首页    期刊浏览 2024年12月12日 星期四
登录注册

文章基本信息

  • 标题:Lettres Latines.
  • 作者:Jones, Matthew L.
  • 期刊名称:Renaissance Quarterly
  • 印刷版ISSN:0034-4338
  • 电子版ISSN:1935-0236
  • 出版年度:2006
  • 期号:March
  • 语种:English
  • 出版社:The Renaissance Society of America
  • 关键词:Books

Lettres Latines.


Jones, Matthew L.


Pierre Gassendi. Lettres Latines.

Ed. and trans. Sylvie Taussig. 2 Vols. Monotheismes et Philosophie 5. Turnhout: Brepols Publishers, 2004. xxxiv + 622 pp.; x + 609 pp. [euro]175. ISBN: 2-503-51353-0.

Sylvie Taussig. Pierre Gassendi (1592-1655), introduction a la vie savante. Monotheismes et Philosophie 6. Turnhout: Brepols Publishers, 2003. 456 pp. illus. bibl. [euro]60. ISBN: 2-503-52182-7.

In the volumes under review, Sylvie Taussig has translated, annotated, and written an introduction to the Latin letters of Pierre Gassendi. These letters appear in the final volume of his Opera omnia; the volume also includes letters written to Gassendi, which Taussig does not translate. The Opera excludes Gassendi's personal correspondence with his closer friends, much of it originally in French and long available in serviceable editions. The Latin letters were for a readership far wider than their addressees; even the Latin letters written to those close to him were often public statements on issues and debates of the day.

Gassendi's Latin letters fall into three major groups. The first group demonstrates the collective labor of a community of scholars, and documents Gassendi's advance from mere aspirant to an important node in the republic of letters. The letters show Gassendi striving to persuade others to conform to this community's norms and to heal the rifts within it. We see Gassendi getting help with Greek, collecting and distributing astronomical observations, and working to reconcile hostile parties, such as Galileo and the Jesuit Christoph Scheiner, or Descartes and the artisan Ferrier. He writes a poem upon the death of Wilhelm Schickard, a model for combining philology and astronomical interests; he tells Galileo to be philosophical about his blindness in one eye; he considers lexical and metrological tools; he discusses vegetarianism with van Helmont--while stressing the purposeful nature of living things. These letters make up the practical work that accompanied his philosophical views: not individual intellection, but collective empirical activity alone could attain those truths about nature and history available to human beings. Historians of science and scholarship will find these early letters crucial for understanding the relationship between the late Renaissance and mid-seventeenth-century learning, in doctrines, empirical methods, and social organization.

An explicit ethical drive dominates the second group of letters, almost all written to Gassendi's protector Prince Louis-Emmanuel de Valois, the governor of Provence from 1637; these letters constitute what Taussig calls a "course of philosophy," designed to form the prince into a more philosophical person and leader. The letters detail Gassendi's project of restoring and correcting Epicurus by refuting the long tradition of denouncing him, by placing him in the history of philosophy, and by explaining his doctrines and standards for judging. Rebutting at length the oft-repeated claim that Epicurus repudiated all the liberal arts, Gassendi claims that Epicurus sought rather to orient those arts toward their proper propaedeutic role in aiding us in living better--a theme central to much early modern consideration of the sciences. This course, Taussig claims, "has as much importance for studying his Epicureanism as the apparently more accomplished treatises" (Intro., 210). She's right. These letters should be central for understanding debates about the purposes and methods of early modern philosophy, and its relation to its predecessors.

With the third group of letters, roughly demarcated by the end of his course for Valois, we return to a less-focused correspondence like that of the younger Gassendi. Now an authority well known for his Life of Peiresc and his observations of Mercury, Gassendi in his letters of the 1640s and 1650s includes discussions of the vacuum and circulation of the blood, and numerous criticisms of Descartes. His collective astronomical and scientific labor continues: he corresponds with Hevelius on instrumentation and observation, encourages the Jesuit Honore Fabry to publish, and discusses Hobbes with Sorbiere. His letters to Valois are full of news of political events, religious conflict, and war.

Taussig's often-eloquent translation of the letters appears in one volume; her seven thousand notes, numbered consecutively, appear in a second volume in miniscule print. Two explicit goals frame her notes: first, clarifying all references and situations mentioned or hinted at in the correspondence, insofar as possible; second, grasping why Gassendi and his editors might have chosen to include each letter. The notes exhaustively document classical turns of phrase and quotations, scientific and philosophical terms and disputes, holidays, political and religious events, geographical locations, and biographies; a smaller number present substantial philosophical discussion of the issues involved in the letters.

Taussig's will to totality accounts both for the greatness and weakness of her notes: they are great in that they illuminate so many facets of every letter, weak in that the refusal to prioritize often leaves her key findings and theses undistinguished amid the plethora of profound erudition. Insightful philosophical points are too often buried; so too are many central bits of philological commentary, such as importance of the Greek salutations used by Gassendi and Louis de Valois. I wished for some form of mark to distinguish the most important notes. Many notes could be edited down: for example, it probably suffices in this context to explain what the feast of the Assumption is, not that it rested on disputed foundations.

Superb in cross-referencing Gassendi's other works, the notes rarely refer to the major discussions in the secondary literature. Taussig comments at length, for example, on Gassendi's important letter to Mersenne concerning the relationship between mathematical and physical points, without citing the crucial chapter considering the letter in Lynn S. Joy's Gassendi the Atomist (1987). Vast numbers of her notes offer no citations whatsoever: it is interesting to learn, for example, about the ratios of populations of different states active in the military during the Thirty Years' War, but strange to offer no source for the information (Letters n. 4492).

No index accompanies the translation and the 7491 notes: while a table of letters organized by correspondent, taken from the original Latin, provides a general survey of topics, it hardly suffices. These letters deserve no less than a series of indices by name, subject, and work cited, as in the Akademie Edition of the works of Leibniz.

The introduction to the letters comes in a third volume. After a brief biographical sketch, cued to the letters, Taussig offers a series of topical chapters on correspondence, on the shared humanistic cultural heritage, on the learning of the time, on the Epicurean project, on Gassendi's involvement with the nobility, and on his relations of the political and religious events of the day. Particularly instructive are Taussig's discussion of the practice of correspondence, its codes, and its vicissitudes; her consideration of Gassendi's defense of the role of the sciences helpful for becoming a sage; and her nuanced account of Gassendi's care in negotiating his relationship with Louis de Valois, and in providing him philosophical instruction. Taussig underscores the importance of ideals and practices of friendship for understanding the doctrines and practice of the letters; Gassendi viewed the practical and philosophical problems of organizing collective scholarly and scientific effort through the analytical frame of friendship. Taussig leads us to see the dialogical form of the letters, the open give-and-take of discussion and empirical observation, as a reflection of Gassendi's philosophical and scientific methods themselves, and to see them as essential aspects of the learned life of the philosophical sage. I would have greatly appreciated a chapter on the reception history of these letters: they offer, for example, potent models of collective labor and epistemic humility--but how widely were they read? And by whom? How widely were they cited?

Despite its extensive bibliography, the text of the introduction fails, with a few exceptions, to refer, even in its footnotes, to the major secondary works on Gassendi and his contexts: the introduction's notes are comprised almost entirely of references to the letters themselves. In neither her introduction nor her notes does Taussig point to the major secondary works discussing the questions at issue in the letters, such as those of Joy, Bloch, Osler, Darmon, and Lennon (just to list some of the most important of the works duly cited in the bibliography). As well as a chronology, the introduction includes a fine series of mini-biographies of the people addressed or invoked in the letters; these biographies, again, largely lack suitable secondary documentation.

To be sure, indices and references would take up valuable page space; a hundred pages could easily be recovered simply by reducing the frequency and length of quotation of the more easily available sources in the notes. The publisher should make at least a name index available to readers and libraries purchasing the rather overpriced volumes, so that Taussig's copious labor will prove more fruitful, and her insights and erudition more accessible.

Although their insufficient editorial and citational apparatus makes these volumes less easy to use than they should be, they are essential reading for Gassendi scholars and for anyone interested in the republic of letters in the seventeenth century; historians of science, scholarship, and literature should feast on them for years to come.

MATTHEW L. JONES

Columbia University

联系我们|关于我们|网站声明
国家哲学社会科学文献中心版权所有