationship with the ultimate Truth, God. Something more than
positive psychology is needed to satisfy this desire to know that which
goes beyond the empirically verifiable. Positive psychology will never
be able to ultimately satisfy the distinctly spiritual cravings of human
beings. Due to its empirical orientation, positive psychology cannot
supplant the role of religion, and yet can be a support of Christian
belief about how to live and aid in Christian practice.
Second, while psychological practices can help relieve a distorted
guilt, it cannot relieve reasonable guilt. The objective guilt of sin
requires not just a calming of subjective feelings of guilt but a
removal of the objective offense. No psychologist can forgive sins; this
requires the work of Jesus Christ. This is essential if our happiness is
to be found in love of God. Sin creates disunion between the sinner and
God. If God is the source of happiness, so long as this disunion
remains, happiness is impeded.
Finally, our happiness is primarily to be found in love--love of
God and love of neighbor. But love requires knowledge; and without deep
knowledge, our love will be shallow. We need God's revelation to
enhance our love, for a purely human approach to understanding God will
lead to partial and fragmentary understandings at best. Although
powerful as an aid to living faith, positive psychology is not a
substitute for faith.
Practical Implications
The division of flourishing into positive emotion, engagement,
relationship, meaning, and achievement can facilitate being more precise
about what could be augmented in a person's life. Spiritual
directors and therapists can help those they are directing or counseling
to consider how each element might be improved. The vision of happiness
provided by Seligman also provides some material for Christian
apologetics and for pastors. It is not just a matter of revelation but
also something that is empirical proven in positive psychology that
financial well-being (once we are past the poverty level) does not
necessarily bring about happiness. Such insights show the reasonability
of Christian beliefs about money (as merely a means and not the ultimate
end of life). These insights also can help pastors to motivate others to
place their highest concern on love of God and neighbor rather than on
the acquisition of material goods.
Christopher Kaczor
Princeton University/Loyola Marymount University
Notes
(1) On the difference between something mattering and something not
mattering, see Pruss (2013), chapter 4.
References
Aquinas, T. (1975). Summa contra Gentiles, book three. Notre Dame,
IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
Aquinas, T. (2012). Summa theologiae. Lander, WY: The Aquinas
Institute.
Aristotle. (1984). The complete works of Aristotle. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Baumeister, R. F., & Leary, M. R. (1995). The need to belong:
Desire for interpersonal attachments as a fundamental human motivation.
Psychological Bulletin, 117,497-529.
Ben-Shahar, T. (2007). Happier: Learn the secrets of daily joy and
lasting fulfillment. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill.
Craig, W. L. (2008) Reasonable Faith: Christian Truth and
Apologetics. Wheaton, IL: Crossway Books.
Csikszentmihalyi, M. (1991). Flow: The psychology of optimal
experience. New York, NY: HarperPerennial.
Diener, E., & Biswas-Diener, R. (2008). Happiness: Unlocking
the mysteries of psychological wealth. New York, NY: Wiley-Blackwell.
Emmons, R. (2007). Thanks! How the new science of gratitude can
make you happier. Boston & New York, NY: Houghton Mifflin Company.
Fredrickson, B. (2013). Love 2.0: How our supreme emotion affects
everything we feel, think, do, and become. New York, NY: Hudson Street
Press.
Hatfield, E., Cacioppo, J. T., & Rapson, R. L. (1993).
Emotional contagion. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 2,
96-99.
Ignatius. (1964). The spiritual exercises of Saint Ignatius. New
York, NY: Image.
Kaczor, C., & Sherman, T. (2009). Thomas Aquinas on the
cardinal virtues. Naples, FL: Saptientia Press of Ave Maria University.
Lyumbomirsky, S. (2013). The myths about happiness: What should
make you happy but doesn't, what shouldn't make you happy but
does. New York, NY: Penguin Press HC.
McGonigal, K. (2012). The willpower instinct: How self-control
works, why it matters, and what you can do to get more of it. New York,
NY: Penguin.
Myers, D. G. (1993) The pursuit of happiness: discovering the
pathway to fulfillment, well-being, and enduring personal joy. New York,
NY: Avon Books.
Pruss, A. (2013). One body: An essay in Christian sexual ethics.
Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
Rubin, G. (2009). The happiness project: Or, why I spent a year
trying to sing in the morning, clean my closets, fight right, read
Aristotle, and generally have more fun. New York, NY: HarperCollins.
Seligman, M. (2011). Flourish: A visionary new understanding of
happiness and well-being. New York, NY: Simon and Schuster.
Stanley, S. M., Blumberg, S. L., & Markman, H. J. (2001).
Fighting for your marriage: Positive steps for preventing divorce and
preserving a lasting love. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Tolstoy, L. (2004). Anna Karennina. New York, NY: Penguin Classics.
Vitz, P. (1995) Psychology as religion: The cult of self-worship
(2nd ed.). Grand Rapids, MI: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Co.
Zagano, P., & Gillespie, C. K. (2006). Ignatian spirituality
and positive psychology. The Way, 45(4), 41-58.
Correspondence concerning this article should be sent to
Christopher Kaczor, Department of Philosophy, Loyola Marymount
University, 1 LMU Drive, Los Angeles, CA 90045;
[email protected]
Christopher Kaczor (Ph.D. in medieval philosophy, University of
Notre Dame) is William E. Simon Visiting Fellow in Religion and Public
Life at the James Madison Program at Princeton University and Professor
of Philosophy at Loyola Marymount University. He has authored several
books including, The Gospel of Happiness: Rediscover Your Faith Through
Spiritual Practice and Positive Psychology. Dr. Kaczor's interests
include bioethics, positive psychology, Thomas Aquinas, and natural law
ethics.